Bowie Book.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bowie Book.Pdf COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW VOLUME 105 MARCH 2019 NUMBER 1 ARTICLES THE GOVERNMENT-COULD-NOT-WORK DOCTRINE Nikolas Bowie* The Supreme Court has recently declared that it is presumptively un- constitutional for the government to compel individuals to do or pay for things to which they have religious or political objections. Last Term, the Court applied this declaration to uphold the First Amendment ar- guments made by public-sector employees, and it appears poised to vin- dicate similar claims by religious objectors to antidiscrimination laws in the future. But this declaration is wrong. Indeed, throughout Ameri- can history—from the Articles of Confederation through Lochner v. New York and Employment Division v. Smith, the Court itself has re- peatedly rejected the notion that compulsory laws, in and of themselves, are presumptively unconstitutional. This Article offers a novel examination of the history of challenges to compulsory laws inside and outside the context of the First Amendment. For centuries, the Supreme Court has faced hundreds of challenges to objectionable taxes, objectionable drafts, objectionable regulations, and objectionable funding conditions. With few exceptions, the Court has responded that the “government could not work” if it lacked the power to compel people to do things to which they objected. Although the Constitution prescribes many specific limits on the powers of the federal and state governments, the Constitution’s very purpose was to * Assistant Professor, Harvard Law School. For advice, criticism, feedback, and inspiration, I thank Christine Desan, Richard Fallon, Kenneth Mack, Leah Litman, Joshua Matz, Lucas Issacharoff, Martha Minow, Samuel Moyn, Matthew Shahabian, Joe Singer, and Laurence Tribe. 1 COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION 2 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1 create a union that had the power to compel political minorities to ac- cept the will of a political majority. Such a union would be incompatible with a governing document that prohibited officials from compelling people to take any action to which they religiously or politically ob- jected—even when those objections were sincerely held. Borrowing the Supreme Court’s own language, I call the Court’s typi- cal response the “government-could-not-work” doctrine, and conclude that objectionable compulsion, in and of itself, should not trigger the strict scrutiny of Abood v. Detroit Board of Education. Rather, compul- sory laws should be treated the same as any other law, and analyzed for whether they are arbitrary, are discriminatory, or otherwise violate specific constitutional limits. I. HISTORY ...................................................................................... 11 A. 1787–1943 .......................................................................... 11 1. The Origins of the Government-Could-Not-Work Doctrine ...................................................................... 11 2. The First Amendment Non-Exception ........................... 14 3. The Public–Private Exception ...................................... 16 B. 1943–1982 .......................................................................... 19 1. West Virginia v. Barnette and Its Aftermath ................ 19 2. The Court Reins in Barnette ......................................... 23 3. The Continuous Public-Private Exception ................... 25 C. 1982–Present ...................................................................... 28 1. The Government-Could-Not-Work Doctrine Returns ... 28 2. The Persistent Public–Private Exception ..................... 33 II. THE GOVERNMENT-COULD-NOT-WORK DOCTRINE ................... 35 III. APPLICATIONS ........................................................................... 42 A. Controversial Recipients .................................................... 42 B. Agency-Fee Arrangements ................................................. 45 C. Municipal Speech ............................................................... 53 D. Antidiscrimination Laws .................................................... 58 IV. CONCLUSION ............................................................................. 60 For over two thousand years, conscientious people from Plato to Gan- dhi have grappled with the dilemma of how to respond when a govern- ment orders you to do something you disagree with—say, pay a tax that COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION 2019] The Government-Could-Not-Work Doctrine 3 will fund a war.1 Perhaps the most famous answer comes from the book of Matthew, when Jesus of Nazareth declared, “Render . unto Caesar the things which are Caesar’s; and unto God the things that are God’s.”2 One way to interpret this declaration contends that you should always comply with fairly imposed civil obligations—at least until you can per- suade others to accommodate your views.3 A second argues that if con- science so dictates, you should disobey the government and accept what- ever punishment it doles in return.4 Recently, a group of constitutional lawyers have offered a third option: Sue the government. Adopting a libertarian interpretation of the First Amendment’s protection of free speech and religious exercise, these law- yers argue that it is presumptively unconstitutional for the government ever to put one’s moral obligations in conflict with one’s civil obligations. 