<<

Florida State University Law Review

Volume 41 Issue 1 Article 2

2013

The Forgotten Henry Simons

Daniel Shaviro [email protected]

Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.law.fsu.edu/lr

Part of the Law Commons

Recommended Citation Daniel Shaviro, The Forgotten Henry Simons, 41 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. 1 (2013) . https://ir.law.fsu.edu/lr/vol41/iss1/2

This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Florida State University Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW

THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS

Daniel Shaviro

VOLUME 41 FALL 2013 NUMBER 1

Recommended citation: Daniel Shaviro, The Forgotten Henry Simons, 41 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 1 (2013). THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS

DANIEL SHAVIRO*

I. INTRODUCTION ...... 1 II. SIMONS’ METEORIC CAREER ...... 5 III. HENRY SIMONS: A DIFFERENT TYPE OF LIBERTARIAN? ...... 10 A. Philosophical ...... 11 B. Assessing and Explaining Simons’ “Interventionism” ...... 15 C. Simons’ Support for Progressive Income Taxation ...... 20 IV. SIMONS ON THE INCOME TAX ...... 25 A. Income Taxation Versus Consumption Taxation ...... 25 1. Why Did Simons Prefer the Income Tax? ...... 25 2. Simons’ View of Realization and Deferral ...... 29 3. What Might Simons Think Today About the Choice Between Income and Consumption Taxation? ...... 33 (a) More Pro-Income Tax? ...... 33 (b) Potentially Pro-Consumption Tax? ...... 35 V. CONCLUSION ...... 37

I. INTRODUCTION Surely just about everyone in the U.S. federal income tax field has heard of Henry Simons, although mainly for just one thing: his fa- mous definition of “personal income” as the value of one’s consumption plus change in net worth during the relevant period,1 as stated in his classic 1938 work, Personal Income Taxation. Simons’ formulation of what became known as the Haig-Simons income defi- nition provided a central orientation point for U.S. tax policy thinking for many decades thereafter. Even today, it remains extremely important. The man behind the definition is, in some respects, considerably less well-known. For example, while most tax aficionados probably would identify him as a strong advocate of the federal income tax and of using a broadly defined base, fewer may know how comfortable he was with retaining the realization principle as a practical accommo- dation.2 Fewer still may be aware that he advocated eliminating the corporate income tax, conditioned only on a rule change providing for shareholder-level gain realization when appreciated stock (or other

* Wayne Perry Professor of Taxation, NYU Law School. I am grateful to Miranda Perry, Chris Sanchirico, Robert Van Horn, and the participants in conferences at the USC and FSU Law Schools for helpful comments on an earlier draft. 1. More precisely, Simons states: “Personal income may be defined as the algebraic sum of (1) the market value of rights exercised in consumption and (2) the change in the value of the store of property rights between the beginning and end of the period in ques- tion.” HENRY C. SIMONS, PERSONAL INCOME TAXATION: THE DEFINITION OF INCOME AS A PROBLEM OF FISCAL POLICY 50 (1938) [hereinafter SIMONS, TAXATION]. 2. See, e.g., HENRY C. SIMONS, FEDERAL 78 (1950) [hereinafter SIMONS, REFORM]. 2 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

property) was transferred by gift or bequest, and accompanied by the suggestion that dividends not be taxed until the shareholder had ful- ly recovered her basis in the underlying stock.3 Perhaps fewest of all realize that today, in active intellectual memory, there are actually two Henry Simonses—albeit each the same person, not just biologically but also intellectually— remembered in two mostly distinct communities. First, of course, there is the income tax community’s Henry Simons, who, in the course of advocating a broad tax base and “drastic progression”4 memorably demolished intellectual opponents,5 vehemently de- nounced support for his own bottom-line positions that was based on reasoning about utility or sacrifice,6 and lucidly addressed how a workable income definition could actually be implemented.7 Simons was not just an income tax writer, however. At the time of his death, most of his published work discussed other issues—for ex- ample, the case for a competitive free-market economy,8 the problems caused by labor unions,9 and his approach to .10 The nontax writings included not only Simons’ best-known work at the time of his death11—which Personal Income Taxation cites as its un- derlying policy guide12—but also the work that he considered his best.13 Moreover, while these writings are little-known today in tax circles, there is a community interested in free enterprise, - school economic analysis, and libertarianism, to which they remain at least historically important but highly controversial.

3. See id. at 112. 4. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 18. 5. See, e.g., id. at 16-17. 6. See id. at 8-16. 7. See id. at 41-60 (Chapter 2: “The Definition of Income”). 8. HENRY C. SIMONS, A Positive Program for Laissez Faire: Some Proposals for a Liberal Economic Policy, in ECONOMIC POLICY FOR A FREE SOCIETY 40 (1948) [hereinafter SIMONS, Positive Program]. 9. See Henry C. Simons, Some Reflections on Syndicalism, 52 J. POL. ECON. 1 (1944). 10. See Henry C. Simons, Rules versus Authorities in Monetary Policy, 44 J. POL. ECON 1 (1936). Simons’ previously published nontax writings were collected and posthu- mously published in Economic Policy for a Free Society (1948). The book includes twelve previously published essays that together are more than 300 pages long. This admittedly is slightly shorter than the combined page count for Personal Income Taxation (1938) plus his only other significant tax policy work, Federal Tax Reform (1950), but the latter was only posthumously published. 11. , Prefatory Note to ECONOMIC POLICY FOR A FREE SOCIETY, supra note 8, at v, v-vi (stating that Simons’ “best-known essay” was A Positive Program for Lais- sez Faire, initially published in 1934, which is discussed in more detail in Part III, infra). 12. See SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 2 n.1. 13. See George J. Stigler, , 17 J.L. & ECON. 1, 5 (1974) (stating that Simons once said that his article on monetary policy, Rules versus Authorities in Mon- etary Policy, was “the best piece of writing he had produced”). 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 3

George Stigler called Simons the “Crown Prince of . . . the Chicago school of ,”14 and others have agreed that he was its “prime architect.”15 What is more, Simons labeled and regarded himself not merely as a supporter but more specifically as a libertar- ian. However, some aspects of Simons’ work—including, but not lim- ited to, his advocacy of progressive income taxation—have caused this characterization to rankle in some quarters. Indeed, the wounds are sufficiently fresh that the title of one recent entry, published in the Journal of Libertarian Studies, used the present tense in pro- claiming: “Henry Simons Is Not a Supporter of Free Enterprise.”16 I first encountered the second Henry Simons at a lecture given by at the Law School about twenty years ago. As I recall, Coase devoted a large portion of his remarks to denouncing Simons for what Coase considered an inappropriate will- ingness to rely on governmental regulatory solutions to market fail- ure, rather than asking how markets could themselves handle these problems.17 My then-Chicago colleague, the late Walter Blum, a Si- mons protégé who kindly acted as a mentor to me when I first en- tered law teaching, told me the next day that Coase had expressed surprise when Walter told him after the lecture of Simons’ continuing prominence as an intellectual architect of the income tax. It may seem most improbable that Simons, at least in his own self-assessment, was “at the same time an extreme libertarian and a believer in massive wealth redistribution.”18 As Herbert Kiesling notes, however, while “[o]ne can wonder how such a strange mixture

14. Id. at 1. 15. See Bruce Caldwell, The Chicago School, Hayek, and , in BUILDING CHICAGO ECONOMICS: NEW PERSPECTIVES ON THE HISTORY OF AMERICA’S MOST POWERFUL ECONOMICS PROGRAM 301, 304-06 (Robert Van Horn et al. eds., 2011) (accepting the “prime architect” claim although disagreeing in other respects with Van Horn’s and Mirowski’s analysis of the Chicago school’s early history); Rob Van Horn & Philip Mirowski, The Rise of the Chicago School of Economics and the Birth of Neoliberalism, in THE ROAD FROM MONT PÈLERIN: THE MAKING OF THE NEOLIBERAL THOUGHT COLLECTIVE 139, 140 (Philip Mirowski & Dieter Plehwe eds., 2009) (calling Simons the “prime architect” of the Chicago school); see also Edmund W. Kitch, The Fire of Truth: A Remembrance of Law and Econom- ics at Chicago, 1932–1970, 26 J.L. & ECON. 163, 179 (1983) (discussing Simons’ strong in- tellectual influence on the development of the Chicago School). 16. See Walter Block, Henry Simons Is Not a Supporter of Free Enterprise, 16 J. LIB- ERTARIAN STUD. 3 (2002). 17. Coase relatedly, but as I recall less prominently at this particular lecture, criti- cized Arthur Pigou, who famously proposed what are now called “Pigovian” taxes to ad- dress negative externalities such as pollution, rather than asking how markets, through the assignment of property rights, could do the job. I would guess that Coase’s reason for emphasizing Simons more than Pigou was that he recalled Simons’ close connection with the University of Chicago Law School, the site and sponsor of the talk, as its first econo- mist faculty member and an important early leader in the Chicago movement. 18. HERBERT KIESLING, TAXATION AND PUBLIC GOODS: A WELFARE-ECONOMIC CRI- TIQUE OF TAX POLICY ANALYSIS 67 (1992). 4 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

could be internally consistent, . . . in Simons’s hands the combination was logical.”19 I will argue that he is best viewed as an egalitarian of a particular kind. He hated wealth inequality, concentrated economic power (as people on the left often do), and centralized political power (as anti-state people on the right often do), but for exactly the same reasons and in exactly the same way. He thus explained that he would have liked what he called “decentralized socialism,” just as much as he liked what he called libertarianism, if not for his conclu- sion that it was self-contradictory and/or would turn into the same thing anyway.20 By itself, this tale of the two (but actually one) Henry Simonses would provide ample motivation for looking back at his work in the context of a conference commemorating one hundred years of the U.S. federal income tax. In particular, it helps to show why he viewed comprehensive income taxation as such a good solution to a large piece of the dilemma that he faced by reason of hating both wealth inequality and government intervention in the economy. However, there is also an interesting story to review regarding Simons’ perspective on the design of the federal income tax. Although his reasons for favoring comprehensive income taxation were quite distinctive, other underlying motivations can lead to the same place. Thus, it is of today, for its own sake, to see how his views, as an undeniably smart commentator early in the intellectual history of the U.S. income tax, look more than seventy years later. I therefore will discuss Simons’ views on the choice between income and con- sumption taxation with an eye both to what has changed since the 1930s and to how these changes might matter to one who shared his normative framework. In effect, I will ask what Simons might think today— but with due understanding that it would be both silly and presumptuous to draw overly confident bottom-line conclusions.21 The rest of this Article will proceed as follows: Part II offers a brief overview of Simons’ career; Part III discusses the issues raised by his self-proclaimed libertarianism, in light of its underlying philosophical motivations, his support for strong economic regulation in certain respects, and his support for a progressive income tax; Part IV dis-

19. Id. 20. HENRY C. SIMONS, Introduction: A Political Credo, in ECONOMIC POLICY FOR A FREE SOCIETY, supra note 8, at 1, 29-32 [hereinafter SIMONS, Political Credo]. , while offering a strong statement of Simons’ libertarian credentials that I quote below, also said of Simons that “[m]uch of his program was almost as harmonious with socialism as with private-enterprise .” GEORGE J. STIGLER, MEMOIRS OF AN UN- REGULATED 149 (1988). 21. I am not the first to ask this sort of question. See Charlene Luke, What Would Henry Simons Do?: Using an Ideal to Shape and Explain the Economic Substance Doctrine, 11 HOUS. BUS. & TAX L.J. 108 (2011). 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 5

cusses his views on the income versus consumption tax debate; and Part V offers a brief conclusion.

