On Chinese Cultural Subjectivity Regarding Exemplary and Narrative Language: Based on Ricoeur’S Research of Narrative

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On Chinese Cultural Subjectivity Regarding Exemplary and Narrative Language: Based on Ricoeur’S Research of Narrative Cultural and Religious Studies, November 2019, Vol. 7, No. 11, 587-599 doi: 10.17265/2328-2177/2019.11.001 D DAVID PUBLISHING On Chinese Cultural Subjectivity Regarding Exemplary and Narrative Language: Based on Ricoeur’s Research of Narrative Wang Wen-Sheng National Chengchi University, Taipei City, Taiwan Exemplary language can, on the one hand, assist a listener to understand what a speaker intends to express, and, on the other hand, provoke a kind of practical force to the listener. Exemplary language is everywhere in our daily life, such as the bedtime stories told by a mother to her child, literary works, and judicial precedents. Many Western philosophers have expounded on this type of language. Exemplary language has become a topic for philosophical discussions. In Chinese classics, there are many expressions using exemplary language, but in different forms. Was there any philosophical reflection on these exemplary languages? The differences between the Chinese and the Western exemplary language initiate our discussion about the different subjectivity of exemplary language, or narrative subjectivity, for narrative will be discussed in this article as an extraordinary exemplary language. As a kind of exemplary language, narrative is analyzed by Ricoeur into two elements: time and meaning. Is his analysis also valid for Chinese narrative language? Can we discuss the difference of narrative subjectivity according to these two elements? The author is going to trace the origins of different subjectivity by analyzing distinct ways of creating characters/words which determinate different language forms in Chinese and the Western culture. The author finds that “linear time” (or objective time) still plays a significant role in the Western culture; by contrast, subjective time seems more dominant in Chinese culture. This also determines the narrative time for Chinese. As for the meaning, there are different purposes and ways of using narrative in Chinese culture and the Western culture, which are reflected, for example, in the different purposes of the Chinese and Western drama. This article aims to explore Chinese narrative subjectivity based on Ricoeur’s research of narrative. Keywords: exemplary language, narrative, Confucianism, Zhuangzi, narrative time, narrative meaning Introduction Exemplary language can, on the one hand, assist a listener to understand what a speaker intends to express, and, on the other hand, provoke a kind of practical force to the listener. Exemplary language is everywhere in our daily life, such as the bedtime stories told by a mother to her child, literary works, and judicial precedents. Many Western philosophers have expounded on this type of language. In other words, exemplary language has become a topic for philosophical discussions. Narrative is a kind of exemplary language. The constituents of narrative: time and meaning, can be those according to which we discuss the subjectivity of the exemplary language. In Chinese classics, there are many expressions using exemplary language. Do they also have the aforementioned effects? Has there been any philosophical reflection on these exemplary languages? When Wang Wen-Sheng, Prof. Dr. of Philosophy, Department of Philosophy, National Chengchi University, Taipei City, Taiwan. 588 BASED ON RICOEUR’S RESEARCH OF NARRATIVE Zhuangzi pointed out “words that are metaphorical (Yu yan, 寓言)”, “words from valued writers/figures (Chong yan, 重言)”, and “words like the water that daily issues from the cup (Zhi yan, 卮言)”, has he made a philosophical reflection on these exemplary languages? Besides, in the Analects and the Mencius, there is no lack of exemplary language. Do they have any philosophical discourse on it? How about other Chinese classics? The differences between the Chinese and the Western exemplary language initiate our discussion about the relation between language and culture. Is language a crucial element that constitutes a culture? Or vice versa? Language itself consists of pre-linguistic elements, such as the level of human existence (Dasein) or that of Being, which is embodied in language. In this regard, Heidegger’s critique of Cassirer could be true: In relation to Being, language is not terminus ad quem, but terminus a quo. Thus, we must investigate the pre-linguistic level, so that we can discuss the subjectivity of the exemplary languages in different cultures. This article is going to trace the origins of different subjectivity by analyzing distinct ways of creating characters/words in Chinese and the Western culture. A Chinese character is with one syllable and one meaning, and normally every word in a Western language is with multiple syllables and one meaning. There have been many discussions about this difference. The Western words with multiple syllables are composed in accordance with