1 Compare, e.g., Plato, Crito 54a–54d, in The Collected Dialogues of Plato 93 (Hugh Teden- nick trans., 1987), with Plato, Apology 28b–38b, in The Collected Dialogues of Plato, supra, at 51–68. See also Alexander Meiklejohn, Political Freedom 21–24 (1960) (articulating the distinction between Socrates’s disobedience to the law in Apology and Socrates’s obedience to the law in Crito). 2 Matthew 22:21 (King James). 3 See, e.g., Romans 13:1–2 (King James) (“Let every soul be subject unto the higher powers. For there is no power but of God: the powers that be are ordained of God. Whosoever therefore resisteth the power, resisteth the ordinance of God . .”); Thomas Aquinas, On Law, Moral- ity, and Politics 64 (Richard J. Regan trans., 2d ed. 2002) (“[Just laws] have obligatory force in the court of conscience from the eternal law, from which they are derived.”); Immanuel Kant, What is Enlightenment?, in Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals 85, 87 (Lewis White Beck trans., 1959) (1785) (“Many affairs which are conducted in the interest of the community require a certain mechanism through which some members of the community must passively conduct themselves with an artificial unanimity . Here argument is certainly not allowed—one must obey.”). 4 See, e.g., 1 Peter 2:19 (King James) (“For this is thankworthy, if a man for conscience toward God endure grief, suffering wrongfully.”); Augustine, On the Free Choice of the Will, On Grace and Free Choice, and Other Writings 10 (Peter King ed. & trans., 2010) (“[A] law that is not just does not seem to me to be a law.”); Mohandas K. Gandhi, “Render Unto Cae- sar,” in 48 The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi 483 (1989) (“Jesus’s whole preaching and practice point unmistakably to non-co-operation, which necessarily includes nonpayment of taxes. Jesus never recognized man’s authority as against God’s.”); Martin Luther King, Jr., Letter from Birmingham Jail, in Why We Can’t Wait 77, 86 (1964) (“I submit that an individ- ual who breaks a law that conscience tells him is unjust, and who willingly accepts the penalty of imprisonment in order to arouse the conscience of the community over its injustice, is in reality expressing the highest respect for law.”); John Locke, A Letter Concerning Toleration 43 (1689) (“[A] private Person is to abstain from the Action that he judges unlawful, and he is to undergo the Punishment, which it is not unlawful for him to bear.”); Henry David Tho- reau, Resistance to Civil Government (Civil Disobedience), in Political Writings 1, 10 (Nancy L. Rosenblum ed., 1996) (1849) (“Under a true government which imprisons any unjustly, the true place for a just man is . a prison.”). COPYRIGHT © 2019 VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW ASSOCIATION 4 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 105:1 As evidence, they draw on cases such as West Virginia v. Barnette, in which the Supreme Court struck down a regulation that compelled object- ing school children to recite the pledge of allegiance.5 In the past few years these lawyers have asked the Court to extend Barnette’s logic to petitioners who object to birth control, labor unions, vaccinations, same- sex marriage, and all kinds of politically charged topics.6 The Supreme Court has been sympathetic to these lawyers, in one case declaring that the First Amendment generally “prevent[s] the government from compelling individuals to express certain views” or “pay subsidies for speech to which they object.”7 The Court has even acted on this dec- laration to invalidate laws that tax public-sector employees and donate the revenue to labor unions.8 But this declaration is wrong. Treating compul- sory laws as presumptively invalid not only contradicts historical practice, it’s also at odds with the Court’s precedent in nearly every other consti- tutional context.9 The First Amendment, along with the rest of the Constitution, was adopted to create a functional government out of the embers of a failing 5 W. Va. State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624, 642 (1943). 6 See, e.g., Janus v. Am. Fed’n, 585 U.S. ___ (2018); Masterpiece Cakeshop, Ltd., v. Colo. Civil Rights Comm’n, 584 U.S. ___ (2018); Friedrichs
Recommended publications
  • Building a Better Mousetrap: Patenting Biotechnology in The
    DRUZIN-FINAL FINAL (DO NOT DELETE) 10/24/2014 3:19 PM RESTRAINING THE HAND OF LAW: A CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK TO SHRINK THE SIZE OF LAW Bryan Druzin∗ ABSTRACT ............................................................................................... 59 I. INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................ 60 II. THE CASE FOR MINIMALISM ................................................................... 64 A. Assumptions and Starting Points ..................................................... 64 B. The Benefits of Minimalism ............................................................. 66 C. The Minimalist Approach to Economic Regulation ......................... 70 D. The Liability of Ideology—Both Left and Right ............................... 72 III. ARTICULATING A FRAMEWORK FOR LEGISLATIVE MINIMALISM ........... 73 A. Non-Interference .............................................................................. 75 B. Formalizing ...................................................................................... 77 C. Fine-Tuning ..................................................................................... 83 D. Dismantling ...................................................................................... 84 E. Concocting ....................................................................................... 85 IV. CLARIFYING THE FRAMEWORK ............................................................... 86 A. A Tabulated Comparison of the Strategies .....................................