II. SIMONS’ METEORIC CAREER Henry Simons was born in 1899 in the small town of Virden, Illi- nois, the second child in an ambitious, upper middle class family.22 Second in his high school class, he was forced by family economic re- verses to enroll at the University of Michigan, rather than following his older sister’s route to an elite eastern private college.23 Here, he initially planned to become a lawyer like his father, but he became interested in . He started teaching economics at the University of Iowa in 1922. In 1927, he followed his mentor, the economist , to the University of Chicago Economics Department.24 Here, things initially did not go well. Many years later, Simons’ close friend Aaron Director reported that “Henry Simons was not liked in the economics department,”25 although he had allies as well as foes. Economics students found him a rude and aggressively indif- ferent teacher,26 quite in contrast to his subsequent very positive re- ception at the University of Chicago Law School. Simons’ scholarly record was also considered weak, as it consisted of “two book reviews in . . . twelve years”27 until finally, in 1934, he published a self- described “propagandist tract” in support of traditional liberalism

22. See Stigler, supra note 13, at 1; SHERRYL DAVIS KASPER, THE REVIVAL OF LAISSEZ- FAIRE IN AMERICAN MACROECONOMIC THEORY: A CASE STUDY OF THE PIONEERS 30 (2002) (noting that “[h]e grew up comfortably as a member of the middle class, the son of a mod- erately successful lawyer and an extremely ambitious homemaker”). 23. See Sherry Davis Kasper, Why Was Henry Simons Interventionist: The Curious Legacy of a Chicago Economist 6 (June 22, 2011) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://www.learningace.com/doc/5293928/7fbcc044dab921c837d7204dff3865e7/paper11kasper. 24. Id. at 6-8; Stigler, supra note 13, at 1 (describing Simons as Knight’s “premier student”). After starting at Iowa, Simons also completed a summer of graduate study at and spent a half-year in Germany studying the work of leading Ger- man . Id.; Edmund W. Kitch, Simons, Henry Calvert, in 3 THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF ECONOMICS AND THE LAW 465 (Peter Newman ed., 1998). George Stigler later noted a view among the University of Chicago economics faculty that Simons “had been sent to Europe for six months so that he would learn German so he could get a Ph.D.” Kitch, supra note 15, at 177. 25. Kitch, supra note 15, at 176. 26. According to , Simons’ colleague in the Chicago Economics Depart- ment, Simons was “almost openly insolent to those who ask questions and generally tells them that the questions they are asking are either too elementary for him to pay attention to or that they are not questions which any sensible person should propound or to which any sensible person reply.” See STIGLER, supra note 20, at 187 (quoting a letter by Douglas). 27. Kitch, supra note 15, at 177. 6 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

called A Positive Program for Laissez Faire: Some Proposals for a Liberal Economic Policy.28 Simons’ long pre-1934 period of academic torpor presumably re- flects that, as George Stigler put it, not just “brilliance” but also a “capacity for boredom . . . marked his entire life.”29 However, both the and the Roosevelt Administration’s whirlwind “One Hundred Days” response to it upon taking office in 1933—which Si- mons detested but considered no worse than what the Hoover Admin- istration had already been doing30—galvanized him into activity. In June 1933, he gave a public speech in which he declared: “I must talk, I believe for the first time of my life, as an extreme conservative, as an exponent of that much ridiculed political philosophy, nine- teenth century liberalism.”31 Positive Program was then his follow- up, explaining not only why he favored what he called a laissez-faire economic policy but also why departures from that approach were, in his view, responsible for the Great Depression. He subsequently called Personal Income Taxation merely “part of a scheme of policy outlined” in Positive Program,32 and the latter includes a section on tax policy that extensively anticipates the now more famous follow-up work. I will further discuss Positive Program in Part III below. In terms of his career, however, while the tract attracted a large audience to its dissent from the popular New Deal-era consensus against laissez- faire economics,33 skeptics on the Chicago faculty viewed it as merely “skillful propaganda” that “isn’t basic scholarship[,] and we shouldn’t be giving our few jobs on that basis.”34 What is more, while “[n]obody had any doubts about how smart Henry Simons was, . . . there were great doubts about . . . whether that book on personal income taxa- tion would ever be finished.”35 He had been working on it since the late 1920s,36 initially as his never-completed Ph.D. dissertation.37

28. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 1. 29. Stigler, supra note 13, at 1. 30. See SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 75 (“One cannot criticize the poli- cies of the present administration without seeming to approve those of its predecessors. In fact, one must condemn the Democrats mainly for their wholesale extension of the worst policies of the past. The N.R.A. is merely Mr. Hoover’s trust policy and wage policy writ large. The agricultural measures and many other planning proposals are the logical coun- terpart and the natural extensions of Republican protectionism.”). 31. Kasper, supra note 23, at 15-16 (quoting a speech given by Simons to the Social Workers Discussion Group in June 1933). 32. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 2 n.1. 33. See ELLIS W. HAWLEY, THE NEW DEAL AND THE PROBLEM OF MONOPOLY 292 (1995). 34. Kitch, supra note 15, at 177 (quoting George Stigler, paraphrasing the views of Paul Douglas at the time). 35. Id. (footnote omitted). 36. Aaron Director, Simons on Taxation, 14 U. CHI. L. REV. 15, 15 (1946). 37. Kasper, supra note 23, at 10-11; Stigler, supra note 13, at 1. Reportedly, the rea- 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 7

There was a clear political and ideological element to the tenure fight over Simons. His mentor, Frank Knight, is “widely remembered as . . . one of the most prominent academic advocates of free markets during the Roosevelt years,” and as a man whose lectures “were cred- ited . . . with transforming incoming socialists into nascent libertari- ans,” leaving behind ardent disciples such as George Stigler and Mil- ton Friedman.38 Knight’s and Simons’ arch-foe in the University of Chicago Economics Department, Paul Douglas—who spent several years trying to get Simons’ faculty appointment terminated39—was a New Deal progressive, highly typical of an era in which institutional- ist economists and legal realist law professors strongly favored ex- tensive government in the economy and viewed laissez-faire as a doc- trine that had utterly failed. As later noted, Simons was “opposed to almost everything that the institutionalists and legal realists stood for.”40 Ordinarily, Simons’ limited scholarly output, halfhearted teaching efforts, and stance outside the intellectual mainstream might have been expected to lead to his dismissal. However, in the face of Knight’s extremely emphatic support for Simons, and accompanying insistence that Simons’ opponents were engaged in a “personal attack on me,”41 the easier course for the Economics Department was simply to put off any final decision.42 Robert Maynard Hutchins, the energetic president of the Univer- sity of Chicago, then resolved the impasse by (in Walter Blum’s later words) “thrusting” Simons onto the law school faculty43 in 1939, one year after Personal Income Taxation had finally appeared in print. Simons had friends in the law school, but “the older members of the son Simons never finished obtaining his Ph.D. is that he “did not want to be examined by inferior minds” in oral examinations. Kasper, supra note 23, at 11 n.7. 38. Angus Burgin, The Radical Conservatism of Frank H. Knight, 6 MOD. INTELL. HIST. 513, 514 (2009). Knight did, however, to the long-lasting puzzlement of his followers, give a lecture at the University of Chicago in 1932 with the title “The Case for Com- munism, from the Standpoint of an Ex-liberal.” See id. He may have later regretted giving this talk, which was not widely published and which his libertarian supporters insisted was meant ironically or as a joke. See id. at 517-18. Others argue that it reflected his genu- ine ambivalence about free market capitalism, especially during the Great Depression, albeit reflecting feelings of “ex-liberalism” more than of actual communism or socialism. See id. 39. See STIGLER, supra note 20, at 187-89; Stigler, supra note 13, at 1-2. 40. Kitch, supra note 15, at 176. 41. Id. at 177 (quoting George Stigler, apparently paraphrasing what he learned from reading Knight’s correspondence). In his autobiography, Stigler quotes a letter from Knight saying: “I ‘feel’ as if eliminating [Simons] is eliminating me, and that when it is done I would be simply ‘through’ with the group, morally and sentimentally.” STIGLER, supra note 20, at 188-89. 42. George Stigler reports that the “controversy was resolved, Solomon-wise, by re- taining Simons and releasing another Knight disciple.” Id. at 189. 43. See Kitch, supra note 15, at 176. 8 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

faculty were either opposed to having an economist or indifferent.”44 Hutchins’ main motive, apart from resolving the impasse at the Eco- nomics Department, was to fill “the practical need to teach economics in the law school,”45 an aim he valued given his view that “law schools as then in existence were mere trade schools anyway.”46 Things immediately started to go much better for Simons, who became a far more enthusiastic and effective teacher in his new set- ting. He not only intrigued and bemused law students who (in George Stigler’s words) had never before met an “intelligent conservative,”47 but rapidly emerged as an intellectual leader. As Milton Friedman later noted, “Henry was a very gregarious fellow” and exerted a “great deal of influence through these social interactions.”48 Walter Blum, for example, “got to know him as a result of drinking beer with him in Hanley’s tavern about once a week over a period of about six or eight months.”49 By the early 1940s, according to Aaron Director, Simons “was slowly establishing himself as the head of a ‘school.’ ”50 , the pro-free market economist whose 1944 work, The Road to Serfdom, became a central libertarian tract, agreed, calling Simons the “intellectual centre” of a group of like-minded economists.51 Si- mons’ influence and teachings centered on using economic analysis to question the basic premises behind interventionist economic pro- grams, such as laws, securities regulations, controls, and pro-union labor laws.52 Simons was in touch with Hayek as early as 1934, when Hayek contacted him to express admiration for A Positive Program for Lais-

44. Id. (quoting Walter Blum). 45. Id. at 167. 46. Id. at 176 (quoting Aaron Director). 47. Id. at 177. 48. Id. at 179. Aaron Director and Allen Wallis also testified to Simons’ influence. See id. 49. Id. (quoting Blum). Simons’ intellectual influence is clear (although its limits can also be discerned) in the classic work WALTER J. BLUM & HARRY KALVEN, JR., THE UNEASY CASE FOR PROGRESSIVE TAXATION (1953). For example, this work shares Simons’ skepti- cism about theories “constructed on notions of benefit, sacrifice, [or] ability to pay.” Id. at 104. The authors agree with Simons that the main reason for tax progressivity is to reduce inequality (a much more obvious conclusion today than when the book was written). Blum and Kalven do, however, note of Simons’ critique of inequality as “unlovely” that “[t]his approach . . . forecloses any further discussion.” Id. at 72. They question the “contention [arguably made by Simons] that money represents economic power which permits its own- ers to make economic decisions affecting the lives of others.” Id. at 78. 50. Director, supra note 11, at v. 51. See Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 169 n.10. 52. See Kitch, supra note 15, at 179 (quoting Walter Blum). Blum states that Simons’ intellectual contributions “had a great deal to do with the tone at the University of Chicago law school at that time and later.” Id. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 9

sez Faire, and they soon became close friends.53 In April 1945, after a Reader’s Digest condensation of The Road to Serfdom had become a national best-seller, things reached a new stage. A speech by Hayek at the Detroit Economics Club, while on a U.S. tour promoting the book, led a politically activist conservative businessman in the audi- ence (Harold Luhnow, president of the Volker Fund) to propose fund- ing a specifically American version of The Road to Serfdom.54 While Luhnow wanted Hayek (or someone designated by him) to write an almost comic-book version of Road, suitable for a barely lit- erate mass audience,55 Hayek urged that the funding go instead to support the creation of a pro-free market intellectual center in the . To this end, he promptly contacted Simons, who re- sponded enthusiastically. Simons proposed the establishment, at the University of Chicago, of an independent Institute to be headed by a serious pro-free market intellectual—he had in mind his close friend Aaron Director, whom he hoped to lure back from Washington to Chicago—and to have a largely academic bent.56 While this was not quite what Luhnow wanted, further negotiations (also involving Rob- ert Maynard Hutchins on behalf of the University of Chicago) led to a more modest plan to create a Free Market Study at Chicago, headed by Director, whose salary the Volker Fund would pay for five years.57 There was one catch, however. The plan stipulated that Director would be granted tenure at the University of Chicago Law School, and this required approval not just from the law school (which agreed) but also from a university committee. On June 18, 1946, the committee rejected the proposal—to Simons’ great disappointment, in part due to his eagerness to persuade Director to move to Chicago. On the very next day, Simons died from an overdose of sleeping pills, possibly or even probably a suicide.58 Shortly thereafter, Director agreed to come to Chicago even with- out an up-front promise of tenure. There, in addition to playing a key foundational role in establishing the law and economics program and movement at the University of Chicago Law School, Director oversaw

53. Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 142. 54. See Caldwell, supra note 15, at 303; Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 140-41. 55. Luhnow apparently “suggested the book How We Live by Fred G. Clark (1944) as stylistic model for the American Road to Serfdom. One doubts if Hayek had ever seen a copy, for if he had, he would have immediately soured on Luhnow. How We Live was a large-print book, with didactic pictures facing each page of ‘text,’ which itself consisted of single-sentence paragraphs written for people who still moved their lips as they read. The quality of argument resembled a fourth-grade civics textbook.” Van Horn & Mirowski, su- pra note 15, at 150. 56. See Caldwell, supra note 15, at 303-04. 57. See Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 149-53. 58. For a full discussion of the question whether Simons committed suicide, see Rob- ert Van Horn, A Note on Henry Simons’ Death, 46 HIST. POL. ECON. (forthcoming 2014). 10 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

the posthumous publication of two additional Simons books: Federal Tax Reform, collecting a linked set of essays that Simons had written in 1943 and 1944 to guide post-World War II U.S. tax policy; and Economic Policy for a Free Society, collecting a number of Simons’ non-tax works, including A Positive Program for Laissez Faire.

III. HENRY SIMONS: A DIFFERENT TYPE OF LIBERTARIAN? Biographically speaking, Henry Simons’ credentials as a libertari- an and free-market conservative could scarcely be stronger. He called himself “severely libertarian or, in the English-Continental sense, liberal”59 and had what one can only call the audacity to write a spir- ited defense of laissez-faire economic principles in 1934, at the very moment when they were at their all-time U.S. low-water mark due to the Great Depression. He was closely associated both with Friedrich Hayek, whom contemporary libertarians still revere, and with such foundational conservative economists as Milton Friedman, George Stigler, and Aaron Director.60 Indeed, if one had to name a single “ar- chitect” of the pro-free market law and economics movement at the University of Chicago, Simons’ credentials are as good as anyone’s.61 Yet there are three at least apparent contradictions in thus classi- fying Simons. The first is that he was not a philosophical libertarian, at least as the term has often subsequently been defined in the litera- ture. The second is that his version of laissez-faire economic policy, as set forth in his 1934 pamphlet, soon came to be seen by pro-free market conservatives as, in Ronald Coase’s later words, “highly interventionist.”62 The third is that Simons is rightly known for supporting progressive redistribution, and to this end championing a comprehensive income tax. Needless to say, progressivity and re- , not to mention the income tax, are anathema today among libertarians and many conservatives. Yet Simons himself evi- dently saw no contradiction, lauding progressivity in the 1934 pam- phlet63 and then describing Personal Income Taxation as merely an

59. Simons, Political Credo, supra note 20, at 1. 60. See, e.g., Robert Van Horn, Chicago’s Shifting Attitude Toward Concentrations of Business Power (1934–1962), 34 U. L. REV. 1527, 1528 (2011) (“From the mid- 1930s through the mid-1940s, among the economists (and economists in training) associat- ed with the University of Chicago, there was a cohort of young economists—which included Henry Simons, Aaron Director, Milton Friedman, and George Stigler—who opposed con- centrations of economic power on the basis of classical liberal doctrine. Simons was the public face of this group.”). 61. See, e.g., Caldwell, supra note 15, at 305; Kitch, supra note 15, at 179; Stigler, supra note 13, at 1; Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15, at 140. 62. Kitch, supra note 15, at 178. 63. See SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 65-69, 76-77. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 11

elaboration of his 1934 ideas.64 The rest of this part discusses these apparent contradictions.

A. Philosophical Libertarianism In contemporary usage, libertarianism often is defined as a rights- based or process-based approach to justice that rejects consequential- ism. Thus, Robert Nozick, in Anarchy, State, and Utopia, disavows “end-result principles” that assess distributive justice in society based on how things have come out, in favor of the “historical” view that “whether a distribution is just depends upon how it came about.”65 Therefore, one can defend a state of affairs merely by showing that it had arisen via voluntary transactions from a just starting point. As Nozick recognized, this logic can support the enforceability of voluntary self-enslavement contracts. It thus can be deployed in de- fense of the essential justice of a society in which nearly everyone is observed to be a slave.66 While most libertarians reject this position, by positing that certain basic human rights are inalienable,67 liber- tarianism today is often construed as requiring acceptance, at least in most cases, of a rights-based, non-consequentialist approach to distributional and other issues. Thus, consider the claim that taking money from billionaires and giving it to poor people would be desira- ble if this would greatly increase aggregate human happiness— taking account both of the relative of a dollar to peo- ple in the two groups and of the transfer’s incentive and political economy effects. To a modern deontological or rights-based libertari- an, the underlying empirical claim need not be false in order for the conclusion to be rejected. Its classification as a rights violation rules it out from the start. This plainly is not Simons’ philosophical position. Consider the following statement from the second paragraph of his Positive Pro- gram: “There is in America no important disagreement as to the proper objectives of economic policy—larger real income, greater reg- ularity of production and employment, reduction of inequality,

64. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 2 n.1. 65. ROBERT NOZICK, ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA 153 (1974). 66. See id. at 331 (“Will it be possible to shift to a nonvoluntary framework permitting the forced exclusion of various styles of life? . . . The comparable question about an individ- ual is whether a free system will allow him to sell himself into slavery. I believe that it would.”). 67. See, e.g., Walter Block, Toward a Libertarian Theory of Inalienability: A Critique of Rothbard, Barnett, Smith, Kinsella, Gordon, and Epstein, 17 J. LIBERTARIAN STUD. 39, 40-41 (2003) (noting that few libertarians agree with his and Nozick’s view that voluntary self-enslavement contracts should be enforceable, and then proceeding to rebut prominent “middle ground” libertarians who have argued to the contrary). 12 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

preservation of democratic institutions. The real issues have to do merely with means, not with ends (or intentions) . . . .”68 To show how this plays today in deontologically libertarian circles, consider the libertarian economist Walter Block’s aforementioned tract, Henry Simons Is Not a Supporter of Free Enterprise.69 Block, while himself an “anarcho-capitalist” libertarian who deems all gov- ernment illegitimate, is willing to extend the label to “limited- government libertarians . . . who take the position that a proper gov- ernment exists only to protect peoples’ rights to personal safety and to the of their legitimately held possessions.”70 Hence, these libertarians, unlike Block himself, accept the potential legitimacy of armies, the police, and the courts. Alas, however, even thus given “at least a sporting chance of attaining the honorific ‘libertarian,’ ”71 Si- mons falls so far short that Block convicts him of intellectual “fraud and false advertising,”72 and closes by asking “how such a leftist could attain a reputation as a rightist . . . [and] why he felt the need to hide his views . . . under the banner of laissez faire. But these are questions for another day.”73 Block is surely right that today’s libertarians—even though, in his view, they are for the most part lamentably heterodox—generally would be inclined to break Simons’ staff and expel him from the Lib- ertarian Order. As we will see shortly, Simons most definitely did not view the government’s role as limited to providing an army, police, and the courts to protect people’s safety and “legitimately held pos- sessions.”74 However, Block’s reading of the term “libertarian” is both ahistorical and too narrow—at least, if we are trying to classify Si- mons as a matter of good intellectual history, rather than simply to apply one’s own preferred definition (which Block, of course, has eve- ry right to do). Consider Hayek’s The Road to Serfdom—surely, in intellectual history, a canonical and foundational libertarian work. Rather than stressing the importance of rights irrespective of consequences, Hay- ek emphasizes the empirical claim that movement towards greater centralized economic planning, even when it has as yet gone no fur- ther than it had in England and the United States as of the book’s 1944 publication date, will lead inexorably to Nazi- or Soviet-style

68. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 40. 69. Block, supra note 16. 70. Id. at 4-5. 71. Id. at 5. 72. Id. at 4 n.3. 73. Id. at 31. 74. Id. at 5. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 13

totalitarianism.75 This is precisely the concern that Simons expressed a decade earlier in Positive Program.76 Simons, just like Hayek, des- pised the “mongrel system of ‘national planning’ ” not only as a mere way station on the march towards totalitarianism, but as something that itself “implies and requires extreme concentration of political power, under essentially undemocratic institutions.”77 The New Deal did not have to turn into Nazism in order for Simons to view it as containing odious qualities of the same type, even if in vastly lesser degree. Even in today’s intellectual climate, it makes little sense to out Simons as a “leftist” and as “not a supporter of free enterprise,” merely because he cared about consequences rather than about in- nate and inviolable rights, and thus was conditionally willing to con- template rights violations. Such a classification scheme would rule out accepting the self-proclaimed credentials of any classical liber- al/contemporary political conservative who relies on the consequen- tialist view that free markets, strong rights, and limited government are generally the best prescription for increasing human welfare. Its adoption would require classifying the likes of , Milton Friedman, and , among others, as likewise “leftists” who oppose capitalism and freedom. In this regard, consider what Milton Friedman says about gradu- ated income taxation in his classic 1962 book, Capitalism and Free- dom. To be sure, Friedman does “find it hard, as a liberal” to see the justification for graduated rates when they are merely being used to redistribute income rather than to finance the costs of government.78 He considers this “a clear case of using coercion to take from some in order to give to others and thus to conflict head-on with individual freedom.”79 Yet Friedman defines the costs of government, which eve- ryone must help to pay for, as “including perhaps measures to elimi- nate poverty,”80 even though this is redistribution (coercively funded) plain and simple. Moreover, Friedman accepts that, in principle, paying for the costs of government “might well call for some measure of graduation, both on grounds of assessing costs in accordance with benefits and on

75. See, e.g., FRIEDRICH A. HAYEK, THE ROAD TO SERFDOM 2-5 (1944). Hayek accepts that wartime calls for centralization of powers, but he views the current English and U.S. course as clearly towards totalitarianism even in the aftermath of Hitler’s then-impending defeat. 76. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 40-41, 76-77. 77. Id. at 52. 78. MILTON FRIEDMAN, CAPITALISM AND FREEDOM 174 (1962). 79. Id. 80. Id. 14 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

grounds of social standards of equity.”81 The only problem he sees is that the “present high nominal rates [then reaching 92%, under the federal income tax] . . . can hardly be justified on this ground—if only because their yield is so low.”82 In short, under Block’s standard, not only is Milton Friedman no libertarian (a point that is uncontrover- sial),83 but only as a matter of degree can he fall short of being a “left- ist” who opposes capitalism and freedom despite having used those two words in the title of his most famous book. So perhaps the next question should be why Friedman, like Simons, declined to admit his ostensibly true nature as a secret “leftist.” Returning to Simons, he certainly did not claim to be a libertarian in today’s deontological sense—unsurprisingly, since any such claim would have been anachronistic. Rather, Simons placed himself squarely in an intellectual tradition whose “distinctive feature . . . is emphasis upon liberty as both a requisite and a measure of pro- gress.”84 While consequentialist and thus “largely pragmatic” in his view of social ethics, he described his views as “giv[ing] special place to liberty . . . as a ‘relatively absolute absolute.’ ”85 George Stigler helped make the case for the accuracy of Simons’ self-characterization in a 1974 retrospective: The central philosophy of the Positive Program was highly in- dividual. Simons believed that it was essential to the preservation of personal freedom that a large sector of economic life be orga- nized privately and competitively—this was a fundamental ele- ment of the liberal position that many, perhaps even an increasing share of us, still believe. . . . Simons’ central goal is as vital and as