linear time, which determine the logic structure. Language has long served as a tool for the Western people to justify a claim or sentence (logon didonai) since the Ancient Greek. The logic structure needed when doing so may have something to do with the multi-syllable words used in Western languages. However, in the Western culture, there are exemplary language and poetic language as well, which can also express a reasonable meaning just as what logon didonai does. This type of language is not a mainstream way of expression in the West, but is very common in Chinese classics. This phenomenon is probably due to the type of Chinese characters, which have been created without the concept of linear time and logic structure. Nevertheless, is exemplary language carried by another form of time? Ricoeur intends to analyze the time in a narrative, which is a type of exemplary language. But it is to be noticed that the time in a narrative might differ because of varied types of characters/words and subjectivity. As for the other element constituting a narrative, “meaning”, it can also be discussed based on the purposes of using narrative and the theoretical backgrounds in different cultures. This article aims to explore Chinese narrative subjectivity based on Ricoeur’s research of narrative. Western Exemplary Language It is called doxa (opinion) in Ancient Greek philosophy whether one uses examples to strengthen the expression of an idea or relies completely on pure examples to communicate. Doxa was considered to be an opinion that could not become real knowledge. Such a criticism was made by Socrates when he pointed out that the Sophists only gave some examples instead of providing definitions when describing things. The doxa that is not qualified to be knowledge reveals the deficiency of exemplary language. However, if one offers some examples based on the knowledge that has been constructed, it can be helpful for the communication and practical usage of the knowledge. Rhetoric by Aristotle raised the concepts of paradéigma (a pattern, example, or sample) and enthúmema (rhetorical syllogism), which are different from the induction and syllogism based on logic. Rhetoric starts from a doxa, with no need to put forward the premise first. As a result, paradéigma takes advantage of a real case to propose an idea, which will always be demonstrated by the real case or doxa. However, this does not mean that BASED ON RICOEUR’S RESEARCH OF NARRATIVE 589 Rhetoric only provides opinions, or doxa. In fact, the theoretical discourse has been intuitively accepted through the words being said. The persuasiveness of Rhetoric is the perfect example proving that the exemplary language can help with communication and is definitely effective. Later, in Kritik der reinen Vernunf, Kant (1976) stated that the ability of judging is crucial for applying traditional logic to the object of experience. In this case, an example is needed as a practice to develop this ability. That is why Kant has said “examples are thus the go-cart of the judgment” (Kant, 1976, pp. 134-136). He also stated in Kritik der Urteilskraft that an empirical concept that is supposed to be real is based on intuition towards an example (Kant, 1974). A rational concept, which can be thought but not aesthetically intuited, can be real only with an allegorical symbol. The example provided by Kant is that when a monarchy is governed according to the laws established by its people; it resembles a mentalized body. By contrast, when a monarchy is governed by the absolute will of an individual, it resembles a mill. The symbols used by Kant (body and mill) serve as allegories of the “rule of law” and “autocracy” (Kant, 1974, pp. 255-257). Later, Arendt also cited Kant’s words: “examples are thus the go-cart of judgment”. Though the words Arendt used was not focusing on applying traditional logic to objects of experience. Instead, she intended to emphasize that aesthetic judgment as well as the moral and political judgments derived from it should be based on personal experiences and examples (Arendt, 2003). Such examples should be the people or things that are widely recognized and valued in the history to have qualities, such as beauty, goodness, and justice. To illustrate the concept, Arendt has said that an exemplary grand bridge enabled herself to recognize and appreciate a grand bridge in front of her. Other examples included Achilles as the example of brevity, Jesus as the example of goodness, and King Solomon as the example of a wise man (Arendt, 2003; Arendt, 2012). Arendt took the concept of allegory proposed by Kant as a kind of “metaphor”, which is different from an example. When we try to understand a phenomenal world, what we need is to just think based on common sense and use examples to demonstrate the concept. When an abstract concept is elaborated on with a specific example, it becomes easier to understand. However, in another situation when reason should go beyond the phenomenal world to lead us to the realm of speculation, metaphor can help us understand rational ideas, which do not correspond with intuition.