    [Show full text]
  • Liberty of Contract
    YALE LAW JOURNAL LIBERTY OF CONTRACT "The right of a person to sell his labor," says Mr. Justice Harlan, "upon such terms as he deems proper, is in its essence, the same as the right of the purchaser of labor to prescribe the conditions upon which he will accept such labor from the person offering to sell it. So the right of the employee to quit the service of the employer, for whatever reason, is the same as the right of the employer, for whatever reason, to dispense with the ser- vices of such employee ........ In all such particulars the employer and the employee have equality of right, and any legis- lation that disturbs that equality is an arbitrary interference with the liberty of contract, which no government can legally justify in a free land." ' With this positive declaration of a lawyer, the culmination of a line of decisions now nearly twenty- five years old, a statement which a recent writer on the science of jurisprudence has deemed so fundamental as to deserve quotation and exposition at an unusual length, as compared with his treat- ment of other points, 2 let us compare the equally positive state- ment of a sociologist: "Much of the discussion about 'equal rights' is utterly hollow. All the ado made over the system of contract is surcharged with fallacy." ' To everyone acquainted at first hand with actual industrial conditions the latter statement goes without saying. Why, then do courts persist in the fallacy? Why do so many of them force upon legislation an academic theory of equality in the face of practical conditions of inequality? Why do we find a great and learned court in 19o8 taking the long step into the past of deal- ing with the relation between employer and employee in railway transportation, as if the parties were individuals-as if they were farmers haggling over the sale of a horse ? 4 Why is the legal conception of the relation of employer and employee so at variance with the common knowledge of mankind? The late Presi- ' Adair v.
    [Show full text]
  • Petitioner, V
    No. 19-___ IN THE Supreme Court of the United States _________ MARK JANUS, Petitioner, v. AMERICAN FEDERATION OF STATE, COUNTY, AND MUNICIPAL EMPLOYEES, COUNCIL 31, ET AL., Respondents. _________ On Petition for Writ of Certiorari to the United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit _________ PETITION FOR WRIT OF CERTIORARI _________ JEFFREY M. SCHWAB WILLIAM L. MESSENGER LIBERTY JUSTICE CENTER Counsel of Record 190 South LaSalle Street AARON B. SOLEM Suite 1500 c/o NATIONAL RIGHT TO Chicago, IL 60603 WORK LEGAL DEFENSE (312) 263-7668 FOUNDATION, INC. 8001 Braddock Road Suite 600 Springfield, VA 22160 (703) 321-8510 [email protected] Counsel for Petitioner QUESTION PRESENTED Is there a “good faith defense” to 42 U.S.C. § 1983 that shields a defendant from damages liability for de- priving citizens of their constitutional rights if the de- fendant acted under color of a law before it was held unconstitutional? (i) ii PARTIES TO THE PROCEEDINGS AND RULE 29.6 STATEMENT Petitioner, a Plaintiff-Appellant in the court below, is Mark Janus. Respondents, Defendants-Appellees in the court be- low, are American Federation of State, County, and Municipal Employees, Council 31; Simone McNeil, in her official capacity as the Acting Director of the Illi- nois Department of Central Management Services; and Illinois Attorney General Kwame Raoul. Other parties to the original proceedings below who are not Petitioners or Respondents include plaintiffs Illinois Governor Bruce Rauner, Brian Trygg, and Ma- rie Quigley, and defendant General Teamsters/Profes- sional & Technical Employees Local Union No. 916. Because no Petitioner is a corporation, a corporate disclosure statement is not required under Supreme Court Rule 29.6.