81. Id. (emphasis added). 82. Id. A few pages earlier, in response to the view that progressive income taxation could be viewed as an insurance device that effectively pools people’s income and ability risk, thereby addressing the market failure that arises if the market fails to supply a suit- able insurance vehicle, Friedman objects only that “the taxes are imposed after” market outcomes are known, with “taxes [being] voted mostly by those who think they have drawn the blanks.” Id. at 163. He states that he would have no objection if one generation voted the tax schedules that were to apply on this ground to as yet unborn generations, although he posits that the resulting rate structure would be much less graduated. Id. 83. Block has noted a long set of issues on which Friedman and libertarians disagree. See Walter Block, Milton Friedman RIP, MISES DAILY (Nov. 16, 2006), http://mises.org/daily/2393. He also has published correspondence in which Friedman good- humoredly called him “a fanatic, not . . . a reasonable man.” Walter Block, Fanatical, Not Reasonable: A Short Correspondence Between Walter Block and Milton Friedman, 20 J. LIBERTARIAN STUD. 61, 61 (2006). 84. SIMONS, Political Credo, supra note 20, at 1. In naming his precursors within the liberal tradition, Simons did not restrict himself to people we would call libertarians. The people he cited included, for example, Adam Smith, John Stuart Mill, John Locke, David Hume, Jeremy Bentham, Alexis de Tocqueville, and his friend (as discussed above) Frie- drich Hayek. Id. 85. Id. at 2. As I discuss below, the full quotation that I excerpted in the text above states that Simons “gives special place to liberty (and nearly coordinate place to equality) as a ‘relatively absolute absolute.’ ” Id. (emphasis added). 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 15

irresistible today as it was forty years ago: to devise a decentral- ized, unpoliticized world in which personal freedom and economic efficiency find wide scope and strong defense.86 Stigler had strong grounds for reaching this conclusion. For ex- ample, Simons was, as Stigler notes, a “violent critic” of New Deal industrial policy legislation such as the National Recovery Act (NRA).87 Nor was he kinder to specific NRA and industrial policy proponents, calling Henry Wallace, Secretary of Agriculture and then-Vice President in the Roosevelt Administration, “our leading advocate of the totalitarian or pre-totalitarian economy of negotiation among tightly organized, monopolizing functional groups.”88 Simons also hated labor unions, saying that “our [most] serious and ominous monopoly problem lies in the labor market and in the power of unions to behave monopolistically.”89 Simons argued that the greatest social and economic ill that the U.S. faced was monopolistic price-fixing, along with “excessive politi- cal interference with relative ,”90 such as through tariffs and industry subsidies. In his view, such interference with market prices was not merely allocatively inefficient (the standard neoclassical claim). Worse still, it was a prime cause of the Great Depression. However, worst of all, in Simons’ view, was the fact that such inter- ference fundamentally violated principles of economic and political freedom and equality, and would lead inexorably to the need for dic- tatorship to mediate the conflicts between organized groups.91 One might almost say here that the case is closed regarding Si- mons’ classical liberal and generally pro-free market credentials, ex- cept for one further consideration. Simons did indeed support a set of policies that involved significant government intervention in the economy. My next topic, therefore, is what to make of what he called his “positive program for laissez faire.”

B. Assessing and Explaining Simons’ “Interventionism” As noted above, one reasonably might expect that a libertarian, or even a generally pro-free market classical liberal, would support

86. Stigler, supra note 13, at 3, 5. In Part III.B, infra, I discuss certain crucial qualifi- cations to Stigler’s view that Simons favored free markets and laissez-faire. 87. See Kitch, supra note 15, at 178. Simons stated, for example, that “[n]o diabolical ingenuity could have devised a more effective agency for retarding or preventing recovery (or for leading us away from democracy) than the National Recovery Act and its codes.” SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 75. 88. Henry C. Simons, For a Free-Market Liberalism, 8 U. CHI. L. REV. 202, 203 (1941). 89. Id. at 205. Simons further discussed his negative view of unions in his article Some Reflections on Syndicalism. See Simons, supra note 9. 90. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 42. 91. See id. at 43-46. 16 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

keeping the government’s economic and regulatory role quite limited. What about Henry Simons? In Positive Program and elsewhere, he called for the “outright dismantling of our gigantic corporations” with a “[l]imitation upon the total amount of property which any single corporation may own.”92 In addition, he favored regulating compa- nies’ financial structure by providing that they could issue only two or three types of securities, centered on a single class of common stock and what we might call plain-vanilla debt.93 Likewise, almost startlingly (or, as Block says, “eerily”94) anticipating the classic 1958 book, The Affluent Society, by the decidedly progressive and anti- laissez-faire economist , Simons condemned advertising for its capacity to manipulate—rather than actually sat- isfying—consumer demand. For this among other reasons, he urged that advertising face heavy taxation.95 Given such features of Simons’ thought, it is unsurprising that Ronald Coase, at a 1983 retrospective session among founders of the Chicago law and economics movement, should find it “difficult to un- derstand” characterizations of the “highly interventionist” Positive Program as pro-free market, adding that he “would be interested if someone could explain this pro-market view of Henry Simons.”96 As Brad DeLong, in telling this story, recounts, “Simons’ former Chicago pupils, his successors as upholders of in econom- ics, did not [respond by] ris[ing] to his defense.”97 Instead, they ad- mitted that “ ‘You can paint him with different colors,’ ” and that “ ‘[i]t’s quite a mixed picture,’ ” to be defended on the ground that, when he wrote in the 1930s, almost everyone else, both at the Uni- versity of Chicago and around the country, was even further to the left.98 Aaron Director, his closest friend in the group attending the

92. Id. at 58-59. 93. See SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 59. 94. Block, supra note 16, at 28. 95. See SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 71-73. Simons complains that “[p]rofits may be obtained either by producing what consumers want or by making con- sumers want what one is actually producing. The possibility of profitably utilizing re- sources to manipulate demand is, perhaps, the greatest source of diseconomy under the existing system.” Id. at 71. 96. Kitch, supra note 15, at 178. Not long after this session, Stigler wrote in his auto- biography that “Simons had preached a form of laissez-faire in . . . A Positive Program for Laissez Faire, but what a form! He proposed nationalization of basic industries such as telephones and railroads because regulation had worked poorly. (I am reminded of the king who was asked to award a prize to the better of two minstrels. After hearing the first, he said, ‘Give the prize to the second.’).” STIGLER, supra note 20, at 148-49. 97. J. Bradford DeLong, In Defense of Henry Simons’ Standing as a Classical Liberal, 9 CATO J. 601, 601 (1990). 98. Id. at 601 (quoting Kitch, supra note 15, at 178 (quoting and George Stigler, respectively)). Thus, Milton Friedman pointed out that, “in 1934 when [Pos- itive Program] appeared, I would say that close to a majority of the social scientists and the 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 17

retrospective, even offered the suggestion that one of Simons’ reasons for expressing support for “interventionist programs was to make the private system of production palatable to his colleagues,”99 as op- posed to actually favoring such programs—as it happens, a sugges- tion that finds some support in Simons’ private correspondence.100 Simons’ old friends may not entirely have remembered, however, the extent to which their own views had changed since the 1930s. Thus, consider Milton Friedman, who recalled viewing Positive Pro- gram as “strongly pro free market in its orientation” when he first read it in the 1930s—only, upon later rereading, to be “astounded at what [he] read.”101 Part of the reason for this change in perspective may have been that Friedman himself had changed in the interim. Friedman, not just in the 1930s but as late as 1947, had been suffi- ciently worried about the corporate monopoly problem to resemble Simons in favoring regulatory restrictions (albeit milder ones) that he hoped would discourage corporate mergers and the existence of large companies.102 Private monopoly, as a potential consequence of corporate size and thus perhaps even its cause, was a major concern to Chicago school economists until empirical work in the 1950s persuaded them of two things. The first was that in private markets pervasively undermines monopoly even if it is briefly established.103 Thus, regula- tory intervention is not needed to combat it. Second, they now con- cluded that the main danger of monopoly “come[s] not from large cor- porations that exploit purely private economies of scale . . . but from interest groups that enter a symbiotic relationship with a govern- ment that purports to ‘regulate’ them.”104 Hence, concern about the private exercise of monopoly power should make one all the more ea- ger to restrict the scope of regulation, since “[w]henever the govern- students in the social sciences at the University of Chicago were either members of the Communist party or very close to it,” and “the general intellectual atmosphere was strong- ly prosocialist.” Kitch, supra note 15, at 178-79. 99. Kitch, supra note 15, at 179. 100. As Sherry Davis Kasper recounts, in response to a letter from Hayek questioning Simons’ proposal for direct government ownership (in lieu of regulation) of natural monopo- lies, Simons wrote: “I may confess privately to having used a low, debating trick. . . . I am willing to prostitute my judgment somewhat, in advocating government ownership, in or- der to vent my spleen fully as to the merits of a grand system of private monopoly with government regulation of prices and wages.” Kasper, supra note 23, at 28. 101. Kitch, supra note 15, at 178. 102. See Van Horn, supra note 60, at 1540. 103. See id. at 1540-43; see also Arnold C. Harberger, Monopoly and Resource Alloca- tion, AM. ECON. REV., May 1954, at 77, 86-87 (suggesting that the deadweight loss result- ing from the exercise of monopoly power was relatively small). 104. DeLong, supra note 97, at 615. 18 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

ment does something, it probably acts in the interest of some power- ful and monopolistic interest group.”105 Given this change in empirical knowledge (or at least belief), DeLong argues that Coase and others were mistaken, in later years, to classify Simons as an interventionist rather than as truly one of them. He merely differed from them empirically, based on the Chica- go school’s state of knowledge about monopoly problems when he was writing, as compared to later. Thus, “Simons was a consistent classi- cal liberal of his times, even if, in retrospect, he may now appear to have been [empirically] wrong in his judgment on specific issues.”106 DeLong concludes that, under Simons’ empirical beliefs concern- ing the monopoly problem (which, again, were standard in Chicago at the time), restricting corporate size so that markets will remain com- petitive is merely “a completion of the idea of the night watchman state. The night watchman state enforces contracts and guards against explicit theft. A monopolist is also an implicit thief because his possession of market power leads to the exchange of commodities at prices that do not reflect underlying social scarcities.”107 Simons makes very much the same point in Positive Program. Re- sponding to laissez-faire’s reputation as “a merely do-nothing policy,” he calls this characterization “unfortunate and misleading. It is an obvious responsibility of the state under [laissez-faire] policy to main- tain the kind of legal and institutional framework within which com- petition can function effectively as an agency of control.”108 In short, breaking up large companies is no more a violation of laissez- faire than enforcing contracts and protecting private property against thieves. The same line of argument could also, perhaps, apply to Simons’ support for heavily taxing advertising. A key complaint he makes about advertising is that, because it is so costly, it “[e]ntrenches mo- nopoly by setting up a financial barrier to the competition of new and small firms.”109 Relatedly, it creates wasteful arms races among firms, which “must spend enormous sums . . . if only to counteract the expenditures of competitors.”110 Thus, even if he adds the Galbraith- style complaint that advertisers manipulate consumers into

105. Id. 106. Id. at 614. 107. Id. at 606. Consistently with this view, Simons defines “commutative justice,” which he distinguishes from “distributive justice” while regarding both as important, as “connot[ing] exchange of equal values, as measured objectively by organized [but competi- tive] markets.” SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 4. Monopoly is indeed theft un- der Simons’ view. 108. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 42. 109. Id. at 72. 110. Id. at 71. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 19

