Constantinos Georgiou Athanasopoulos

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Constantinos Georgiou Athanasopoulos Constantinos Athanasopoulos, 1 Constantinos Georgiou Athanasopoulos Supervisor Mary Haight Title The Metaphysics of Intentionality: A Study of Intentionality focused on Sartre's and Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mind and Language. Submission for PhD Department of Philosophy University of Glasgow JULY 1995 ProQuest Number: 13818785 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a com plete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. uest ProQuest 13818785 Published by ProQuest LLC(2018). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States C ode Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. ProQuest LLC. 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106- 1346 GLASGOW UKVERSITT LIBRARY Constantinos Athanasopoulos, 2 ABSTRACT With this Thesis an attempt is made at charting the area of the Metaphysics of Intentionality, based mainly on the Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre. A Philosophical Analysis and an Evaluation o f Sartre’s Arguments are provided, and Sartre’s Theory of Intentionality is supported by recent commentaries on the work of Ludwig Wittgenstein. Sartre’s Theory of Intentionality is proposed, with few improvements by the author, as the only modem theory of the mind that can oppose effectively the advance of AI and physicalist reductivist attempts in Philosophy of Mind and Language. Discussion includes Sartre’s critique of Husserl, the relation of Sartre’s Theory of Intentionality to Realism, its applicability in the Theory of the Emotions, and recent theories of Intentionality such as Mohanty’s, Aquilla’s, Searle’s, and Harney’s. Constantinos Athanasopoulos, 3 Acknowledgements Firstly and foremost I would like to thank God for allowing me to finish this project: AOEAIOIO 0EOS HMQN AOEA EOI. Secondly, my parents, George and Charicleia who with great financial sacrifices have equipped me with a University Education, lasting more than seven years now. Thirdly, my Supervisor, Mary Haight, who has put up with me for four years, and has supported me fully for the duration of my research (and I hope long after), Fourthly, my brother John and sisters Ioanna and Eurikleia, their spouses and children, relatives, teachers, and the many special friends in Greece, Canada, and Scotland who have supported me emotionally (and not only) in this long road towards submission. Undoubtedly, the importance on the role of the Emotions and Intentionality that this thesis is emphasising is the result of my associations with people who could dress my existence with the comfort of sympathy and friendship in times of hardship. Special thanks I owe to all the members of the Glasgow Department and other Departments of Philosophy across Scotland, and in my alma matter, Brandon University, Canada, who have supported with their warmth and help a “budding Greek Philosopher”, and especially Dr.Jim Edwards, Mr.Dudley Knowles, Mr.David Campbell, Mr.John Porter, Dr.Christopher Martin, Mr. Terry Greenwood, Dr. Scott Meikle, Dr.Nick Zangwill, Dr John Divers, Prof.Robin Downie, Prof.Alexander Broadie, Mr.Ephraim Borrowski, Mr. Richard Stalley, Mr.Pat Shaw, ProfEva Schaper, Prof.Timothy Sprigge, Prof.John Skorupski, Prof. Crispin Wright, Dr.John Haldane, Mr.Lesley Stevenson, Dr.Berrys Gaut, Prof.Eric Matthews, Dr.Gordon Graham, Dr.Peter Clark, Prof.Bob Hale, Mr.Christopher Bryant, Dr.Theodore Scaltsas, and the Dundee-St.Andrews Discussion Group on the Mind and AI (1990-1) and Profs.K.Hanly, P.Gosselin, and M. Yoh, (I know I have forgotten many, please forgive me). Also I developed some of the ideas expressed here during my attendance and participation in Conferences; for some of these I was supported financially by The Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association, The British Society for the Philosophy of Science, The Philosophical Quarterly, and the Departments of Logic and Metaphysics, and Moral Philosophy at St. Andrews. Finally, but most importantly, I owe a lot to the Fathers and Sisters (in Scotland, in Essex, in Geneva, and in Greece) that have prayed (and I hope will keep praying) for me; with their freely and abundantly offered hospitality, kindness and support, have helped me greatly in keeping mind and soul together during my stay here. Constantinos Athanasopoulos, 4 CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION (pp.6-12). i) Intentionality: First Use in Brentano. (pp.6-7) ii) What any proposed account of Intentionality must have as components and criteria, (pp.7-8) iii) What additional components and criteria any valid theory of Intentionality should have, (pp.8-12) II. HUSSERL’S THEORY OF INTENTIONALITY (pp.12-18). m . SARTRE’S CRITIQUE OF HUSSERL’S THEORY OF INTENTIONALITY AND SARTRE’S OWN THEORY (pp. 19^ 114). i) The