    [Show full text]
  • Contracts of Adhesion-Some Thoughts About Freedom of Contract
    CONTRACTS OF ADHESION-SOME THOUGHTS ABOUT FREEDOM OF CONTRACT FRIEDRICH KESSLER With the development of a free enterprise system based on an un- heard of division of labor, capitalistic society needed a highly elastic legal institution to safeguard the exchange of goods and services on the market. Common law lawyers, responding to this social need, trans- formed "contract" from the clumsy institution that it was in the six- teenth century into a tool of almost unlimited usefulness and pliability. Contract thus became the indispensable instrument of the enterpriser, enabling him to go about his affairs in a rational way. Rational be- havior within the context of our culture is only possible if agreements will be respected. It requires that reasonable expectations created by promises receive the protection of the law or else we will suffer the fate of Montesquieu's Troglodytes, who perished because they did not ful- fill their promises. This idea permeates our whole law of contracts, the doctrines dealing with their formation, performance, impossibility and damages. Under a free enterprise system rationality of the law of contracts has still another aspect.1 To keep pace with the constant widening of the market the legal system has to place at the disposal of the members of the community an ever increasing number of typical business trans- actions and regulate their consequences. But the law cannot possibly anticipate the content of an infinite number of atypical transactions into which members of the community may need to enter. Society, therefore, has to give the parties freedom of contract; to accommodate the business community the ceremony necessary to vouch for the delib- erate nature of a transaction has to be reduced to the absolute minimum.
    [Show full text]
  • Conscience and At-Will Employment
    Articles FIRING THOREAU: CONSCIENCE AND AT-WILL EMPLOYMENT James A. Sonne* It is a virtual axiom of the American workplace that, absent a contract or express law to the contrary, "an employer may terminate an employee at any time, for any reason or no reason at all."' Indeed, this presumption of "at-will" employment, which prevails in forty-nine states and the District of Columbia,' has been the law of the land for more than a century. Rooted in freedom of contract and private property principles, the rule is designed to yield efficiencies across a broad range of industries. Despite the prominence of at-will power, however, a growing (and potentially contradictory) trend in employment law, particularly in the health care field, is that employees should be protected in the exercise of their consciences-even if such exercise is contrary to their employers' wishes or the demands of their jobs.' This "conscience clause" movement is * Associate Professor, Ave Maria School of Law. B.A., Duke University; J.D., Harvard Law School. The author thanks George Remy and Jeffrey Melville for their research; Professors Richard Myers, Lynn Wardle, and Robert Vischer for their insights; Mary and Margaret Grace Sonne for their encouragement; and Ave Maria for its support. 1. Cynthia L. Estlund, Labor, Property, and Sovereignty After Lechmere, 46 STAN. L. REV. 305, 312 (1994). 2. See PETER 0. HUGHES, LABOR AND EMPLOYMENT LAW (MB) § 259.02 n.5 (2006) (observing "[e]mployment is presumed to be at will in ...every state" except Montana). For the District of Columbia, see Dantley v.
    [Show full text]
  • The First Amendment in Its Forgotten Years
    The First Amendment in Its Forgotten Years David M. Rabbant TABLE OF CONTENTS I. Free Speech Before the Courts 522 A. Supreme Court Cases 524 I. Avoiding First Amendment Issues 525 Resisting Incorporation into the Fourteenth Amendment 525 Excluding Publications from the Mails 526 Neglecting First Amendment Issues 529 Limiting the Meaning of Speech 531 2. Addressing First Amendment Issues 533 Justice Holmes and the Bad Tendency of Speech 533 Review of Statutes Penalizing Speech 536 The First Amendment as the Embodiment of English Common Law 539 3. Hints of Protection 540 4. Summary 542 B. Decisions Based on State Law 543 1. The Bad Tendency Doctrine 543 Speech by Radicals 543 Obscenity and Public Morals 548 2. Libel 550 3. Political Speech 551 4. Labor Injunctions 553 5. Speech in Public Places 555 C. The Judicial Tradition 557 t Counsel, American Association of University Professors. 514 Prewar Free Speech II. Legal Scholarship 559 A. The Social Interest in Free Speech 563 B. The Distinction Between Public and Private Speech 564 1. Schofield's Formulation of the Distinction 564 2. Other Scholarly Support for the Distinction 566 C. The Expanding Conception of Free Speech 568 D. The Rejection of Blackstone 570 E. The Limits of Protected Speech 572 1. The Direct Incitement Test 572 2. Pound's Balancing Test 575 3. Schroeder's Test of Actual Injury 576 4. The Benefits of LibertarianStandards 578 F. The Heritage of Prewar Scholarship 579 III. The Role of the Prewar Tradition in the Early Develop- ment of Modern First Amendment Doctrine 579 A.
