Being Toward Birth: Natality and Nature in Merleau-Ponty

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Being Toward Birth: Natality and Nature in Merleau-Ponty Being Toward Birth: Natality and Nature in Merleau-Ponty Author: Kascha Snavely Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/1186 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2009 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy BEING TOWARD BIRTH: NATALITY AND NATURE IN MERLEAU-PONTY a dissertation By KASCHA SNAVELY submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2009 © copyright by KASCHA SNAVELY 2009 ii Abstract Being Toward Birth: Natality and Nature in Merleau-Ponty By Kascha Snavely This dissertation articulates Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy of nature in relation to the existential condition of “natality,” as defined by Arendt. Where Heidegger emphasizes mortality in his post-metaphysical ontology, these investigations follow Merleau-Ponty and Arendt who emphasize that humans are not only mortals but “natals,” beings who begin. The project has a twofold aim: 1. to present an exegesis of Merleau-Ponty’s oeuvre with a special emphasis on the Nature Courses and 2. to sketch out a natal ontology in its own right. This ontology depends on Merleau-Ponty’s methodological advancement beyond genetic phenomenology to generative and “poetic” phenomenology, a practice that incorporates historicity and expressivity. He offers a critique of science, particularly of evolutionary biology, that is shown to be relevant in a contemporary context. His natal ontology co-emerges with an ethical standpoint; he shows that a natural prereflective relation to a plurality of others, rather than only a single other, fundamentally conditions human existence. In a natal ontology, knowledge depends on being born with others, through a co-naissance of one’s worldly situation. iii I would like to express my sincere gratitude to my advisor Jeffery Bloechl for his patience and guidance in this project. My thanks also goes to Richard Kearney who has offered invaluable advice, and to my outside reader, Galen Johnson. I could not have completed this project without the help of my mother Roxanne Semon and the support of my husband, John Snavely. iv Table of Contents Introduction: Of Being Numerous Chapter 1 Of Being Born: Connaissance, Comportement and the Structure of Behavior Chapter 2 Of Being Moved: Motivation, Momentum, Freedom, and Nature the Phenomenology of Perception Chapter 3 Of Being with Others: Natality and the Atmosphere of Humanity in the Phenomenology of Perception Chapter 4 Retrieving Nature’s Interiority: Toward Poetic Phenomenology Chapter 5 Beginning Elsewhere: Generative Phenomenology and Poetic Phenomenology Chapter 6 Totality: Animality, Genesis and Development Chapter 7 Plurality and Visibility Conclusions Practical Implications of a Natal Ontology List of Abbreviations Works Cited v Introduction: Of Being Numerous “Shipwrecked by the singular We have chosen the meaning Of being numerous” – George Oppen Natals and Plurals: Toward a Natal Ontology through Merleau-Ponty We are not born alone, nor do we live alone. That will be basic assertion of this project. This is not a novel suggestion. But it is one that I would like to situate in a particular philosophical history. According to Maurice Merleau-Ponty, this history is for the most part a Cartesian history. In his courses on nature, Merleau-Ponty describes how the Cartesian project marks a certain origin of modern and contemporary thought on being and nature and, perhaps more importantly, the beginning of a method for approaching the origin of one’s self and other selves. Following Merleau-Ponty, let us return to that beginning. In his famed Meditations on First Philosophy, Descartes reflects on his origin, reinitiating philosophy as a sort of naval-gazing: philosophy as reflection, as a turn toward interiority. Descartes considers his origins, but he considers these origins without regard to his exterior. Descartes ask himself: “From what source, then, do I derive my existence? Why, from myself or from my parents, or from whatever other things there are there are that are less perfect that God” (32). Initially, it seems to Descartes that his parents caused him: he recognizes that his parents brought him into the world. Yet this moment of appearing in the world does not satisfy Descartes’s quest for his origins. Parents, human lineage, and generation do not define sense of origin that Descartes intends; behind particular parents must lie an infinite series of other parents, and other 1 causes that began these other people (Descartes 34). In order to escape this evident infinite regress, Descartes returns to the classical Scholastic postulation of a metaphysical God as the absolute site and source. This God not only sets in motion the chain of events leading to Descartes’s birth, but also preserves Descartes’s and others existences (Descartes 34). In the