“want[ing] what one is actually producing,”111 which seems to raise broader issues about the welfare effects of market outcomes, one could argue that he is mainly just seeking to advance his anti- monopoly program, while also addressing a collective action problem as between business rivals that leads to waste. As George Stigler later noted, Simons’ hostile view of advertising was widely held among economists before the 1960s, when Stigler’s own work on the economics of information made the case for viewing advertising much more benignly, as “an extremely efficient way of conveying much of this information . . . [that] is as essential for com- petitive firms as for monopolies.”112 Thus, in defense of Simons’ standing as a pro-free market classical liberal notwithstanding his view of advertising, one could again argue that the dispute is merely empirical, concerning means rather than ends, and that it is anach- ronistic to judge Simons based on whether he had accepted, in ad- vance, arguments that the Chicago school only made decades later. Nonetheless, his view of advertising does indeed suggest a more ca- pacious sense of market failure, and of the need for government in- tervention, than one might expect from a “laissez-faire” economist. The metaphor of the mere night watchman grows increasingly strained as the list of market failures that the state must address keeps growing. Suppose one nonetheless accepts Simons’ classical liberal and generally pro-free market credentials. How does one square them with his favoring significant redistribution through an income tax that features “drastic progression”113 in its rates? One possibility is to separate the two Henry Simonses as if they were different people. Thus, DeLong “place[s] to one side” Simons’ tax policy views when assessing his classical liberal credentials,114 and George Stigler— sounding less certain than one might have expected—describes these views as “surely independent” of Simons’ other beliefs.115 Simons himself evidently did not thus classify his tax views, how- ever. Indeed, Positive Program treats a set of tax policy recommenda- tions that are largely identical to those in Personal Income Taxa- tion—mainly written by this time, although not yet published—as part and parcel of his libertarian and laissez-faire program. As we will see next, this reflects a commonality of motivation that has pow- erful internal logic, even if it is not at all how people typically parse the issues today.

111. Id. 112. STIGLER, supra note 20, at 164. 113. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 18. 114. DeLong, supra note 97, at 603 n.3. 115. See Stigler, supra note 13, at 4. 20 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

C. Simons’ Support for Progressive Income Taxation In determining why Simons favored “drastic progression,” a natu- ral first stop is Personal Income Taxation, and in particular the first half of its forty-page first chapter. Here Simons evaluates at length various grounds for favoring progressivity, while the second half of the chapter considers tradeoffs to pursuing redistribution (such as effects on efficiency) and the question of what tax and other fiscal instruments might be deployed in its behalf. Unfortunately, the re- sult of this inquiry—unless supplemented by looking at other writ- ings by Simons—is disappointing and even perplexing, potentially creating the false impression that his endorsement of progressivity is so whimsical and seemingly unmotivated that the question of how it might relate to his other economic views is destined to remain myste- rious. Only when one supplements it, in particular by looking at Posi- tive Program and at A Political Credo, which offers a broader account of his political views,116 does the mystery lift to a degree. Simons opens the first chapter of Personal Income Taxation with a harsh attack on tax policy writers who “dissemble” their true under- lying beliefs by “maintain[ing] a pretense of rigorous, objective analy- sis untinctured by mere ethical considerations.”117 These aspiring, but fake, scientists “religiously eschew a few proscribed phrases, clut- ter up title-pages and introductory chapters with pious references to the science of public finance, and then write monumental discourses upon their own prejudices and preconceptions.”118 Whom exactly might Simons mean by this? The answer appears to be: virtually everyone in the then-existing academic literature on tax policy. He starts by mentioning the “doctrine of taxation according to benefit,” under which “[e]ach person may be called upon, as in his dealings with private enterprise, to pay according as he receives.”119 But given the impossibility of measuring different people’s benefit from the provision of public goods, such as national defense and in- ternal security, this “slogan, of course, has little more than emotive content,” and “leads nowhere at all.”120 Next he addresses “[t]he greater part of what has been written about justice in taxation . . . couched in terms of sacrifice. This con- cept, along with ‘ability’ and ‘faculty,’ ” rests ultimately on the con-

116. Simons wrote A Political Credo in 1945, although it was only published posthu- mously “in an endeavor to formulate specifically the political predispositions implicit in his work.” SIMONS, Political Credo, supra note 20, at 1 (editor’s note). 117. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 1. 118. Id. at 2. 119. Id. at 3. 120. Id. at 4. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 21

cept of utility.121 Unfortunately, however, each version of these doc- trines (in Simons’ view) is utter nonsense—unsurprisingly, given how “absurd” and “naïve” he finds all “hedonistic ethics” and welfare eco- nomics (i.e., anything relying on the concept of utility).122 So what if “[m]any professors of economic dialectic still find comfort and intel- lectual satisfaction (and ‘filler’ for courses and textbooks) in the ‘ex- planations’ of hedonism,” and if they “continue to practice a kind of utility therapy and to write their prescriptions for the economist’s millennium in the hedonistic code”?123 Thus, John Stuart Mill’s doctrine of “equal sacrifice—that tax burdens should so be distributed that the same total sacrifice is im- posed upon every individual”—has received “devastating criticism,” in particular from Francis Edgeworth, who “demonstrates conclusive- ly—so far as is possible with such dialectical tools—that equal indi- vidual sacrifice by no means minimizes the total burden” in utility terms, which definitionally is the proper utilitarian aim.124 Yet Edgeworth’s “minimum sacrifice” theory fares no better in Si- mons’ hands. This theory ostensibly supports complete leveling of income, on the ground that everyone has the same utility function, characterized by declining marginal utility of income. Thus, so long as A has even one dollar more than B, equalizing their after-tax in- comes will increase B’s welfare more than it reduces A’s welfare. Si- mons raises numerous objections, however. What about people’s at- tachment to their current levels of income?125 And what about the unproved “assumption that all individuals are, or must be treated as, equally efficient as pleasure machines”?126 Given these absurdities (in Simons’ view), “[w]hat really commends the Edgeworth doctrine to liberal students, of course, is its conclusion—its pseudoscientific statement of the case against inequality.”127 Having thus disposed, at least to his own satisfaction, of what re- mains today the most widely followed ground in the literature for favoring progressive redistribution,128 Simons concludes

121. Id. at 5. 122. Id. at 12. 123. Id. at 14-15. 124. Id. at 6. 125. Id. at 8-10. 126. Id. at 11. 127. Id. at 10. 128. I refer here to the claim that people have, or should generally be treated as hav- ing, identical utility functions characterized by declining marginal utility. Edgeworth’s claim that this leads to favoring a 100% tax rate and full equalization of everyone’s after- tax income is generally rejected today due to concern about incentive effects. The literature on optimal income taxation, building on ’ work, generally treats the ques- tion of tax rate design as turning on the tradeoff between Edgeworth’s logic and concern about the incentive effects of positive marginal tax rates. See generally J.A. Mirrlees, An 22 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

his scathing survey of the existing literature by dismissing the work of writers who assert that tax burdens should vary based on “ability” or “faculty.”129 This standard is “totally ambiguous,” and thus not even to be described as a “principle” except in scare quotes. Given that “ability or faculty . . . cannot be conceived quantitatively or de- fined in terms of any procedure of measurement,” their use “indicates that the writer prefers the kind of taxation which he prefers; that he is unwilling to reveal his tastes or examine them critically; and that he finds useful in his profession a basic ‘principle’ from which, as from a conjuror’s hat, anything may be drawn at will.”130 This brings us near the end of Simons’ almost wholly destructive survey in Personal Income Taxation of why one might favor a pro- gressive tax system. What does he propose to do instead? In a word, he proposes simply to be forthright about his own priors and preju- dices. Then comes what is probably the most famous sentence in Per- sonal Income Taxation, other than the income definition: “The case for drastic progression in taxation must be rested on the case against inequality—on the ethical or aesthetic judgment that the prevailing distribution of wealth and income reveals a degree (and/or kind) of ine- quality which is distinctly evil or unlovely.”131 And with that said, Si- mons moves on to discussing tradeoffs and methods of implementation. Reading Personal Income Taxation all by itself can make it seem natural to conclude that Simons’ aversion to inequality—and his con- sequent support for “drastic progression”—is a mere isolated preju- dice or sentiment that he sees no need to explain. We have the biases we have, he suggests, so all we can do is acknowledge them and move on, as distinct from reasoning or arguing about them.132 And if that is so, then there might perhaps also be no point in seeking to relate this particular sentiment to anything else that Simons believes, given the lack of any broader discussion of his views in Personal Income Taxa- tion. And while careful readers may have observed that Chapter One has a footnote at the start, stating that one’s tax policy views are “properly a derivative, or subordinate part, of a broader position on general questions of economic policy,” as to which (for Simons’ views) readers are encouraged to consult Positive Program,133 this precedes

Exploration in the Theory of Optimum Income Taxation, 38 REV. ECON. STUD. 175 (1971). 129. Simons finds a kind word for the “so-called sociopolitical theory of [the German writer] Adolph Wagner.” SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 15. Wagner is praised, how- ever, for saying that one needs a prior view as to the proper distribution of income in order to support any particular theory. Thus, “[h]is views (if we pursue them no farther) seem eminently sensible and represent sound criticism of other writers.” Id. 130. Id. at 17. 131. Id. at 18-19. 132. See id. at 2. 133. Id. at 2 n.1. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 23

the famous “unlovely” statement by a full sixteen pages and thus is easy to miss. As it happens, the words “evil” and “unlovely” are in fact derived from Positive Program, where Simons states the following: Turning now to questions of justice, of equitable distribution, we may suggest that equitable distribution is at least as important with respect to power as with reference to economic goods or in- come . . . . Surely there is something unlovely, to modern as against medieval minds, about marked inequality of either kind. A substantial measure of inequality may be unavoidable or essential for motivation; but it should be recognized as evil and tolerated on- ly so far as the dictates of expediency are clear.134 This still does not offer an underlying rationale for Simons’ dislike of inequality. It does, however, reveal the core of what his support for laissez-faire has in common with his tax policy views. Both political power and economic wealth, in his view, should be distributed more equally, rather than less equally, albeit subject to “dictates of expedi- ency” to the contrary.135 With respect to political power, this means having a limited government that leaves alone relative prices and the allocation of capital between industries. With respect to economic power, it calls for redistribution through the income tax. Positive Program’s reference to “unloveliness” comes right after a sustained denunciation, first of centralized economic planning as leading inexorably to dictatorship, and then of private monopoly power as equally odious and dangerous.136 Simons has the same re- vulsion for state actors wielding centralized authority to tell us what to do—the case of unequal political power—as he does for princes liv- ing it up in their castles while paupers starve—the case, in his view, of unequal economic power. Elsewhere in Positive Program and Political Credo, Simons ex- presses more of the same vision. Thus, to offer a full quote that I se- lectively edited above, he says that classical liberalism “gives special place to liberty (and nearly coordinate place to equality) as a ‘relative- ly absolute absolute.’ ”137 These two values are linked, however, by the difficulty of having either one without the other. “Freedom with- out power, like power without freedom, has no substance or mean- ing.”138 And this presumably applies to no less than to political freedom, given Simons’ habit of linking the two. In Si- mons’ view, therefore, an economically unequal society, even if re-

134. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 51-52 (emphases added). 135. See id. 136. See generally id. at 40-51. 137. SIMONS, Political Credo, supra note 20, at 2 (emphasis added). 138. Id. at 6. 24 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

flecting free market outcomes rather than the exercise of government or private monopoly power, is one in which the worst-off people are not entirely free. This is a horizontal, or even a leveling, vision of both economic and political power. Simons does not like plutocrats rising far above the peasants (even if the latter, as a formal legal matter, are entirely free), any more than he likes Washington bureaucrats telling private economic actors what to do. Is this “liberal” in the classical sense? That depends on how one defines the tradition. In any event, howev- er, emotionally no less than intellectually, it is certainly no Ayn Rand or Paul Ryan version of the laissez-faire creed. Simons does not yearn for a world in which the great are permitted to thrive, but for one in which the small do not have anyone too far above them, either politi- cally or economically.139 In this regard, Sherry Davis Kasper makes an important point about the difference between Simons’ intellectual background and that of his successors in the Chicago school. She notes that he, like other economists who received their training between the two World Wars, was influenced by the immediately preceding era’s Gilded Age economists, for whom “the primary problem . . . [was] the concentra- tion of economic wealth and power and the accompanying inequality it engendered.”140 She later adds that Simons “worked in the climate of interwar pluralism. As a result, he looked through the world with a different set of lenses, colored primarily by elements of progressive social science that the pluralism of interwar economics allowed to linger.”141 Only, Simons amalgamated these classic Gilded Age and interwar concerns of economic power with a commonly motivated dis- like of centralized political power that his successors would hold without retaining the Gilded Age element. One last point worth noting here concerns how Simons’ views about economic and political power cohered to make a comprehensive income tax so attractive to him. One of its greatest virtues, in his view, was that, insofar as it treated all different types of income neu- trally, it avoided engaging in selective economic regulation—the great vice, along with regressivity, that he ascribed to the tariffs and excise duties that were still a key U.S. federal revenue source when he wrote and published Personal Income Taxation. Taxing all income as alike as possible keeps the government out of the price-fixing and resource allocation business, thus preserving free market conditions

139. See id. at 23 (“A cardinal tenet of libertarians is that no one may be trusted with much power—no leader, no faction, no party, no ‘class,’ no majority, no government, no church, no corporation, no trade association, no labor union, no grange, no professional association, no university, no large organization of any kind.”). 140. Kasper, supra note 23, at 5. 141. Id. at 28. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 25

and limiting centralized political power, even if people face very high tax rates.

IV. SIMONS ON THE INCOME TAX With Simons’ general philosophical commitments and motivations better in focus, I turn now to his work on income taxation and will focus on why, and to what extent, he preferred income taxation to consumption taxation. After discussing his main arguments and con- clusions, along with the separate issue of the degree to which he ac- tually favored an income tax in practice, I will ask what has changed since he wrote and how that might affect the views that one who shared his intellectual commitments would hold today.

A. Income Taxation Versus Consumption Taxation

1. Why Did Simons Prefer the Income Tax? For a number of decades, the leading big-picture issue in U.S. ac- ademic debate about tax policy has been whether the federal income tax should be replaced by an individual-level consumption tax that, like the income tax, has graduated rates. Experts’ awareness that one can levy a consumption tax at the individual level—as distinct from, say, a retail sales tax or value-added tax model, in which busi- nesses’ role in collecting the tax impedes applying varying individual rates—often is thought to date from no earlier than 1955, when the British economist Nicholas Kaldor published a book advocating - flow taxation of individuals,142 or perhaps even 1974, when Har- vard law professor William Andrews published a classic article on the subject.143 It thus may come as a surprise to see Simons addressing this very topic at length, in both Personal Income Taxation and Federal Tax Reform. This, however, turns out to reflect two antecedents. The first is economist ’s advocacy of a progressive consumption tax, to which Simons responded at some length—and, by his acerbic standards, quite respectfully—in Personal Income Taxation. The sec- ond, less well-known today, although cited by both Simons and Fish- er, is an actual legislative proposal for a cash-flow tax, which Con- gressman Ogden Mills introduced in 1921 and wrote about in the Na- tional Tax Journal.144 This was essentially a Kaldor- or Andrews- style cash-flow consumption tax avant la lettre. It involved replacing the existing income tax with a tax on people’s consumer expenditures

142. See generally NICHOLAS KALDOR, AN EXPENDITURE TAX (1955). 143. See generally William D. Andrews, A Consumption-Type or Cash Flow Personal Income Tax, 87 HARV. L. REV. 1113 (1974). 144. Ogden L. Mills, The Spendings Tax, 7 NAT’L TAX ASS’N BULL. 18 (1921). 26 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

during the year, which it would have computed by requiring taxpay- ers to report on the following information: (1) Cash or equivalent assets on hand at the beginning of the taxable year ; (2) Total receipts including amounts borrowed ; (3) The amounts of the items exempt from taxation [i.e., deduct- ible], including investments ; (4) Cash or equivalent assets at the close of the taxable year.145 With Ogden Mills’ proposal retaining its status as a known though untested alternative as of the late 1930s, debate concerning its mer- its took on an odd form. Based on an argument that went back at least to John Stuart Mill,146 Fisher asserted that such a tax not only was both feasible and desirable, but was actually the true form of an “income tax.” In Fisher’s view, an income tax, as conventionally de- fined to include both consumption and returns to saving, involves the “fallacy of double counting,” because it applies twice to assets’ capi- talized value—first when they are received, and then again when they generate annual consumption or cash returns. “[S]avings may be invested in land or in confectionery. The only true income is the use of the land or the use of the confectionery. To include also the value of the land or the value of the confectionary is to count as in- come the capitalization of income.”147 Thus, taxing returns to saving was not merely a bad policy idea (although it might be that as well, if it reduced saving). In addition, Fisher viewed it as actively fallacious, reflecting the “confusions”148 promulgated by sloppy writers. Simons’ response to Fisher is partly semantic, reflecting the char- acter of Fisher’s own argument. He calls his disagreement with Fish- er “essentially one of terminology rather than of logic.”149 While the question of how to define a given term is “only that of choice among verbal symbols . . . , it seems a hardly debatable proposition that us- age is already too firmly established to permit our accepting Fisher’s proposal”150 regarding what “income” actually means. “His proposal comes all too tardily in the history of our language; and his pleas

145. Id. at 19-20. Items that were effectively deductible included not only most invest- ment outlays, but also ordinary and necessary business expenses, other taxes paid, chari- table gifts, amounts paid for medical and dental services, and funeral expenses. Id. at 19. For examples that mention the Mills bill, see Irving Fisher, The Double Taxation of Sav- ings, 29 AM. ECON. REV. 16, 16-17 (1939), and SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 226. 146. See John Stuart Mill, PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY bk. V, ch. 2, § 4 (Donald Winch ed., Pelican Books 1970) (1848), quoted in Fisher, supra note 145, at 16 (arguing that “[u]nless . . . savings are exempted from income-tax, the contributors are twice taxed on what they save”). 147. IRVING FISHER, THE NATURE OF CAPITAL AND INCOME 108-09 (1906). 148. Id. at 107. 149. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 89. 150. Id. at 98. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 27

have been, and must be, without effect upon our courts, legislatures, accountants, and men of affairs—not to mention the economists.”151 The disagreement was not just semantic, however. Simons was fundamentally unsympathetic to the line of thought that had led Fisher down his semantic blind alley. As Simons notes, the real intel- lectual value of Fisher’s work on income and capital lay in his devel- opment of time-preference theory, which treats saving as merely de- ferred consumption.152 Once one accepts this view of saving, it be- comes clear that taxing returns to saving means that future con- sumption is being taxed at a higher rate than current consumption (all else equal), which may appear unmotivated. And if it is unmoti- vated, one may conclude that consumption is a better tax base than income, resulting not just in less economic distortion but also in bet- ter measurement of people’s relative “ability” or “ability to pay.”153 Simons, however, believed that “there is something sadly inade- quate about the idea of saving as [merely] postponed consumption.”154 “Many people save mainly because it is the thing to do, because it is expected of them.”155 And—echoing his denunciation of utility-based theories in other contexts—“[t]o assert that considerations of utility determine the allocation of consumption funds [over time] explains nothing at all but merely says, with egregious extravagance of lan- guage, that people consume what they consume.”156 Accordingly, in his view, two people with the same income make a better horizontal comparison than two people with the same consumption, and the former pair is thus the one whose members should presumptively be equated through the choice of tax base.157

151. Id. (footnote omitted). 152. See id. at 95. 153. See, e.g., DAVID F. BRADFORD & U.S. TREASURY TAX POLICY STAFF, BLUEPRINTS FOR BASIC TAX REFORM 2, 37 (2d rev. ed. 1984); Joseph Bankman & David A. Weisbach, The Superiority of an Ideal Consumption Tax Over an Ideal Income Tax, 58 STAN. L. REV. 1413 (2006). 154. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 97. 155. Id. at 96-97. 156. Id. at 95. Although perhaps not germane here, I have explained elsewhere why I regard Simons’ position on this issue, which is commonly expressed to this day, as itself fallacious. The value of wealth lies in the fact that it can be used to buy things. According- ly, under a perpetual flat rate consumption tax, one has already borne the full burden of the tax with respect to one’s unconsumed wealth. The fact that it can be spent is what gives it value. “Wealth is worth only what it can buy; otherwise, it might as well be play money from the board games Monopoly or Life.” Daniel N. Shaviro, Replacing the Income Tax With a Progressive Consumption Tax, 103 TAX NOTES 91, 105 (2004). Treating saving as deferred consumption therefore correctly reflects the fact that we have no particular reason to think savers are better off on a lifetime basis than consumers, unless we mean to rely on specific empirical theories regarding people’s behavior and welfare. 157. Under a view of saving as deferred consumption, if A and B earn the same wage this year and the tax base is consumption (with a perpetual flat rate), they pay the same taxes, in present value over the long run, even if this year one of them consumes less and 28 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

As a matter of logic, then, Simons preferred income taxation to consumption taxation. Perhaps the most important motivation, how- ever, lay in his underlying distributional concerns. Because economic income includes, not just current year consumption, but also the amount of any increase in the market value of one’s assets during the year, it offers a “more inclusive measure of economic power”158 than does consumption. And economic power was the very thing that he wanted the tax system to equalize. So what, he argued, if—as he ex- pressly agreed—to save the preponderance of a large income was “moral[ly] superior[]” to engaging in “vulgar and tasteless ostentation in private consumption”?159 While “[o]ur private sentiments may properly distinguish between better and worse uses of great economic power,”160 tax policy should take no heed of the difference. [T]here is an urgent social and political problem of preventing ex- cessive and persisting inequality of power. . . . [T]hese distinctions should not blind us to the need for mitigating inequality or to the danger that our efforts in this direction will miscarry if we attempt to differentiate greatly among persons according to the way in which they use their power.”161 A last reason for Simons’ preferring the income tax to Fisher’s and Ogden Mills’ spendings (i.e., progressive consumption) tax was ad- ministrative. The income tax was in current use and working reason- ably well, albeit susceptible to significant improvement. “Fisher is urging us to abandon the best part of an established revenue system and to start anew with an untried form of personal tax.”162 Departing radically from existing (and income-based) business accounting and creating a need, among other challenges, to measure taxpayers’ dissaving (such as from borrowing) was asking for trouble and might prove unworkable.163 What is more, while Simons understood that the spendings tax could achieve “the same degree of progression that we now have, or the same amount of taxes on persons of great wealth,” this might require imposing high-end marginal tax rates as high as 1000%.164 This seemed likely to be politically unfeasible and would, in any event, increase compliance problems.165 saves more. Thus, support for consumption taxation does not rely on the claim that two people who consume the same amount this year should bear the same tax burden, even if one of them has greater savings. 158. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 229. 159. Id. 160. Id. 161. Id. 162. Id. at 226. 163. See id. at 227-28. 164. Id. at 230. 165. Id. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 29

In sum, the picture so far appears clear. Simons was on the in- come tax side of the long-standing debate and seemingly considered it important to tax wealth-holders on their returns to saving. The case is apparently closed, and with a conclusion as unsurprising as that in the banal headline “Dog Bites Man.” Surely everyone in the tax community who has heard of Simons already knew that he was a strong income tax proponent. A surprise emerges, however, when one turns to the details of his tax reform views. Simons was actually quite comfortable with letting savers defer their income tax liabilities without penalty, so long as the deferral was not potentially permanent, and thereby embraced an end result that looks very similar to that under consumption taxa- tion, so long as one specifies (as he did) that making gifts and be- quests is itself a form of consumption. I show this next by examining how he dealt with the realization requirement, under which gain and loss are not taxed prior to the occurrence of a realization event, such as an asset sale.