    [Show full text]
  • Contract Law Through the Lens of Laissez-Faire Richard A
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Coase-Sandor Working Paper Series in Law and Coase-Sandor Institute for Law and Economics Economics 1997 Contracts Small and Contract Large: Contract Law Through the Lens of Laissez-Faire Richard A. Epstein Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/law_and_economics Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Richard A. Epstein, "Contracts Small and Contract Large: Contract Law Through the Lens of Laissez-Faire" (Coase-Sandor Institute for Law & Economics Working Paper No. 49, 1997). This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Coase-Sandor Institute for Law and Economics at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Coase-Sandor Working Paper Series in Law and Economics by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Contracts Small and Contract Large: Contract Law Through the Lens of Laissez-Faire by Richard A. Epstein* Introduction: A Fallen Theory? Laissez-faire capitalism, and its associated doctrine of freedom of contract, had many stalwart defenders during the nineteenth century. But it has received a rocky reception from many legal and philosophical commentators in the twentieth century. Freedom of contract often been pronounced "dead on arrival" as an organizing principle for complex contemporary societies. That principle has been said to be insensitive to differences in wealth, status, position and power that make the exercise of contractual choice a myth for the weak and dispossessed. Within the legal literature, it has been attacked as ignoring the large concentrations of wealth that distort market processes and that trample down the rights of consumers and workers.
    [Show full text]
  • An Empirical Appraisal of the Liberty of Contract
    An Empirical Appraisal of the Liberty of Contract “I got my first job when I was nine. Worked at a sheet metal factory. In two weeks, I was running the floor. Child labor laws are ruining this country.” -Ron Swanson Aaron Gordon Honors Thesis Department of Political Science Northwestern University Advisor: Prof. Daniel Galvin May 3, 2017 1 Abstract From approximately 1895-1937, the US Supreme Court interpreted the Constitution’s Due Process clauses to implicitly protect a “Liberty of Contract”—the right of individuals to make contracts without arbitrary government interference. The Court relied on this principle to invalidate a variety of regulatory measures, including maximum hours and minimum wage laws. The Court abandoned its enforcement of this doctrine in 1937, and today, the Liberty of Contract is widely condemned by legal thinkers as right-wing judicial activism. Supposedly, the Court’s protection of contractual freedom imposed a strict laissez-faire ideology on the country, interfered with Progressive reform legislation, and harmed public welfare—especially that of workers, consumers, and the poor. But such claims are often made without empirical support. My aim here is to evaluate, based on the surviving data and evidence, the practical impacts of the Liberty of Contract by examining a) the extent to which the doctrine interfered with policymakers’ efforts at economic regulation, and b) the economic and social effects of notable decisions in which the Court invalidated legislation on Liberty-of-Contract grounds. I conclude a) that the Court was quite deferential to legislators in Liberty-of-Contract cases, though its decisions to invoke the doctrine in invalidating laws were often arbitrary; and b) that the societal effects of such invalidations were often either neutral or positive.
    [Show full text]
  • Libertarian Corporatism Is Not an Oxymoron
    ROGERS.TOPRINTER (DO NOT DELETE) 6/14/2016 5:06 PM Libertarian Corporatism is Not an Oxymoron Brishen Rogers* Introduction Our constitutional democracy and our republican form of government, Joseph Fishkin and William Forbath argue in their recent work, depend on “a measure of economic and social democracy.”1 A truly democratic state, in their view, cannot just regulate powerful actors. It must also enable or positively encourage “robust intermediate organizations,” especially unions, to “offset the political power of concentrated wealth.”2 The history of the welfare state bears out this point. It is no accident that the era of mass unionization was also an era of quite progressive taxation, relatively tame executive compensation, and definancialization.3 Nor is it an accident that the decline of the welfare state, the decline of the labor movement, and the rise in income inequality have occurred in tandem in virtually every advanced economy.4 Mainstream policy debate around inequality, which focuses largely on ensuring progressive taxation, often misses this lesson.5 And yet empowering secondary associations can be very difficult in a constitutional culture that prizes individual liberty. It is not enough to just protect workers’ freedom to choose unionization while leaving other property relations intact,6 since economic elites will generally resist * Associate Professor, Temple University Beasley School of Law, [email protected]. The research leading up to this Essay was supported in part by the Roosevelt Institute’s Future of Work Initiative. For helpful comments and conversations, thanks to Willy Forbath, Joey Fishkin, and participants in the Texas Law Review Symposium on the Constitution and Economic Inequality.