Recommended publications
  • Two Conceptions of Harmony in Ancient Western and Eastern Aesthetics: “Dialectic Harmony” and “Ambiguous Harmony”
    TWO CONCEPTIONS OF HARMONY IN ANCIENT WESTERN AND EASTERN AESTHETICS: “DIALECTIC HARMONY” AND “AMBIGUOUS HARMONY” Tak-lap Yeung∗ Abstract: In this paper, I argue that the different understandings of “harmony”, which are rooted in ancient Greek and Chinese thought, can be recapitulated in the name of “dialectic harmony” and “ambiguous harmony” regarding the representation of the beautiful. The different understandings of the concept of harmony lead to at least two kinds of aesthetic value as well as ideality – harmony in conciliation and harmony in diversity. Through an explication of the original meaning and relation between the concept of harmony and beauty, we can learn more about the cosmo-metaphysical origins in Western and Eastern aesthetics, with which we may gain insights for future aesthetics discourse. Introduction It is generally accepted that modern philosophy can trace itself back to two major origin points, ancient Greece in the West and China in the East. To understand the primary presuppositions of Western and Eastern philosophical aesthetics, we must go back to these origins and examine the core concepts which have had a great influence on later aesthetic representation. Inspecting the conception of “harmony”, a central concept of philosophical aesthetic thought for both the ancient Greek and Chinese world, may bring us valuable insight in aesthetic differences which persist today. In the following, I argue that the different understandings of “harmony”, which are rooted in ancient Greek and Chinese thought, can be recapitulated in the name of “dialectic harmony” and “ambiguous harmony” regarding the representation of the beautiful.1 The different understandings of the concept of harmony lead to, at least, two kinds of aesthetic value as well as ideality – harmony in conciliation and harmony in diversity.
    [Show full text]
  • Confucian Ren.Pmd
    CONFUCIAN “REN” AND CHRISTIAN LOVE Zhao Jianmin Beijing Institute for the Study of Christianity and Culture, Bejing, China Abstract “Ren” (benevolence, perfect virtue 仁) is the core of Confucian- ism, which says “The benevolent man loves others”. But what is the place of Ren in today’s society? The heart of Christianity is “love” __ “The one who loves others is a kind hearted man”. But is “love” being misused in society? In order to create a new spirit for modern society, people should explore their own tradition, which should be combined with the modern values first. Ren and love could work together to achieve this goal. Great civilizations can not only coexist but also work hand in hand to found a harmonious society for every one. º·¤Ñ´ÂèÍ礼 ¤ÓÇèÒ àËÃÔ¹ (àÁµµÒ¸ÃÃÁ ¤Ø³¸ÃÃÁ·ÕèÊÁºÙóì) ¹Ñé¹à»ç¹ËÑÇ㨢ͧ¤ÓÊÑè§Ê͹ ¢Í§ÅÑ·¸Ô¢§¨×êÍ·Õè¡ÅèÒÇÇèÒ ºØ¤¤Å·ÕèÁÕàÁµµÒ¸ÃÃÁÂèÍÁÃÑ¡¼ÙéÍ×è¹ ã¹·Ó¹Í§à´ÕÂǡѹ ¤ÇÒÁÃÑ¡ ¡çà»ç¹¤ÓÊ͹ËÅÑ¡¢Í§¤ÃÔʵÈÒÊ¹Ò ¤¹·ÕèÃÑ¡¼ÙéÍ×蹡ç¤×ͼÙéÁÕã¨àÁµµÒ à¾×èÍ·Õè¨ÐÊÃéҧʻÔÃÔµÊÓËÃѺÊѧ¤ÁÊÁÑÂãËÁè ¤¹àÃÒ¤Çäé¹ËÒ¨Ò¡¢¹º¸ÃÃÁà¹ÕÂÁ »ÃÐླմÑé§à´ÔÁ¢Í§µ¹àͧáÅйÓ仺ÙóҡÒáѺ¤Ø³¤èÒÊÁÑÂãËÁè àËÃÔ¹ áÅÐ ¤ÇÒÁÃÑ¡ ÊÒÁÒö仴éÇ¡ѹä´é 㹡Ò÷Õè¨ÐºÃÃÅض֧à»éÒËÁÒ¹Õé ºÃôÒÍÒøÃÃÁ ·ÕèÂÔè§ãË­è·Ñé§ËÅÒ¨֧äÁèà¾Õ§áµèÍÂÙèÃèÇÁâÅ¡¡Ñ¹à·èÒ¹Ñé¹ áµèÊÁ¤ÇÃÍÂèÒ§ÂÔ觷Õè¨ÐÃèÇÁÁ×͡ѹ ÊÃéÒ§Êѧ¤Á·ÕèÃÒºÃ×è¹ÊÁѤÃÊÁÒ¹ÊÓËÃѺ·Ø¡¤¹ “Ren”of Confucianism “Ren” and “Li” ( ) are the most important concepts in Confucian 210 Prajna~ __ V ihara, __ Volume 13, Number 1-2, January-December, 2012, 210-226 c 2000 by Assumption University Press thought, but Ren is more fundamental.