Transcendence of Ego: The Negative Critique of the Husserlian Consciousness, (pp.20-67) ii) ’’Intentionality: A Fundamental Idea of Husserl's Phenomenology”: The Positive Critique of the Bursting Consciousness, (pp.68-73) iii) Critical Evaluation and Analysis of the Essays: The Superiority of Sartre's Theory. (pp.74-I14) IV. INTENTIONALITY AND REALISM (pp.115-168). i) Introduction, (pp.115-116) ii) Is Sartre a Realist or an Idealist? (pp.l 16-155) Constantinos Athanasopoulos, 5 iii) Can Sartre be a McCullochian Realist? (pp.155-160) iv) Can Sartre be a Hegelian in his views on Being? (pp.160-165) v) Sartre and Wittgenstein on Reality, (pp.165-168) V. INTENTIONALITY AND THE EMOTIONS (pp.169-245). i) Sartre’s Theory of the Emotions, (pp.169-218) ii) Critical Evaluation of Sartre’s Theory, (pp.218-230) iii) Sartre and Language, (pp.230-238) iv) Wittgenstein and Sartre on the Emotions and Language. (pp.238-245) VI. CRITIQUES ON SARTRE’S THEORY OF INTENTIONALITY (pp.246-266). i) Jitendra Nath Mohanty: Intentionality and Indian Philosophy of Consciousness, (pp.246-254) ii) Richard E. Aquilla: Intentionality as the Study of Mental Acts. (pp.255-257) iii) John R. Searle; Intentionality of the Speech Acts, (pp.257-264) iv) M aurita Harney: Intentionality of Sense, (pp.264-266) VH. CONCLUSION (pp.267-268). VHL BIBLIOGRAPHY (pp.269-275) Constantinos Athanasopoulos, 6 L Introduction. In the Introduction I shall attempt a description of the first use of the term ’'Intentionality” by Brentano; in addition, I shall provide an outline of some of the components any theory of Intentionality has to have in order for it to use the term comprehensively and to follow the legacy that Brentano left us. i) Intentionality: Brentano’s Use of the Term. The word comes from the Latinmtendere (to stretch, to point at), and means the metaphorical stretching of consciousness in order to beo f something, i.e., to have an object, which may or may not actually exist. Brentano1 first coined the termIntentionality for distinguishing (from other kinds of acts) and characterising mental acts as "the direction of the mind to an object" in perception, judgement or belief approval or disapproval. In Brentano's theory the mental acts contain their object intentionally within themselves. With what is called "Brentano's Irreducibility Thesis" it is claimed that Intentionality is an irreducible feature of mental phenomena, and since no physical phenomena could exhibit it, mental phenomena could not be a species of physical phenomena. 1 See in Franz Brentano,Psvcholoeie vom emvirischen Stancbunkt (1874). Constantinos Athanasopoulos, 7 Brentano also coined the phrase "Intentional Inexistence of the Intentional Objects of Mental Acts", to indicate that the intentional object may or may not exist in reality. By this he meant that even though we cannot want or believe without wanting or believing something, what we want or believe may not necessarily exist. For example, we may want the care of ex-associates of ours, while they disregard us and it is almost certain that they shall not care for us in the future; or we believe that ex-associates of ours still care for us, even though it is almost certain that they do not. ii) What any proposed account of Intentionality must therefore have as components and criteria. (These are necessary components and criteria but not sufficient. I am not certain whether we can ever establish the necessaryand sufficient criteria of Intentionality. These criteria can be as varied as the human minds themselves!) Three major truths have to be taken into consideration, if any proposed account of Intentionality is to be faithful to the legacy of Brentano: a) The modes of Intentionality may or may not be only symbols, sentences, propositions. Intentionality is far more complex than any known mode of representation, having as parts logical, linguistic, emotive, imaginary, conscious and unconscious elements and relations. These elements and relations that can involve the body, the will and the intellect, cannot be easily put in any single category of representation. Constantinos Athanasopoulos, 8 b) Intentionality does not only have as objects things that exist, or have existed, or that shall exist. It may also have things that never existed, or shall never exist (e.g. things such as fictional beings, and even logically impossible beings). c) Intentionality is also of things that are not ours, i.e., do not belong to human intellects, neither to their artifacts. An example of this is a cliff for a geologist and a painter, or a poet; a drift-wood for an artist, etc. The cliff and the drift-wood do not actually have Intentionality in the same way as for example a book has Intentionality for a reader, however they are treated as if they had it (this point shall become clearer later on). iii) Additional components and criteria that any valid theory of Intentionality should have.