2. Simons’ View of Realization and Deferral As Simons well understood, an income tax in name may not func- tion much like one in practice if taxpayers can take sufficient ad- vantage of a realization-based system. Current law, for example, might permit a “very wealthy diversifying ‘operator’ . . . [to] show lit- tle or no taxable income at all, while living like a king and steadily increasing his net worth.”166 All that this required was selectively re- alizing losses and not gains, while borrowing as needed to fund cur- rent consumption. The deferred tax liability would then disappear at death, given the allowance at that point of a tax-free step-up in basis.167 While realization can turn the income tax into something that functions more like a consumption tax, in the above scenario we do not even have that. Blocking exploitation of the scenario may there- fore be crucial to the effectiveness of the income tax (in name) as ei- ther a true income tax or an effective consumption tax, so far as high- end progressivity is concerned. And if one prefers the income tax ap- proach, as Simons emphasized that he did, one might be expected to emphasize as well the importance of limiting the deferral, not just the permanent elimination, of the tax on unrealized gain. Our priors here might therefore lead us to predict that Simons would want to address and limit taxpayers’ use of realization for deferral, and not just for permanent elimination of gain. This, however, is not at all what we find when we look closely at Personal Income Taxation and Federal Tax Reform.

166. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 62. 167. Id. 30 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

Simons is remembered as a foe of realization doctrine for several reasons. One is that the Haig-Simons income definition gives realiza- tion absolutely no place. Changes in the market value of one’s assets are economic income, as the definition makes clear, whether one sells the assets or not. Simons also notably called financial accounting’s reliance on realization a “professional conspiracy against truth,” albe- it one that might be expedient “in a world of corruptible accountants and optimistic directors.”168 And he famously executed a brutally ef- fective intellectual takedown169 of Edwin R. A. Seligman of Columbia University for incoherently arguing that realization is a conceptually necessary component of income.170 Seligman was Simons’ elder by thirty-eight years and arguably had been the preeminent U.S. tax economist since before Simons was born.171

168. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 81. 169. See id. at 85-88. Simons’ critique of Seligman is remarkably sarcastic and dis- missive. Seligman assumes what he needs to in order to supply the end result he wants, “then moves merrily to his conclusion.” Id. at 85. “[H]e has evidently no misgivings as to the finality of his [in Simons’ view, ad hoc and incoherent] contribution.” Id. He starts by defining income as consumption, but “[b]efore long . . . income becomes something more familiar—savings being slipped in quite unceremoniously.” Id. At one point in Seligman’s argument, “income” depends on value, but soon enough this “ceases to be true.” Id. at 86. A periodicity requirement for income is “essential” at two points in Seligman’s argument, but at another point “is excluded utterly.” Id. “Seligman’s differentiation between the growth of a herd and the growth of a forest is one of the less obscure features of his argument.” Id. Later on, “[i]ncome depends on the number of trees cut—but only provided they do not cut too many!” Id. at 87. “After an extended parade of dogmatic assertions—put forward as necessities of logic—the author [adds yet another extraneous argument] . . . rather casual- ly.” Id. “Professor Seligman’s insistence both upon ‘realization’ and upon depreciation de- ductions seems to involve serious logical difficulties.” Id. at 88. “Of course, it goes without saying that, after dragging in an amazing variety of income concepts and choosing useful attributes from different ones at will, Seligman finds little difficulty in throwing out an item like stock dividends, which was almost defenseless from the start.” Id. 170. The Seligman article to which Simons gave this harsh treatment was Edwin R.A. Seligman, Are Stock Dividends Income?, 9 AM. ECON. REV. 517 (1919), from which the opin- ion of the Supreme Court in Eisner v. Macomber, 252 U.S. 189 (1920), holding that stock dividends cannot constitutionally be taxed because they fail a realization prerequisite for finding taxable income, had largely been cribbed. Simons was not the only tax academic to be unimpressed by Seligman’s analysis. See, e.g., Robert Murray Haig, The Concept of In- come—Economic and Legal Aspects, in THE FEDERAL INCOME TAX 1 (Robert Murray Haig ed., 1921) (describing cases such as Eisner as “leading toward a definition of income so narrow and artificial as to bring about results which from the economic point of view are certainly eccentric and in certain cases little less than absurd”); Paul H. Wueller, Concepts of Taxable Income II, 53 POL. SCI. Q. 557, 564 (1938) (Seligman’s “concepts of income are, in the last analysis, but philological derivatives—without acknowledged social purpose.”). 171. Seligman was born in 1861, started at Columbia in 1885, published two major books on taxation in the 1890s, was the president of the American Economic Association from 1902 through 1904, and became a chaired Professor of Political Economy at Columbia in 1904. He then continued publish regularly through 1932. See Ajay K. Mehrotra, Edwin R.A. Seligman and the Beginnings of the U.S. Income Tax, 109 TAX NOTES 933, 936-38 (2005). Simons clearly saw no need to pull punches with an eminent senior member of his field, whose influence he obviously thought had lasted long enough. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 31

In practice, however, Simons was comfortable with taxpayers’ use of realization accounting to defer gain. It is not just that he consid- ered realization “indispensable to a feasible income-tax system”172 and opposed departing from it selectively even where this was most feasible, such as under an early proposal to require annual mark-to- market accounting for publicly traded securities.173 What is more, he considered realization “relatively unobjectionable in principle where it results only in postponement of assessment” rather than its per- manent elimination.174 Annual accrual of gain, while “implied by the underlying definition of income . . . is quite unnecessary to effective application of that definition.”175 He even called the argument that income must be allocated to the right period, in order to eliminate the “interest saving” from deferral, “this mosquito argument,” at which he had “several times swatted . . . [and] must now swat once more, [albeit] not to kill the pest.”176 Part of the reason for Simons’ impatience with arguments that income must be allocated to the right period, rather than being de- ferred under the realization rule, was simply his general conviction that the best should not be the enemy of the good. A reasonably well- functioning system should be considered entirely acceptable, even if along the way it posed insoluble (or, in his words, “hopeless”) dilem- mas that could only be given “arbitrary” solutions.177 However, he did not consider the time value of deferral—in an era when interest rates were low, by the standards of more recent decades—as merely some- thing that one would like to eliminate, but that in practice was too small to worry about. Instead, in many circumstances he was actual- ly affirmatively reluctant to deny it to taxpayers. Simons recognized, for example, that “long postponement of tax payment” can have a significant “interest cost to the Treasury.”178 Nonetheless, allowing such postponement to businesses would yield “some gains, even to the Treasury, in allowing capital so to ‘fructify.’ The interest loss seems a moderate price to pay, not only for simple tax procedure but also for stimulation of new enterprise and venture- some investment . . . .”179 Indeed, there was “very much to be said for not forcing unproved enterprises to deplete their reinvestable earn- ings or reserves by forcing them to pay taxes,” even indirectly via a

172. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 162. 173. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 74. 174. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 162. 175. Id. at 208. 176. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 127. 177. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 53-54 (discussing problems of imputed income and of drawing a firm boundary between business expenses and personal consumption). 178. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 127. 179. Id. 32 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

shareholder-level tax that would lead to increased dividend pay- outs.180 Simons argued that this “scheme really does derive sound support from much the same argument which Professor Fisher has used, persuasively but (I think) improperly, to condemn the income tax.”181 This perspective, under which the mere deferral of gain was unob- jectionable so long as it did not turn into permanent exclusion, per- vasively influences Simons’ actual reform proposals. As Aaron Direc- tor noted in his introduction to the posthumously published Federal Tax Reform, Simons’ “great contribution” to income tax thinking was to propose what he called “constructive realization.”182 Under this ap- proach, “[e]very transfer of property by gift, inheritance or bequest [w]ould be treated as a realization, at the estimated fair market val- ue, by the donor or by the deceased owner’s estate.”183 This tax would be levied in addition to treating gifts as taxable income to the donee while retaining their non-deductibility by the donor—a result that Simons defended on the ground that gifts constituted consumption by both parties.184 So long as constructive realization guaranteed a final accounting when the taxpayer ceased to own appreciated property, Simons not only could tolerate, but affirmatively supported, eliminating the cor- porate tax.185 The fact that corporate shareholders could thereby earn income that was free of any current tax was not a problem, so long as there was corporate-level dividend withholding plus a guarantee that any transfer of the underlying stock, including by gift or bequest, would be treated as a realization by the shareholder, with the gain being taxed at the ordinary income rate (and preferably subject to averaging, so taxpayers would not be adversely affected by the “bunching” problem if annual rates were steeply graduated).186 How could Simons be so casual, ambivalent, and even self- contradictory regarding whether income’s broader tax base than con- sumption (as he saw it) was actually reached in practice? The answer probably goes back to his underlying motivation for viewing tax re- form as a vital part of his “laissez-faire program.” At the time when

180. Id. at 128. 181. Id. 182. Id. at vii. 183. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 167. 184. See id. at 57-58. Simons dismissed the critique that this would result in double- counting on the ground that this critique “implies . . . the familiar, and disastrous, miscon- ception that personal income is merely a share in some undistributed, separately measura- ble whole.” Id. at 58. He further argued that a gift exclusion unwisely “distinguish[es] among an individual’s receipts according to the intentions of second parties.” Id. at 57. 185. See, e.g., SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 16, 23, 40. 186. Id. at 40, 44. 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 33

he wrote, the U.S. income tax contributed less than 10% of all federal revenues,187 with the rest coming from tariffs and excise taxes that he abhorred as both anti-free market and regressive. Replacing them with a broad-based and relatively neutral levy that reflected individ- uals’ overall personal circumstances was the big thing, with the exact details being considerably less important. What is more, Si- mons’ broader macroeconomic (and his experience of the Great Depression) appear to have encouraged him to focus more on savings and growth, as opposed to just internal tax policy analysis, than if he had been purely a tax scholar, and one who lived in less interesting times.

3. What Might Simons Think Today About the Choice Between Income and Consumption Taxation? Given Simons’ surprising degree of comfort with employing an in- come tax by name that, in practice, often followed timing rules that were at least as favorable to taxpayers as those under a consumption tax, it is natural to ask, if only out of curiosity or as a kind of parlor game, what he might think about the choice of tax base today. Or more precisely, without speculating about such imponderable ques- tions as whether he would have been swayed by intellectual devel- opments and fashions in the field that he never lived to see, one can ask what, given his views, he might have made of our many subse- quent decades of practical experience. Overall, I see two reasons why he might have been more fervently pro-income tax in practice today than he was back then, and two reasons why he might have shifted to favoring a progressive consumption tax.