    [Show full text]
  • Reynolds V. United States: the Ih Storical Construction of Constitutional Reality Donald L
    University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Constitutional Commentary 2004 Reynolds V. United States: The iH storical Construction of Constitutional Reality Donald L. Drakeman Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Drakeman, Donald L., "Reynolds V. United States: The iH storical Construction of Constitutional Reality" (2004). Constitutional Commentary. 276. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm/276 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Constitutional Commentary collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. REYNOLDS v. UNITED STATES: THE HISTORICAL CONSTRUCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL REALITY Donald L. Drakeman* In the Supreme Court's first case interpreting the Constitu­ tion's free exercise clause, Chief Justice Morrison Waite en­ dowed the next two centuries of religion clause jurisprudence with a generous legacy of constitutional history. In that 1879 case, Reynolds v. United States, the Chief Justice called upon the founding fathers to decide whether polygamous Mormons in the Territory of Utah were immunized by their faith from prosecu­ tion under a federal statute outlawing bigamy. 1 The Court's rul­ ing offered Mr. Reynolds, a minor Mormon official, no hope of sanctuary within the First Amendment. More important than this specific decision, however, was the historical approach to in­ terpreting the religion clauses adopted by the Chief Justice, which has had the effect of essentially writing Thomas Jefferson and James Madison directly into the First Amendment.
    [Show full text]
  • Property Law and the Mortgage Crisis: Libertarian Fantasies and Subprime Realities
    Property law and the mortgage crisis: Libertarian fantasies and subprime realities Joseph William Singer* Libertarian thinking is on the rise in the United States, but libertarians wrongly characterise regulation as a deprivation of both freedom and property rights and an inefficient interference with the free market. While libertarians are correct to praise the value of freedom, they fail to appreciate how regulations promote liberty, property and efficiency. The subprime crisis reminds us that neither property nor liberty nor the market can exist without law. Laws establish minimum standards for economic and social relationships appropri- ate to a free and democratic society that treats each person with equal concern and respect. Property rights are structured by law to protect consumers from unfair practices and to ensure that economic relationships comply with minimum standards of decency. A THOUGHT EXPERIMENT What would markets look like if there was no law? In his satirical novel Jennifer Government, Max Barry answers this question. He brings to life a libertarian dystopia where deregulation has run amok.1 In Barry’s world, governments have been privatised and the free market is almost entirely unfettered by laws or rules. Freely negotiated contracts and competition among market actors determine the kind and level of services rendered in the economy. Laws exist that prohibit force or fraud but people have to pay to have those laws enforced. If you want government services, you have to pay for them. Laws prohibiting murder, for example, are enforced only if the victim’s family or friends hire government employees to bring the murderer to justice.
    [Show full text]
  • First Amendment
    FIRST AMENDMENT RELIGION AND FREE EXPRESSION CONTENTS Page Religion ....................................................................................................................................... 1063 An Overview ....................................................................................................................... 1063 Scholarly Commentary ................................................................................................ 1064 Court Tests Applied to Legislation Affecting Religion ............................................. 1066 Government Neutrality in Religious Disputes ......................................................... 1070 Establishment of Religion .................................................................................................. 1072 Financial Assistance to Church-Related Institutions ............................................... 1073 Governmental Encouragement of Religion in Public Schools: Released Time ...... 1093 Governmental Encouragement of Religion in Public Schools: Prayers and Bible Reading ..................................................................................................................... 1094 Governmental Encouragement of Religion in Public Schools: Curriculum Restriction ................................................................................................................ 1098 Access of Religious Groups to Public Property ......................................................... 1098 Tax Exemptions of Religious Property .....................................................................
    [Show full text]