    [Show full text]
  • The Difference Between Confucian and Mencian Benevolence
    Journal of chinese humanities � (���6) ��7-�35 brill.com/joch The Difference Between Confucian and Mencian Benevolence Chen Ming (陳明) Professor of Philosophy, Capital Normal University, China [email protected] Translated by Eric Chiang Abstract Confucius and Mencius differ in many ways in describing and demonstrating benevo- lence. For Confucius, benevolence is a basic concept, with filial piety at its core, and entails socially and culturally regulated action; benevolence symbolizes self-perfection while sagacity symbolizes perfection of all things in the universe. In contrast, for Mencius, who transforms the Confucian universe of unending life into a philosophical universe and changes Confucian benevolence of familial respect into a universal and absolute moral sentiment or instinct, the universe is a basic concept. With the universe as the metaphysical core, Mencius changes benevolence from the fruit of intention to an object of thought, so it is no longer a relation between life and its projects but, rather, a relation between the mind and its cultivation. Confucius talks about benevolence through the individual and familial morality while Mencius does so through the uni- verse and human nature. Distinguishing Confucian and Mencian benevolence has the- oretical importance for Confucianism and practical importance in our lives. Keywords Benevolence – Confucius – Mencius – universe Regarding benevolence [ren 仁], Confucius and Mencius agree on three points. The first is its central importance. The word “benevolence” appears over a hun- dred times in the sixteen-thousand-word Analects [Lunyu 論語]. Originator of the doctrine of the Goodness of Human Nature, Mencius believes that benevo- lence reigns over other virtues, such as righteousness, courtesy, and wisdom, © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���6 | doi �0.��63/�35��34�-��340035Downloaded from Brill.com09/24/2021 10:30:12PM via free access 218 Chen and advocates for a benevolent government.
    [Show full text]
  • Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Xunzi, Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy 7, DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-7745-2 1 2 M
    Eric L. Hutton Editor Dao Companion to the Philosophy of Xunzi Editor Eric L. Hutton Department of Philosophy University of Utah Salt Lake City , UT, USA Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy ISBN 978-94-017-7743-8 ISBN 978-94-017-7745-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-7745-2 Library of Congress Control Number: 2016953488 © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2016 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifi cally the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfi lms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specifi c statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. Printed on acid-free paper This Springer imprint is published by Springer Nature The registered company is Springer Science+Business Media B.V.