Recommended publications
  • 35 Fallacies
    THIRTY-TWO COMMON FALLACIES EXPLAINED L. VAN WARREN Introduction If you watch TV, engage in debate, logic, or politics you have encountered the fallacies of: Bandwagon – "Everybody is doing it". Ad Hominum – "Attack the person instead of the argument". Celebrity – "The person is famous, it must be true". If you have studied how magicians ply their trade, you may be familiar with: Sleight - The use of dexterity or cunning, esp. to deceive. Feint - Make a deceptive or distracting movement. Misdirection - To direct wrongly. Deception - To cause to believe what is not true; mislead. Fallacious systems of reasoning pervade marketing, advertising and sales. "Get Rich Quick", phone card & real estate scams, pyramid schemes, chain letters, the list goes on. Because fallacy is common, you might want to recognize them. There is no world as vulnerable to fallacy as the religious world. Because there is no direct measure of whether a statement is factual, best practices of reasoning are replaced be replaced by "logical drift". Those who are political or religious should be aware of their vulnerability to, and exportation of, fallacy. The film, "Roshomon", by the Japanese director Akira Kurisawa, is an excellent study in fallacy. List of Fallacies BLACK-AND-WHITE Classifying a middle point between extremes as one of the extremes. Example: "You are either a conservative or a liberal" AD BACULUM Using force to gain acceptance of the argument. Example: "Convert or Perish" AD HOMINEM Attacking the person instead of their argument. Example: "John is inferior, he has blue eyes" AD IGNORANTIAM Arguing something is true because it hasn't been proven false.
    [Show full text]
  • Fitting Words
    FITTING WORDS Answer Key SAMPLE James B. Nance, Fitting Words: Classical Rhetoric for the Christian Student: Answer Key Copyright ©2016 by James B. Nance Version 1.0.0 Published by Roman Roads Media 739 S Hayes Street, Moscow, Idaho 83843 509-592-4548 | www.romanroadsmedia.com Cover design concept by Mark Beauchamp; adapted by Daniel Foucachon and Valerie Anne Bost. Cover illustration by Mark Beauchamp; adapted by George Harrell. Interior illustration by George Harrell. Interior design by Valerie Anne Bost. Printed in the United States of America. Unless otherwise indicated, Scripture quotations are from the New King James Version of the Bible, ©1979, 1980, 1982, 1984, 1988 by Thomas Nelson, Inc., Nashville, Tennessee. Scripture quotations marked NIV are from the the Holy Bible, New International Version®, NIV® Copyright © 1973, 1978, 1984, 2011 by Biblica, Inc.® Used by permission. All rights reserved worldwide. Scipture quotations marked ESV are from the English Standard Version copyright ©2001 by Crossway Bibles, a division of Good News Publishers. Used by permission. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopy, recording, or otherwise, without prior permission of the author, except as provided by USA copyright law. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data available on www.romanroadsmedia.com. ISBN-13: 978-1-944482-03-9 ISBN-10:SAMPLE 1-944482-03-2 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 FITTING WORDS Classical Rhetoric for the Christian Student Answer Key JAMES B.
    [Show full text]
  • The 13Th Annual ISNA-CISNA Education Forum Welcomes You!