third of his Meditations, Descartes proves God and thereby shows himself that he is “not alone in the world” (Descartes 29). Locked in his interiority, withdrawn from his senses, without flesh, Descartes required a metaphysical God to secure him access to the world and to company in that world. But if, following Merleau-Ponty and his phenomenological contemporaries, we abandon the Cartesian appeal to metaphysics as the absolute origin, then we find ourselves in a post-metaphysical era searching for our origins. No longer does an appeal to classical formulations of God, the soul or freedom suffice to describe either our beginnings or our aims in life. With the end of metaphysics, philosophy no longer poses the question, “Why is there something rather than nothing?” Instead, we look at where we stand in relation to that question, to its appearance in our tradition. We might then, as Heidegger suggests, ask instead, “How does it stand with being?” (Introduction to Metaphysics 27) Or, how is being disclosed? That is, how is being for the one who poses the questions? Heidegger offers these alternatives to traditional metaphysical questions which cannot address the phenomena of life’s appearance for us. For Heidegger in Being and Time, being discloses itself to the mortal being, to Da-sein. It is the human condition of mortality that first and foremost discloses being. This Heideggerian turn follows a long philosophical tradition, perhaps first instantiated with Plato’s record of Socrates’s death in the Phaedo, persisting through Kierkegaard’s double 2 emphasis on selfhood and fear of death, and continuing into Heidegger’s own work which emphasizes mortality over natality. Provocative and formative as this revelation of existence in relation to mortality has been, such phenomenology risks preemptively foreclosing and overlooking the very phenomenal appearance of life in birth. In this project, I repose Heidegger’s question and consider another post- metaphysical response, one oriented toward beginnings. This response is suggested by the work of Heidegger’s contemporaries, Hannah Arendt and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. Perhaps death is not the phenomenological event par excellence as Heidegger implies (Dastur 183). Perhaps birth, perhaps natality not mortality, discloses being. As Heidegger would no doubt affirm, death eludes experience: “One could say that death is the event par excellence, except that it is never present, it never presently happens. It does not open up a world, but rather closes it forever” (Dastur 183). After death, I cannot reflect on death in this world; after birth, I can reflect on the ramifications of that event, if not the event itself. Given this non-appearance of death, perhaps phenomenology might pursue birth rather than death as the paradigmatic event, bearing witness in phenomenological reflection to the opening and initiating of worlds. If we begin a philosophical meditation on Heidegger’s question but without Descartes’s rejection of exteriority and flesh, we see new possibilities. We ask similar and related questions: When did we, and do we begin? Do I begin or do we begin? Do I begin with my own birth? If I give birth, when does the other person begin and when does the child cease to be a part of me? Yet the answers to these questions differ profoundly when we admit our exteriority – our corporeality, our visibility – into consideration. We notice a certain fragility and passivity inherent to corporeality; we 3 note that while we begin, we cannot do so with absolute agency and freedom as the Cartesian subject might. I might ask, when I begin an action, how much of it actually originates in me? I notice that in my natality, I am motivated and caught in a momentum of existence. When we attend to our exteriority and corporeality, we also find that this momentum and flesh indicates that we are not alone as we act. When we gaze at our navel, we see our navel: We see the mark in our flesh of our connection to other bodies. We see a literal reminder of what Merleau-Ponty calls our “umbilical bond” to being (VI 107). Hannah Arendt found birth to be the paradigmatic phenomenological event for the political philosophy described in the Human Condition (HC 9). As she puts it in the Life of the Mind, Arendt suggests that we think of ourselves as “natals” as well as mortals (2 109). In the Human Condition Arendt argues that humans distinguish themselves as beings who begin: “With the creation of man, the principle of beginning came into the world itself, which, of course, is only another way of saying that the principle of freedom was created when man was created but now before” (HC 17). Our human actions, far from passive effects, initiate new and unpredictable trajectories of movements, events, and thoughts. Arendt’s description of human being in terms of natality contrasts sharply with that of her eminent teacher Heidegger who shaped post-metaphysical phenomenology and ontology.