    [Show full text]
  • 201604-Article4.Pdf
    Cambridge Journal of China Studies 47 From Verbal-static to Visual-dynamic: a Perspective Shift in Studying the Structure of Lun Yu Jiuquan HAN Hebei Agricultural University, China Email: [email protected] Abstract : Starting off from Makeham’s (2003) differentiation between historical meaning and scriptural meaning, Huang’s (2011) citation of coherence theories and Xu’s (2002; 2004a; 2004b) embodimental reading by rejecting Western logos, this paper takes a perspective shift from verbal-static to visual-dynamic to study the structure of The Analects of Confucius. While a sheer verbal-static reading of the Lun Yu is doomed to the extremities of either praising its structure into the heaven or damning it into the hell, and to the ambiguity to argue that its structure is neither very coherent nor quite chaotic, a new perspective from verbal-static to visual-dynamic might lead to a view that the compilers of the Lun Yu actually take a reverse thinking in compiling this historic classics by segmenting and quantifying. (Mcluhan,1962,1964) Confucius’ thoughts into bricks and tiles scattering here and there, which induces careful readers to reconstruct for themselves Confucius’ systemic TEMPLE composed of key notion windmills centering round how to be a Junzi by constant recitation, visualization and interpretation based on Gestalt cognition principles of spontaneous similarity, proximity and continuation. Key Words: Perspective shift, Reconstruction, Lun Yu, Segmentation, Quantification, Gestalt principles Volume 11, No. 4 48 1 INTRODUCTION Various studies of The Analects of Confucius (Lun Yu),to date, cover its politic-ethical meaning and significance, influences both at home and abroad, name origin, compiling, varieties of versions and structural analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Courage to Trust–Discussion of Moral Personality Built on the Confucian Ethics
    Ethics in Progress (ISSN 2084-9257). Vol. 6 (2015). No. 2. 11-25. doi: 10.14746/eip.2015.2.2 Courage to Trust–Discussion of Moral Personality Built on the Confucian Ethics Lei Kang (Guangdong University of Foreign Studies) Ying Qiu (Guangdong University of Foreign Studies) Tie Zheng (Guangdong University of Foreign Studies) Anne Rubienska (Guangdong University of Foreign Studies) 1. Introduction to Confucian Ethics of Xin Though the Analects is not the only literature to study Confucius’s thoughts, nor does it include all the theories by Confucius, the book indeed reveals Confucius’s main views on ethics. Through the joint efforts by Confucius and his students, a complete set of ethical values for purpose of building noble characters for personal development was established some 2500 years ago in China, which however were harnessed by rulers of different times to set patriarchal hierarchy as social order and means of governance. Resorting to ritual and music as main administrative guideline, Confucius believed that ethical guidance and virtue development should be the fundamental task for any nation, and people need to be educated to show their reverence for destiny and respect for ancestors, which was later regarded as a convention similar to religious attitude among Chinese people. Positioning the virtue of benevolence (Ren) as the core, Confucius proposed several cardinal virtues as essential ethic elements for one’s value system, including filial piety, loyalty, forgiveness, intelligence, bravery, courtesy, mediocrity, humility, generosity, trustworthiness, etc. (Wan 2009, 80). However, the way these virtues were expounded and discussed in the Analects led us to the question: Are these virtues only moral principles and attitudes, or do they imply specific conduct code or behavioural norms as well? According to Yang Bojun (1980, 257-258), the word “Xin” has been mentioned in the Analects for 38 times, more frequent than the words for “filial piety”, “justice” and “loyalty”; therefore, we could see that the moral value of Xin was thought highly by Confucius.
    [Show full text]
  • Explanatory Comments on Di Zi Gui (Students' Rules)
    1 Return to Home: http://www.tsoidug.org/ Return to Di Zi Gui: http://www.tsoidug.org/dizigui.php Explanatory Comments on Di Zi Gui (Students’ Rules) – 1 Verses 1 - 5: THE MAIN SUMMARY by Feng Xin-ming, Jan. 6, 2008; edited Jan. 11 & 15, 2008 For the Di Zi Gui text for verses 1 – 5, see p. 5 at http://www.tsoidug.org/dizigui/dizigui_web.pdf. This is the first page of the text of Di Zi Gui. (1)弟子規,聖人訓。 di` zi^ gui`, sheng` ren’ xun` The Rules for Students, are the Sage’s teachings. Explanatory Comments: “Sage” refers to Confucius. He is quoted to have said verses (2) to (4) in the book The Analects, Chapter “Xue Er” (學而篇), paragraph 6. In traditional Chinese, Confucius is often called “sheng ren,” which can be translated as “The Saintly Person,” showing the high regard reserved for him. (2)首孝弟,次謹信, shou^ xiao` ti`, ci` jin^ xin` First be xiao ti, i.e. good to parents (xiao), and respectful to elders (ti); next be reverent and trustworthy. Explanatory Comments: The most important thing and the first thing that students must achieve is to be xiao ti, i.e. to be good to one’s parents and respectful to one’s elders. The second most important thing and the next thing that students must achieve is to be jin xin, i.e. reverent and trustworthy. Please note how Confucius considers that being good to parents and respectful to elders (xiao ti) is the most important thing for a student to learn.