    13th Annual ISNA Education Forum April 6th -8th, 2011 The 13th Annual ISNA-CISNA Education Forum Welcomes You! The ISNA-CISNA Education Forum, which has fostered professional growth and development and provided support to many Islamic schools, is celebrating its 13-year milestone this April. We have seen accredited schools sprout from grassroots efforts across North America; and we credit Allah, subhanna wa ta‘alla, for empowering the many men and women who have made the dreams for our schools a reality. Today the United States is home to over one thousand weekend Islamic schools and several hundred full-time Islamic schools. Having survived the initial challenge of galvanizing community support to form a school, Islamic schools are now attempting to find the most effective means to build curriculum and programs that will strengthen the Islamic faith and academic excellence of their students. These schools continue to build quality on every level to enable their students to succeed in a competitive and increasingly multicultural and interdependent world. The ISNA Education Forum has striven to be a major platform for this critical endeavor from its inception. The Annual Education Forum has been influential in supporting Islamic schools and Muslim communities to carry out various activities such as developing weekend schools; refining Qur‘anic/Arabic/Islamic Studies instruction; attaining accreditation; improving board structures and policies; and implementing training programs for principals, administrators, and teachers. Thus, the significance of the forum lies in uniting our community in working towards a common goal for our youth. Specific Goals 1. Provide sessions based on attendees‘ needs, determined by surveys.
    [Show full text]
  • 35. Logic: Common Fallacies Steve Miller Kennesaw State University, [email protected]
    Kennesaw State University DigitalCommons@Kennesaw State University Sexy Technical Communications Open Educational Resources 3-1-2016 35. Logic: Common Fallacies Steve Miller Kennesaw State University, [email protected] Cherie Miller Kennesaw State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.kennesaw.edu/oertechcomm Part of the Technical and Professional Writing Commons Recommended Citation Miller, Steve and Miller, Cherie, "35. Logic: Common Fallacies" (2016). Sexy Technical Communications. 35. http://digitalcommons.kennesaw.edu/oertechcomm/35 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Open Educational Resources at DigitalCommons@Kennesaw State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Sexy Technical Communications by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Kennesaw State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Logic: Common Fallacies Steve and Cherie Miller Sexy Technical Communication Home Logic and Logical Fallacies Taken with kind permission from the book Why Brilliant People Believe Nonsense by J. Steve Miller and Cherie K. Miller Brilliant People Believe Nonsense [because]... They Fall for Common Fallacies The dull mind, once arriving at an inference that flatters the desire, is rarely able to retain the impression that the notion from which the inference started was purely problematic. ― George Eliot, in Silas Marner In the last chapter we discussed passages where bright individuals with PhDs violated common fallacies. Even the brightest among us fall for them. As a result, we should be ever vigilant to keep our critical guard up, looking for fallacious reasoning in lectures, reading, viewing, and especially in our own writing. None of us are immune to falling for fallacies.
    [Show full text]
  • The Myth of the Superuser: Fear, Risk, and Harm Online
    The Myth of the Superuser: Fear, Risk, and Harm Online ∗ Paul Ohm Fear of the powerful computer user, the “Superuser,” dominates debates about online conflict. He is a mythic figure: difficult to find, immune to technological constraints, and aware of legal loopholes. Policymakers, fearful of his power, too often overreact by passing overbroad, ambiguous laws intended to ensnare the Superuser but which are instead used against inculpable, ordinary users. This response is unwarranted because the Superuser is often a marginal figure whose power has been greatly exaggerated. The exaggerated focus on the Superuser reveals a pathological characteristic of the study of power, crime, and security online, which springs from a widely held fear of the Internet. Building on the social science fear literature, this Article challenges the conventional wisdom and ∗ Associate Professor of Law and Telecommunications, University of Colorado Law School. Thanks to Tim Wu, Orin Kerr, Phil Weiser, Julie Cohen, Pierre Schlag, Brett Frischmann, Victor Fleischer, Miranda Fleischer, Viva Moffat, and Jean Camp for their helpful comments. Thanks also for suggestions and support from participants in the University of Colorado Law School Faculty Workshop, including Clare Huntington, Nestor Davidson, Scott Peppett, Mimi Wesson, Amy Schmitz, Sarah Krakoff, and Brad Bernthal; the Intellectual Property Scholars Conference; and the Telecommunications Policy Research Conference. Thanks also to Todd Blair and Michael Beylkin for outstanding research assistance. 1327 1328 University of California, Davis [Vol. 41:1327 standard assumptions about the role of experts. Unlike dispassionate experts in other fields, computer experts are as susceptible as laypeople to exaggerate the power of the Superuser.