Recommended publications
  • Merleau-Ponty in Contemporary Perspective Phaenomenologica
    MERLEAU-PONTY IN CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVE PHAENOMENOLOGICA COLLECTION FONDEE PAR H.L. VAN BREDA ET PUBLIEE SOUS LE PATRONAGE DES CENTRES D'ARCHIVES-HUSSERL 129 MERLEAU-PONTY IN CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVE Edited by PATRICK BURKE and JAN VAN DER VEKEN Comite de redaction de la collection: President: S. IJsseling (Leuven) Membres: W. Marx (Freiburg i. Br.), J.N. Mohanty (Philadelphia), P. Ricreur (Paris), E. Straker (KOln), J. Taminiaux (Louvain-Ia-Neuve), Secretaire: J. Taminiaux MERLEAU-PONTY IN CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES Edited by PATRICK BURKE and lAN VAN DER VEKEN ..... SPRlNGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS" MEDIA, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Merleau-Ponty in contemporary perspective! edited by Patrick Burke and Jan Van der Veken. p. cm. -- IPhaenomenologica ; v. 129) Papers presented at the internatIonal sympasium on Merleau-Ponty. held in Nov. 1991 by the Institute of Philosophy and the Husserl Archives at the Kathol ieke Universiteit te Leuven. rncludes bibl iographical references and index. ISBN 978·94·010-4768·5 ISBN 978·94·011·1751·7 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978·94·011·1751·7 1. Merleau-Ponty. Maurice. 1908-1961--Congresses. r. Burke. Patrick. II. Veken. Jan van der. III. Series, Phaenomenologica 129. B2430.M3764M4695 1993 194--dc20 92-38343 ISBN 978-94-010-4768-5 printed an acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved © 1993 Springer Science+Business Media Oordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1993 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover lst edition 1993 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT Pittsburgh, PA 15282
    DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY DUQUESNE UNIVERSITY 600 FORBES AVENUE PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT PITTSBURGH, PA 15282 RETURN SERVICE REQUESTED 3 0 3 DUQUESNE GRADUATE PHILOSOPHY NEWS Spring 2013 • Volume 6, Issue 1 DEPARTMENT NEWS The Department is thrilled to announce the Dr. Schwebel’s publications include a chapter entitled “Monad hiring of Tom Eyers as Assistant Professor and Time: Reading Leibniz with Heidegger and Benjamin,” to PROOF Tuesday / April 30 / 2013 12:17 PM within the Philosophy Department. Dr. Eyers be included in the forthcoming book “Sparks Will Fly”: Martin received his Ph.D. from Kingston University Heidegger and Walter Benjamin, edited by Andrew Benjamin and in London and recently completed a Post- Dimitris Vardoulakis. Doctorate Fellowship at Washington University in St. Louis. Dr. Eyers specializes in contemporary French The department congratulates George Yancy on philosophy, psychoanalysis (particularly Lacan), and Marxism. his promotion to full Professor! Dr. Yancy has Dr. Eyers will start teaching classes in the fall, including a published prolifically since his hiring in 2007. course on Contemporary Philosophy as well as offering Basic He is the author of Look, A White!: Philosophical Philosophical Questions courses. Dr. Eyers’ published works Essays in Whiteness and Black Bodies, White include his books, Lacan and the Concept of the Real and the Gazes: The Continuing Significance of Race as upcoming Post-Rationalism: Psychoanalysis, Epistemology, and well as his recently released edited books: Race Marxism in Post-War France (May 2013). and Pedagogy: Scholars of Color Reflect on Exploring Race in Predominantly White Classrooms (2013), Pursuing Trayvon Martin: The department is also excited to announce Historical Contexts and Contemporary Manifestations of Racial NEWS FROM ALUMNI the hiring of Paula Schwebel as a visiting Dynamics (2012), Christology and Whiteness: What Would Jesus Assistant Professor within the philosophy Do? (2012), and Reframing the Practice of Philosophy: Bodies of department.