    [Show full text]
  • Benevolence-Oriented Filial Piety of Confucius
    International Academic Workshop on Social Science (IAW-SC 2013) Benevolence-Oriented Filial Piety of Confucius Xu Xiangqun Foreign Language Academy of Shandong Women’s University Jinan, Shandong, China [email protected] Abstract—On the basis of his predecessors, Confucius made a filial piety could no longer be based. Keen to see these, connotative innovation of filial piety. Proposing that filial Confucius wisely turned people's attention to benevolence. piety stemmed from the inner heart and was a manifestation By doing so, he found a more general and solid foundation of benevolence, he turned it from an external norm to an for the existence of filial piety. internal requirement of human heart. He transformed In proposing benevolence, Confucius built a foundation patriarchal filial piety of the Western Zhou Dynasty into for the Chinese traditional concept of filial piety by filial piety as family ethics. He expanded filial piety from echoing with human nature. In addition, filial piety was domain of family ethics to that of social ethics, and thus shifted from a relationship between different social levels enriched the meaning of filial piety, making it more socially in the Western Zhou Dynasty to benevolence of humanity significant. He thought sacrificial filial piety was able to play infused with intrinsic equality. Thus, filial piety was an educational role. transformed from a standard of aristocratic morality into a Keywords-Filial Piety ; Benevolence ; Confucius more universal morality for common people. In this way, the aristocratic color of filial piety in the Western Zhou Confucius approved of the LiYue culture and system of Dynasty gradually faded, and the scope of applicability the Western Zhou Dynasty, he remarked,"I prefer the was broadened.
    [Show full text]
  • The Difference Between Confucian and Mencian Benevolence
    Journal of chinese humanities � (���6) ��7-�35 brill.com/joch The Difference Between Confucian and Mencian Benevolence Chen Ming (陳明) Professor of Philosophy, Capital Normal University, China [email protected] Translated by Eric Chiang Abstract Confucius and Mencius differ in many ways in describing and demonstrating benevo- lence. For Confucius, benevolence is a basic concept, with filial piety at its core, and entails socially and culturally regulated action; benevolence symbolizes self-perfection while sagacity symbolizes perfection of all things in the universe. In contrast, for Mencius, who transforms the Confucian universe of unending life into a philosophical universe and changes Confucian benevolence of familial respect into a universal and absolute moral sentiment or instinct, the universe is a basic concept. With the universe as the metaphysical core, Mencius changes benevolence from the fruit of intention to an object of thought, so it is no longer a relation between life and its projects but, rather, a relation between the mind and its cultivation. Confucius talks about benevolence through the individual and familial morality while Mencius does so through the uni- verse and human nature. Distinguishing Confucian and Mencian benevolence has the- oretical importance for Confucianism and practical importance in our lives. Keywords Benevolence – Confucius – Mencius – universe Regarding benevolence [ren 仁], Confucius and Mencius agree on three points. The first is its central importance. The word “benevolence” appears over a hun- dred times in the sixteen-thousand-word Analects [Lunyu 論語]. Originator of the doctrine of the Goodness of Human Nature, Mencius believes that benevo- lence reigns over other virtues, such as righteousness, courtesy, and wisdom, © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���6 | doi �0.��63/�35��34�-��340035Downloaded from Brill.com09/28/2021 02:46:53PM via free access 218 Chen and advocates for a benevolent government.
    [Show full text]
  • The Making of the “Junzi”
    The Making of the “Junzi”: A Modern Perspective on the Pedagogy of Junzi in the Analects Thesis Presented in partial fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts and Science in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Kai Liang, B.A. Graduate Program in East Asian Languages and Literatures The Ohio State University 2015 Thesis Committee: Xiaobin Jian, Advisor Galal Walker Copyright by Kai Liang 2015 Abstract This thesis investigates the pedagogy of junzi in the Luny which is also known as Analects. The Analects has been passed down for about 2000 years, and its pedagogy sustained as a tradition in Chinese culture still needs to be further explored today. Currently, the field of Chinese as a Foreign Language (CFL) mainly borrows ideas, methodologies and strategies from the field of English as a Second Language (ESL). This thesis is looking into how the pedagogy of junzi in the Analects may inspire the CFL. Through analyzing the pedagogy of junzi in the Analects, this paper reveals the characteristics of its pedagogy and discusses its value to today’s Chinese language pedagogy in CFL. According to the research in this paper, the Analects uses shared experience, related concepts and contexts to illustrate and construct the meaning of junzi. Additionally, the Analects points to xue, a dynamic process which involves other mental and physical activities, as the approach to becoming a junzi. Through examining concepts and terms related to junzi and xue found in the Analects, and analyzing how they functioned in a constructive framework to define the meaning of junzi and xue, the features of the pedagogy were revealed and in turn discussed with respect to their value in CFL.