    [Show full text]
  • Informal Fallacies in Legal Argumentation
    South Carolina Law Review Volume 44 Issue 2 Article 4 Winter 1993 Informal Fallacies in Legal Argumentation Kevin W. Saunders University of Oklahoma Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/sclr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Kevin W. Saunders, Informal Fallacies in Legal Argumentation, 44 S. C. L. Rev. 343 (1993). This Article is brought to you by the Law Reviews and Journals at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in South Carolina Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Saunders: Informal Fallacies in Legal Argumentation INFORMAL FALLACIES IN LEGAL ARGUMENTATION KEVIN W. SAUNDERS" I. INTRODUCTION ............................ 344 II. VARIETIES OF INFORMAL FALLACIES ............... 345 A. Argumentum ad Hominem .... ............ B. Argumentum ad Misericordiam . ............ C. Argumentum ad Populum ..... ............ D. Argumentum ad Vericundiam .. ............ E. Ignoratio Elenchi .......... ............ F. Petitio Principii ........... ............ G. Post Hoc Ergo Propter Hoc ... ............ H. Argumentum ad Ignorantiam ... ............ L Argumentum ad Terrorem .... ............ J. Argumentum ad Antiquitam ... ............ K. Accident and Hasty Generalization ........... L. Composition ............. ............ M. Division ............... ° . o ..° ° . N. Complex Question ......... ............° ° 0. Tu Quoque .............. ............° ° P. Ambiguity .............. ............ 1. Equivocation .........
    [Show full text]
  • Accent Accent Is a Form of Fallacy Through Shifting Meaning. in This Case, the Meaning Is Changed by Altering Which Parts Of
    FALLACIES Accent Accent is a form of fallacy through shifting meaning. In this case, the meaning is changed by altering which parts of a statement are emphasized. For example: "We should not speak ill of our friends" and "We should not speak ill of our friends" Be particularly wary of this fallacy on the net, where it's easy to misread the emphasis of what's written. Ad hoc As mentioned earlier, there is a difference between argument and explanation. If we're interested in establishing A, and B is offered as evidence, the statement "A because B" is an argument. If we're trying to establish the truth of B, then "A because B" is not an argument, it's an explanation. The Ad Hoc fallacy is to give an after-the-fact explanation which doesn't apply to other situations. Often this ad hoc explanation will be dressed up to look like an argument. For example, if we assume that God treats all people equally, then the following is an ad hoc explanation: "I was healed from cancer." "Praise the Lord, then. He is your healer." "So, will He heal others who have cancer?" "Er... The ways of God are mysterious." Affirmation of the consequent This fallacy is an argument of the form "A implies B, B is true, therefore A is true." To understand why it is a fallacy, examine the truth table for this implication. Here's an example: "If the universe had been created by a supernatural being, we would see order and organization everywhere.
    [Show full text]
  • Christ Church Library, Carroll Collection
    Christ Church Library, Carroll Collection Digitised image notes and captions by Edward Wakeling Carroll-MS 7 – Further sections of Symbolic Logic, Part II, Advanced Introductory notes: These are other logical manuscripts from the Warner Bequest. They concern standard logical fallacies, as listed by W. S. Jevons Elementary Lessons in Logic (1876), Lesson XXI, “Material Fallacies,” from page 177. Clearly, Dodgson intended to explain these fallacies in Symbolic Logic, Part II, Advanced, but the book was only planned in outline as these headings reveal, and not completed. Carroll-mss_0043-ms7_01_r Dodgson indicated that this was to form part of Book XV – Fallacies, in his second volume of Symbolic Logic. Bartley does not include Book XV in his reconstruction. The literal translation of the Latin “a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter” is “from an unqualified statement to a qualified one” and represents the logical fallacy known as “A Fallacy of Converse Accident.” For example, “If we allow people with terminal cancer to use medical marijuana, then everyone should be allowed to use medical marijuana” is a fallacious argument based on a generalisation. Carroll-mss_0044-ms7_01_v The verso is blank Carroll-mss_0045-ms7_02_r Logical heading only for “Argumentum ad hominem” (Argument to the man). This is an argument deriving its power from the situation of one’s opponent – for example, advice to a barrister might be “If you have a bad case to defend, abuse the plaintiff’s attorney.” Carroll-mss_0046-ms7_02_v The verso is blank Carroll-mss_0047-ms7_03_r The “change of epoch” is Dodgson’s heading for more fallacious arguments – two examples are given.