    [Show full text]
  • Merleau-Ponty's Aesthetic Interworld: from Primordial Percipience to Wild
    Penultimate version. Please cite the published version in Philosophy Today, DOI: 10.5840/philtoday20181024231 Merleau-Ponty’s Aesthetic Interworld: From Primordial Percipience to Wild Logos ‘…each brushstroke must satisfy an infinite number of conditions’ (Cézanne’s Doubt:65-66, Le Doute de Cézanne:28). Abstract: The overall aim of this paper is to defend the value of the arts as uniquely instructive regarding philosophical questions. Specifically, I aim to achieve two things: firstly, to show that through the phenomenological challenge to dualist and monist ontologies the key debate in aesthetics regarding subjective response and objective judgment is reconfigured and resolved. I argue that Merleau-Ponty’s analyses complement and complete Kant’s project. Secondly, I propose that through his phenomenological interrogations of the creative process the broader issue of the viability of his relational non-dualist ontology is defended against accusations that it has not gone beyond dualism or that it has collapsed into a monism. Key words: Merleau-Ponty; ontology; aesthetics; intertwining; Kant; expression; Cézanne Since Plato’s infamous ‘banishment’ of the mimetic poets from his ideal city-state, the expressive arts have had a chequered history in philosophy, at times elevated to the divine and at other times treated with disdain for their purported inability to offer truth and with suspicion for their seductive charms. Neither of these extreme stances is finally defensible. There is both a mystery in the arresting power of great art and an opacity in the creative 1 process that defy ready explanations. The overall aim of this paper is to defend the value of the arts as uniquely instructive regarding philosophical questions.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Painting in Merleau-Ponty's Thought
    PERCEPTION AND Painting in Merleau-Ponty’s THOUGHT Perception and Painting in Merleau-Ponty’s Thought Carolyne Quinn Paris III, Université de Sorbonne-Nouvelle/University College Dublin Abstract Maintaining that “the perceived world is the always presupposed foundation of all rationality, all value and all existence” (1964/1964: 13), Maurice Merleau- Ponty sought to develop a descriptive philosophy of perception, our kinaesthetic, prescientific, lived-bodily experience and cognition of the world—the unification of our affective, motor and sensory capacities. For Merleau-Ponty, ‘perception’ is an expressive and creative instance intimately linked with artistic practice, and although he wrote about all kinds of art, painting was the art form he considered in most depth. This paper seeks to elaborate upon the links between perception and painting in his thought, examining his three main essays on the topic of painting. We begin with the descriptive phenomenology of “Cézanne’s Doubt” under the influence of Edmund Husserl (1945), to structuralism in “Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence” (1952), and finally to his formulation of an original ontology in “Eye and Mind” (1961). Keywords: Perception; painting; Merleau-Ponty; art; phenomenology In the lexicon of Maurice Merleau-Ponty, ‘perception’ has an idiosyncratic meaning and drawing attention to and describing the role of this notion in human experience may be said to be one of the main aims and contributions of his phenomenology to philosophy today. Arguing perception to be an expressive
    [Show full text]
  • MERLEAU-PONTY and BARTHES on IMAGE CONSCIOUSNESS: Probing the (Im)Possibility of Meaning
    MERLEAU-PONTY AND BARTHES ON IMAGE CONSCIOUSNESS: Probing the (Im)possibility of Meaning NATASHA BEAUDIN PEARSON or bothδιανοια Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Roland Barthes, images are not merely Fobjects in space; they belong to the realm of the metaphysical. Paintings “move” us, according to Merleau-Ponty: their “quality, light, color, depth […] awaken an echo in our bod[y] and […] our body welcomes them.”1 To encounter a painting is to apprehend it through one’s body. We constitute “brute meaning” by drawing upon the “fabric of the world” in which our bodies are inextricably caught.2 Conversely, for Barthes, poignant photographs “wound” us: they contain an “element [the punctum] that rises from the scene, shoots out of it like an arrow, and pierces” us.3 Unlike Merleau-Ponty, Barthes believes that pictures resist meaning-making. They provoke an “internal agitation,” an “animation” in the viewer. Yet this “affect” cannot wholly be reduced or explained.4 Hence, I think the crux of Merleau-Ponty’s and Barthes’ disagreement about the ontology of image consciousness has to do with the possibility of meaning-making (or lack thereof). While Merleau-Ponty believes that a painting can be meaningful and express the essential “indivisible whole[ness]” and “imperious 1 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, “Eye and Mind,” in The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader, ed. Galen Johnson (Evanston, IL: Northwestern UP, 1993), 125. 