(a) More Pro-Income Tax? (1) Importance of timing. The first reason why Simons might have become more eager to impose a true income tax, in the sense of limit- ing interest-free deferral, is that the decades since he published Per- sonal Income Taxation and Federal Tax Reform have taught us how much timing matters. Perhaps this is simply because we have fre- quently lived with higher interest rates than those of his era, and thus have gotten to observe how pervasively timing issues can domi- nate income tax practice and lead to economic distortions.188 As Wil- liam Andrews put it, we have learned that realization is often the

187. SIMONS, TAXATION, supra note 1, at 39. 188. On the other hand, with today’s generally lower tax rates than those in the 1930s, the distinction between pre-tax and after-tax rates of return may be narrower. One way of describing the key advantage of deferral is that it enables one to enjoy returns to saving at the pre-tax rather than the after-tax rate of return. 34 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

“Achilles’ heel” of the income tax,189 and not just because Simons’ constructive realization approach has never been adopted. Today, income tax proponents generally recognize that it is quite important to their goals that deferral issues be addressed more aggressively than he thought was necessary. Thus, for example, few would argue today that we can simply eliminate the corporate income tax while still imposing such a tax at the individual level, serene in the knowledge that a given shareholder’s slice of corporate income might often fail to be taxed before that shareholder died. (2) Greatly increased high-end inequality. Over the last thirty years, high-end income inequality in the U.S. has vastly increased. Between 1986 and 2008, for example, under one relevant measure the share of national income earned by the top 1% of the income dis- tribution almost doubled, while the income share of the top 0.01% more than tripled.190 Unsurprisingly, and as Simons would have predicted, increased economic inequality has affected the distribution of political power. In the last few years, we have seen the greatest and most sustained collapse of employment levels since the Great Depression prompt startlingly little concern from Washington policymakers. Instead, the concern of people in business and finance about forestalling even the remotest threat of modest appears to matter a lot more po- litically. Likewise, consider the spectacle in the 2012 presidential campaign of billionaire donors, set free from campaign finance re- strictions by the Supreme Court’s Citizens United decision,191 giving millions of dollars to support their favored candidates and causes in apparent exchange for access and at least hoped-for influence. It is not just anachronistic projection to posit that all this would have disgusted, and even enraged, the Henry Simons who wrote in the 1930s and 1940s. He viewed concentrated economic and political power as ugly and offensive, and he thought no group, profession, or class should be allowed too much superiority or sway in either realm. Thus, he presumably would have wanted to take strong measures to address high-end inequality. At least when he wrote, the income tax, along with the estate and gift tax, was the main policy tool that he considered suitable for this purpose. His concern that a spendings tax would not be progressive enough in practice, even if in principle it

189. See William D. Andrews, The Achilles’ Heel of the Comprehensive Income Tax, in NEW DIRECTIONS IN FEDERAL TAX POLICY FOR THE 1980S, at 278 (Charles E. Walker & Mark A. Bloomfield eds., 1983). 190. See Daniel N. Shaviro, 1986-Style Tax Reform: A Good Idea Whose Time Has Passed, 131 TAX NOTES 817, 834 (2011) (summarizing research by Facundo Alvaredo, Tony Atkinson, Thomas Piketty, and Emmanuel Saez). 191. Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 558 U.S. 310, 365-66 (2010). 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 35

could be, would surely have remained relevant to his analysis of the choice of policy tool.

(b) Potentially Pro-Consumption Tax? (1) Political difficulty of addressing inter-asset distortions. I posit- ed above that the clearly demonstrated importance of timing issues over the last few decades might have motivated Simons to support fuller implementation of a true Haig-Simons income tax. It also is possible, however, that it would move him in the opposite direction, by demonstrating that the income tax could not be as politically pure and economically neutral as he had fondly hoped. Even by the early 1940s, he was worrying that the federal income tax “reads less and less like a prescription of taxes on persons according to their in- comes, and more and more like an inventory of miscellaneous dispen- sations” to well-connected interest groups.192 This introduction of “in rem elements,” like those in excise taxes, was an instance of “con- cealed democratic corruption,” exemplified at the time by the oil depletion allowance.193 Simons favored tax policy transparency194 and might reasonably have concluded (as others have) that an income tax inherently lacks this virtue with respect to cost-recovery methods that are neutral be- tween assets or industries. By contrast, in a cash-flow tax that ap- plies to businesses (whether incorporated or not) as well as directly to individuals, expensing achieves inter-asset neutrality by relatively simple and transparent means. He thus might reasonably have asked himself the question of whether shifting to a cash-flow consumption tax might lead to greater neutrality and transparency, thereby reduc- ing industry groups’ capacity to hijack economic and regulatory poli- cy. As I have argued elsewhere,195 it is far from certain that shifting to a cash-flow consumption tax would actually improve political out- comes, but the possibility that it would (by reason of uniform expens- ing’s simplicity) would certainly have merited Simons’ consideration. (2) Administrative complexity of the income tax. A second reason why Simons might consider giving up on the income tax, if he saw where we are today, concerns its tax planning, compliance, and ad- ministrative costs. The baroque complexities of modern practice, founded in large part on realization problems that matter much more

192. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 96. 193. Id. 194. See id. at 4-5. 195. See, e.g., Daniel Shaviro, Simplifying Assumptions: How Might the Politics of Con- sumption Tax Reform Affect (Impair) the End Product?, in FUNDAMENTAL TAX REFORM: ISSUES, CHOICES, AND IMPLICATIONS 75, 75-76 (John W. Diamond & George R. Zodrow eds., 2008). 36 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

than he had anticipated given the frequent existence of higher inter- est rates (along with the continuing non-adoption of his constructive realization idea), might conceivably move him to consider progressive consumption tax prototypes, even though they remain largely untested. One set of issues that Simons did not and could not have fully an- ticipated in the 1930s concerns the extraordinary growth, since that era, of aggressive tax sheltering transactions and legal responses thereto, the latter involving both expansive judicial doctrines196 and detailed statutory enactments.197 A second set of issues that he did anticipate, but that arguably has grown worse, concerns entity-level corporate income taxation, which most analysts now agree (contrary to his view) is necessary if one taxes income rather than consumption at the individual level. Simons detested the impact of income tax con- siderations on companies’ business planning and also on their finan- cial structure. His Federal Tax Reform emphasizes the undesirability of the corporate income tax system’s bias in favor of debt over equi- ty.198 And while debt bias is not inevitable under a corporate income tax, as decades of diverse “corporate integration” proposals have shown,199 the very fact that none have been enacted may add to the appeal of a “Gordian knot” solution, in the form of eliminating the need to tax income at the entity level. International tax considerations arguably weigh in this direction as well. The rise of international business transactions, along with capital flows that facilitate income-shifting for tax purposes in the decades since Simons wrote, may cause longstanding problems with the international tax rules to be ever more damaging to the cause of taxing individuals on the income they earn through corporate enti- ties. With a corporate income tax, in which residence determinations must be made at the entity rather than the individual level, these problems inevitably lack good solutions. 200

196. The economic substance doctrine that lies at the core of judicial responses to ag- gressive tax planning predates the publication of Simons’ Personal Income Taxation. See Gregory v. Helvering, 293 U.S. 465 (1935). However, Gregory concerned not the creation of artificial tax losses, but the use of a tax-free reorganization rule to reduce greatly the tax imposed on a corporate distribution. Id. at 468-70. Simons noted the “awful complexity” of the corporate reorganization rules and attributed it to what he considered the mistake of taxing corporations as if they were natural persons. SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 89-90. 197. Detailed statutory responses to tax sheltering in the current tax code include, for example, the investment interest limitation, the at-risk rules, and the passive loss rules. See I.R.C. §§ 163(d), 465, 469. The economic substance doctrine was also recently codified. See id. § 7701(o). 198. See SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 4, 19, 26. 199. On the variety of leading corporate integration proposals, see, for example, DAN- IEL N. SHAVIRO, DECODING THE U.S. CORPORATE TAX 151-65 (2009). 200. See generally DANIEL N. SHAVIRO, FIXING U.S. INTERNATIONAL TAXATION (2014). 2013] THE FORGOTTEN HENRY SIMONS 37

While income taxation surely looks worse administratively than it did when Simons was writing, progressive consumption taxation looks somewhat better. Ogden Mills’ spendings tax was fairly rudi- mentary in design and in its degree of specification. Its lineal de- scendant, the “Blueprints” cash flow that David Bradford and the U.S. Treasury Tax Policy Staff developed in the 1980s,201 goes consid- erably further in showing how such an approach might work. It also contains a tax rate-smoothing or income averaging feature202 that Simons might conceivably have liked, given his belief that this is im- portant.203 The decades since Simons wrote have also seen the prom- ulgation of an alternative approach to progressive consumption taxa- tion: Bradford’s X-tax, which builds administratively on the rise (since the 1950s) of value-added taxes that tax consumption relative- ly simply and efficiently through broad-based taxes that are collected at the company level.204 While these progressive consumption tax models remain largely untested, clearly the consumption tax side of the administrability debate has gained ground today relative to when Simons was writing. Obviously, one cannot, in the end, really say what Simons would think today about the choice of tax base if he were miraculously re- vived and apprised of the last few decades’ main developments. He surely would, however, be disappointed by the trajectory of the in- come tax in recent decades. It thus is plausible that he would be open to considering whether a progressive consumption tax could both do much better administratively and sufficiently match the actual pro- gressivity of the existing income tax. If one had a definite answer to these questions, not only Simons’ choice, but also ours, would likely be a lot easier and clearer.

V. CONCLUSION The Henry Simons who called himself an “extreme conservative” and foe of economic regulation, and the Henry Simons who favored “drastic progression” in the income tax, were one and the same intel- lectually, not just biologically. They shared a dislike for concentrated economic and political power, and a view of liberty and equality as not just comparably important, but also highly interdependent in practice. In his view, unlike that of many of today’s libertarians and

201. See BRADFORD & U.S. TREASURY TAX POLICY STAFF, supra note 153. 202. See id. at 44. 203. See SIMONS, REFORM, supra note 2, at 40, 127. 204. The X-tax combines a value-added tax with allowing businesses to deduct wages, which are taxed to workers under a progressive rate structure. See ROBERT CARROLL & ALAN D. VIARD, PROGRESSIVE CONSUMPTION TAXATION: THE X TAX REVISITED (2012); Da- vid F. Bradford, The X Tax in the World Economy (Nat’l Bureau Econ. Research, Working Paper No. w10676, 2004). 38 FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 41:1

free market advocates, a plutocratic society would be unappealing even if everyone’s legal rights were formally inviolate. It is an inter- esting question—grist for a number of recent studies205—why his con- cern about economic as well as political power, and his view that “[f]reedom without power . . . has no substance or meaning,”206 have faded as much as they have among his successors in the classical liberal tradition. Intellectual history moves inexorably forward, reflecting not just fashion but new information and improved understanding. Thus, to my mind (although others may disagree), neither Simons’ scorn for theories based on utility and/or ability, nor his analysis of the choice between income and consumption taxation, is persuasive today. His hatred of all hierarchies, while appealing to me emotionally, needs a fuller intellectual foundation than he offers. And his broader econom- ic analysis, such as that concerning the dangers of monopoly power, may in some respects be more dated still. Even seventy years down the road, however, much of Simons’ work remains compelling, lucid, and persuasive. This is no small ac- complishment. His brilliance, vehemence, and urgent commitment to improving the world in which he lived helped motivate him to pro- duce, not just a few instances of inspired advocacy, but substantial contributions both to income tax scholarship and to the intellectual and institutional foundations of modern law and economics. I only wish that, in some imaginary place, I could adequately praise and thank him to his face—perhaps over a beer at Hanley’s tavern in the twilight zone as Walter Blum looks on with a benign half-smile, and even Ronald Coase, persuaded at last to accept the value of Simons’ contributions, nods approvingly.

205. See, e.g., DANIEL STEDMAN JONES, MASTERS OF THE UNIVERSE: HAYEK, FRIEDMAN, AND THE BIRTH OF NEOLIBERAL POLITICS (2012); Caldwell, supra note 15; DeLong, supra note 97; Kasper, supra note 23; Van Horn & Mirowski, supra note 15. 206. SIMONS, Positive Program, supra note 8, at 6.