    [Show full text]
  • A Discussion of Xunzi's “Encouraging Learning” and Its Significance For
    Journal of chinese humanities � (���6) �7�-�89 brill.com/joch A Discussion of Xunzi’s “Encouraging Learning” and Its Significance for Confucianism Wang Bo (王博) Professor of Philosophy, Peking University, China [email protected] Translated by Colleen Howe Abstract Much of Xunzi’s philosophy can be characterized as a deepening of themes introduced by Confucius and, at the same time, a reaction against Mencius’ brand of Confucianism. For Xunzi, the idea of learning was a critical concept in achieving both of these goals. In Xunzi’s philosophy, learning is not simply the accumulation of knowledge but, rather, the process of coming to understand morality as a lifelong process of self-cultivation and self-improvement. Xunzi did not agree with Mencius that human nature was inher- ently good; instead he believed that human nature was bad, which is why individuals must actively learn to control their base desires. It is no coincidence that, in Xunzi’s project of self-cultivation based on learning to overcome one’s primal nature, chapter 1 of his anthology is “Encouraging Learning.” Reexamining the respective moral philoso- phies of Xunzi and Mencius from the perspective of learning and its role in moral culti- vation can provide a deeper understanding of their overall philosophy. Keywords Confucianism learning – Mencius – moral philosophy – Xunzi The Complete Library of the Four Treasures [Siku quanshu zongmu 四庫全書 總目] says: Xun Kuang’s works aimed at illuminating the teachings of the Duke of Zhou and Confucius. He honored ceremony and valued learning. He believed that the nature of man is evil and that goodness is learned © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���6 | doi �0.��63/�35��34�-��Downloaded340033 from Brill.com09/28/2021 01:07:37PM via free access A Discussion of Xunzi’s “Encouraging Learning” 173 through conscious effort.
    [Show full text]
  • Articles Discourse on “Humanity” in East Asian Confucianisms: Zhu Xi’S “Treatise on Humanity” and Its Reverberations in Tokugawa Japan*
    13 Articles Discourse on “Humanity” in East Asian Confucianisms: Zhu Xi’s “Treatise on Humanity” and its Reverberations in Tokugawa Japan* HUANG Chun-chieh** Translated and Abridged by Jan VRHOVSKI*** 1. Introduction In the intellectual history of East Asian Confucian discourse on humanity there have been two major peaks. The first is Confucius’ statement that “to be humane is to overcome one’s self and return to ritual propriety” (keji fuli weiren 克己復禮為仁), which established a basis for the relationship of insepa- rability between humanity (ren 仁) and ritual propriety (li 禮), as well as for the mutual tensions which exist between them. The very same statement also initiated the subsequent discourses and polemics on humanity that ensued among Confucian scholars of China, Japan and Korea. The second peak is represented by the monumental work “Treatise on Humanity” (Renshuo 仁説), written during the Southern Song dynasty by the renowned Confucian scholar Zhu Xi (朱熹, Huian 晦庵, 1130-1200). In this article, we will explore and discuss the Tokugawa (1603-1868) Japanese Confucians’ response to Zhu Xi’s “Treatise on Humanity.” In the 9th year of the reign of Emperor Xiaozong of the Northern Song (9th year of the Qiandao 乾道 era, 1173), Zhu Xi composed the text entitled “Treatise on Humanity,” in which he expounded on the most important core-value in the Confucian philosophical tradition, “humanity” * Translation from the Chinese original: Huang Chun-chieh, “Dongya rujia renxue zhi naehan: Zhuzi renshou jiqi zai dechuan riben de huixiang 東亞儒家「仁」學之 內涵:朱子〈仁說〉及其在德川日本的迴響” in his Dongya Rujia Renxue Shilun 東亞儒 家仁學史論(Taipei: National Taiwan University Press, 2017), chapter 6, pp.
    [Show full text]