2 Ibid., 123. 3 Roland Barthes, Camera Lucida, trans. Richard Howard (New York: Hill and Wang, 1981), 26. 4 Barthes, Camera Lucida, 19-20. 8 Merleau-Ponty and Barthes on Image Consciousness unity” of the world,5 Barthes contends that “since every photograph is contingent (and thereby outside of meaning), photography cannot signify (aim at a generality) except by assuming a mask.”6 In this paper, I outline Barthes’ critique of Merleau- Ponty’s phenomenology of painting—and his phenomenology more generally—and propose how we might explain the two philosophers’ disagreements on the subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Art and Phenomenology Today
    The University of Maine DigitalCommons@UMaine Honors College 5-2014 Somaesthetics and Aesthetic Transactions: Art and Phenomenology Today Monique Boutin University of Maine - Main Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.library.umaine.edu/honors Part of the Art and Design Commons, and the Art Practice Commons Recommended Citation Boutin, Monique, "Somaesthetics and Aesthetic Transactions: Art and Phenomenology Today" (2014). Honors College. 154. https://digitalcommons.library.umaine.edu/honors/154 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@UMaine. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors College by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UMaine. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SOMAESTHETICS AND AESTHETIC TRANSACTIONS: ART AND PHENOMENOLOGY TODAY by Monique J. Boutin A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for a Degree with Honors (Art History and Studio Art) The Honors College University of Maine May 2014 Advisory Committee: Justin Wolff, Associate Professor of Art History, Advisor Michael Grillo, Associate Professor of Art History and Chair, Department of Art Kirsten Jacobson, Associate Professor of Philosophy James Linehan, Professor of Art Andy Mauery, Associate Professor of Art © 2014 Monique Boutin All Rights Reserved Abstract This thesis inquires into the application of Richard Shusterman’s somaesthetics with respect to contemporary art, through an analysis of the work of Yann Toma and Tatiana Trouvé included in the exhibition Aesthetic Transactions, 2012. In exploring somaesthetics in relation to art, this thesis addresses John Dewey’s aesthetics and idea of the consummatory experience, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology with respect to art and experience as parts of the foundation of Shusterman’s ideas of somaesthetics.
    [Show full text]
  • Publications
    Publications Hugh J. Silverman CHAPTERS IN BOOKS CHAPTERS IN BOOKS 1974-1979 1. “Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty: Interpreting Hegel” in RADICAL PHENOMENOLOGY: ESSAYS IN MEMORY OF MARTIN HEIDEGGER, ed. John Sallis (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1978), 209-224. 2. “Dasein and Existential Ambiguity” in HEIDEGGER’S EXISTENTIAL ANALYTIC, ed. F.A. Elliston (The Hague: Mouton, 1978), 97-108. CHAPTERS IN BOOKS 1980-1989 3. “Philosophy” (52 entries) in CRITICAL BIBLIOGRAPHY OF FRENCH LITERATURE, ed. Douglas W. Alden and Richard A. Brooks (Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1980), 77-87. Compiled and reviewed with A.S. Weiss. 4. “Un Egale Deux ou l’espace autobiographique et ses limites,” trans. Françoise Marin, in LE DEUX (Revue d’esthetique), ed. M. Le Bot (Paris: 10-18, 1980), 279- 301. 5. “Sartre’s Words on the Self” in JEAN -PAUL SARTRE: CONTEMPORARY APPROACHES TO HIS PHILOSOPHY, eds. H. J. Silverman and F.A. Elliston (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press and Brighton, Sussex: Harvester Press, 1980), 85- 104. 6. “Merleau -Ponty and the Interrogation of Language” in MERLEAU -PONTY: PERCEPTION, STRUCTURE, LANGUAGE, ed. John Sallis (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1981), pp. 122-141. Hugh J. Silverman CHAPTERS IN BOOKS - Page 2 of 6 __________________________________________________________________________ 7. “The Limits of Logocentrism (On the Way to Grammatology)” in HEIDEGGER AND LANGUAGE, ed. David Wood (Coventry, England: Parousia Press, 1981), 51-70. Also in PHENOMENOLOGY AND THE HUMAN SCIENCES, ed. J. N. Mohanty (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1985), 107-119. 8. “Beckett, Philosophy and the Self” in THE PHILOSOPHICAL REFLECTION OF MAN IN LITERATURE, ed. Anna Teresa Tymieniecka (Analecta Husserliana, vol.12) (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1982), 153-160.
    [Show full text]
  • The Extended Body and the Aesthetics of Merleau-Ponty David Goldblatt
    The Extended Body and the Aesthetics of Merleau-Ponty David Goldblatt 25 Evental Aesthetics ABSTRACT An extended “restless” body was the center of perceptual and ontological importance for Merleau- Ponty — a source of insight into how persons navigate and understand the world. But he was sufficiently aware as well of the roles an extended body played in art. This paper considers two stages in Merleau-Ponty’s work, roughly corresponding to his early and late writings, where the boundary between body and world can be flexible and complex but where the body’s extension is artistically significant. After Fred Rush’s coinage of “prosthetic effect,” I utilize prosthesis metaphorically to illustrate the use of an extended body in the production and reception of art when the world demands an immediate response and the imposition of engagement and where the potential for aesthetic identification has greater explanatory power as a unit than as a body separate from that environment. The second use deals with Merleau-Ponty’s more difficult notions of flesh and chiasm to consider an intersecting world unfolding itself — reversing the direction of the usual dialogue between artist and a soliciting world, as Merleau-Ponty sees it. In the course of doing so, this essay includes a discussion of Paul Klee’s painting, The Ventriloquist in the Moors, Descartes on phantom limb pains and artistic identity. While technology has fostered digital devices, which appear as prostheses and form significant aspects of our culture, Merleau- Ponty had imagined our extended bodies in more ubiquitous and quotidian ways. KEYWORDS Merleau-Ponty Prosthetic Ventriloquism Flesh Cézanne Klee Descartes Volume 5 Number 1 (2016) 26 The Extended Body and the Aesthetics of Merleau-Ponty Maurice Merleau-Ponty was sufficiently astute in recognizing that an extended view of the human body had significant consequences for the understanding of production, reception, and experience in art.
    [Show full text]
  • Perspectives Volume 2. 2009
    PERSPECTIVES International Postgraduate Journal of Philosophy Volume 2 Autumn 2009 SPECIAL ISSUE: Continental Philosophy EDITORS: Anna Nicholson, Luna Dolezal, Seferin James, Sheena Hyland UCD School of Philosophy PERSPECTIVES International Postgraduate Journal of Philosophy Founding Editors Anna Nicholson, Luna Dolezal, Sheena Hyland Editors Anna Nicholson, Luna Dolezal, Seferin James, Sheena Hyland International Board of Reviewers Maria Baghramian (University College Dublin) Joseph Cohen (University College Dublin) Christopher Cowley (University College Dublin) Fred Cummins (University College Dublin) Tsarina Doyle (NUI Galway) Brian Elliott (University College Dublin) Sinead Hogan (Dun Laoghaire Institute of Art, Design and Technology, Dublin) Fiona Hughes (University of Essex, UK) Galen Johnson (University of Rhode Island, USA) Christopher Mole (University College Dublin) Aislinn O’Donnell (National College of Art and Design, Dublin) Felix Ó Murchadha (NUI Galway) Maria Baghramian Acknowledgements Margaret Brady The Editors gratefully acknowledge the support of Christopher Cowley University College Dublin, National University of Ireland. Helen Kenny Funding Emma Nic Eodhasa UCD School of Philosophy UCD SEED Fund The International Board of Reviewers UCD School of Philosophy Design and Layout Patrick McKay, Advantage Point Promotions UCD College of Human Sciences Thanks to Maria Baghramian Margaret Brady Christopher Crowley Helen Kenny Emma Nic Eodhasa James O’Shea Patrick McKay International Board of Reviewers UCD School of Philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • Three Essays in Conversational Ethics
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 1997 Three essays in conversational ethics Scott Forrest Aikin The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Aikin, Scott Forrest, "Three essays in conversational ethics" (1997). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5623. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5623 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Three Essays in Conversational Ethics by Scott Forrest Aikin B.A. Washington University in St. Louis, 1994 presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts The University of Montana 1997 Approved by: kMJLtsS rso/iChairfeersoj Dean, Graduate^School Date UMI Number: EP41087 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI EP41087 Published by ProQuest LLC (2014). Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code ProQuest LLC.
    [Show full text]
  • 20Th Century Avant-Garde Poetics in Gertrude Stein, Mina Loy, and Blaise Cendrars
    University of Rhode Island DigitalCommons@URI Open Access Dissertations 2016 The Color of Grammar and the Surface of Language: 20th Century Avant-Garde Poetics in Gertrude Stein, Mina Loy, and Blaise Cendrars Sarah E. Kruse University of Rhode Island, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/oa_diss Recommended Citation Kruse, Sarah E., "The Color of Grammar and the Surface of Language: 20th Century Avant-Garde Poetics in Gertrude Stein, Mina Loy, and Blaise Cendrars" (2016). Open Access Dissertations. Paper 449. https://digitalcommons.uri.edu/oa_diss/449 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by DigitalCommons@URI. It has been accepted for inclusion in Open Access Dissertations by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@URI. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE COLOR OF GRAMMAR AND THE SURFACE OF LANGUAGE: 20TH CENTURY AVANT-GARDE POETICS IN GERTRUDE STEIN, MINA LOY, AND BLAISE CENDRARS BY SARAH E. KRUSE A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN ENGLISH UNIVERSITY OF RHODE ISLAND 2016 DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DISSERTATION OF SARAH E. KRUSE APPROVED: Dissertation Committee: Major Professor Mary Cappello Peter Covino Galen Johnson Nasser H. Zawia DEAN OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL UNIVERSITY OF RHODE ISLAND 2016 ABSTRACT The study here arises from a long held interest in the philosophical works of Ludwig Wittgenstein and a preoccupation with the role and function of ordinary language. Examining the late work of Wittgenstein, and focusing on his last work, Remarks on Color, I connect the place of color within language and its fundamental role in our visual perception with an earlier idea of Wittgensteinian grammar.
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking Merleau-Ponty in and out of Time
    The Twenty-First Century Body: Thinking Merleau-Ponty In and Out of Time Fortieth Annual Meeting of the International Merleau-Ponty Circle and Juried Art Exhibition October 1-3, 2015 Worcester Polytechnic Institute Alden Memorial Hall Wednesday, September 30 Pre-Conference Activity 5:00–7:30 Architecture and Laboratories Tour Meet at the Courtyard Marriott Worcester Lobby, 72 Grove St. at 4:45pm Architecture At and Around Campus: Pure Experience, Emulation, and Lumber David Samson, WPI Engineering the Heart Glenn Gaudette, Katrina Hansen, Joshua Gershlak, WPI Flesh and Not Flesh: A Robotics Demonstration Michael Gennert, Robotics, WPI Moving the Virtual Body: Some Demonstrations Robert Lindeman, Mi (Mia) Feng, Zhixin (Jason) Yan, WPI Thursday, October 1 8:30–9:00 Registration and Refreshments 9:00–9:30 Welcome and Opening Remarks Jennifer McWeeny, WPI 9:30–11:00 Session I: Soul and Cyborg Moderator: Ann Murphy, University of New Mexico Structure, Vital Form and the Cyborg: Are We Natural Born Cyborgs? Dorothea Olkowski, University of Colorado Springs The Sense of the Transcendental: Heraclitus, Husserl, and Merleau-Ponty on the Soul Keith Whitmoyer, Pace University 11:00–11:15 Break 11:15–12:45 Session II: The View from Here and Now Moderator: Rajiv Kaushik, Brock University Measurement as Transcendental-Empirical Écart: Merleau-Ponty on Deep Temporality David Morris, Concordia University The Space of the Flesh: On the Dialectics of Orientation and the Absurdity of the Origin Jay Worthy, University of Alberta 12:45–2:30 Lunch 2:30–3:15
    [Show full text]