    [Show full text]
  • IGNORING QUALIFICATIONS (SECUNDUM QUID) AS a SUBFALLACY of HASTY GENERALIZATION Douglas N. WALTON in the Experience of Teaching
    Logique A n a ly s e 129-130 (1990), 113-154 IGNORING QUALIFICATIONS (SECUNDUM QUID) AS A SUBFALLACY OF HASTY GENERALIZATION Douglas N. WALTON In the experience of teaching courses on informal logic and argumentation, one finds that the fault of being overly rigid and absolutistic in thinking, of being too insensitive to the defeasible nature of much ordinary reasoning, is an important type of error. In a critical discussion, it is important for an arguer to be open to refutation, to admitting her argument was wrong, should convincing evidence be brought forward by the opposing side. It would be nice to have a name for this general type of failure in argument, and for the subfallacies or special failures that come under it. The idea of neglecting qualifications, or legitimate exceptions to a plau- sible generalization in a particular case, is a clear and simple kind of failure that covers this gap. It is quite generally clear to students, from their per- sonal experience, at least in general, what kind of error this is.(') On some accounts, the traditional informal fallacy of secundum quid (originally from the Aristotelian fallacy para to pi, meaning 'in a certain respect')) fills this bill, referring to the fault of not paying attention to qualifications that would invalidate the use of a general proposition in a particular case. For example, in the Dictionary of Philosophy (Runes, 1964, p. 287) we find: Secundum quid: (Lat.) Relatively, in some respect, in a qualified sense; contrasted with simpliciter, absolutely. — V.J.B. Secundum quid, or more fully, a dicto simpliciter ad dictum secundum quid, is any fallacy arising from the use of a general proposition without attention to tacit qualifications which would invalidate the use made of it.
    [Show full text]
  • 3Informal Fallacies 3
    3622_W_Hurley_ch03 6/29/07 11:35 AM Page 113 3Informal Fallacies 3 3.1 Fallacies in General A fallacy is a defect in an argument that consists in something other than false premises alone. The fallacies introduced in this chapter involve defective patterns of arguing that occur so often they have been given specific names. Such defects com- prise either mistakes in reasoning or the creation of an illusion that makes a bad argu- ment appear good. The term non sequitur (“it does not follow”) is another name for fallacy. Both deductive and inductive arguments may contain fallacies; if they do, they are either unsound or uncogent, depending on the kind of argument. Conversely, if an argument is unsound or uncogent, it has one or more false premises or it contains a fallacy (or both). Fallacies are usually divided into two groups: formal and informal. A formal fallacy is one that may be identified by merely examining the form or structure of an argu- ment. Fallacies of this kind are found only in deductive arguments that have identifiable forms. Chapter 1 presented some of these forms: categorical syllogisms, disjunctive syllogisms, and hypothetical syllogisms. The following categorical syllogism contains a formal fallacy: All bullfights are grotesque rituals. All executions are grotesque rituals. Therefore, all bullfights are executions. This argument has the following form: All A are B. All C are B. All A are C. By merely examining this form, one can see that it is invalid. The fact that A, B, and C stand respectively for “bullfights,”“grotesque rituals,” and “executions” is irrelevant in detecting the fallacy.
    [Show full text]
  • Exercise Answers
    Exercise 1.1 Exercise Answers Exercise 1.1 Part I 1. P: Titanium combines readily with oxygen, nitrogen, and hydrogen, all of which have an adverse effect on its mechanical properties. C: Titanium must be processed in their absence. 2. P: The good, according to Plato, is that which furthers a person's real interests. C: In any given case when the good is known, men will seek it. 3. P: The denial or perversion of justice by the sentences of courts, as well as in any other manner, is with reason classed among the just causes of war. C: The federal judiciary ought to have cognizance of all causes in which the citizens of other countries are concerned. 4. P: When individuals voluntarily abandon property, they forfeit any expectation of privacy in it that they might have had. C: A warrantless search and seizure of abandoned property is not unreasonable under the Fourth Amendment. 5. P1: Artists and poets look at the world and seek relationships and order. P2: But they translate their ideas to canvas, or to marble, or into poetic images. P3 Scientists try to find relationships between different objects and events. P4: To express the order they find, they create hypotheses and theories. C: The great scientific theories are easily compared to great art and great literature. 6. P1: The animal species in Australia are very different from those on the mainland. P2: Asian placental mammals and Australian marsupial mammals have not been in contact in the last several million years. C: There was never a land bridge between Australia and the mainland 7.
    [Show full text]
  • Search and Seizure, Establishment of Religion, and Constitutional Reason
    Please do not remove this page A tale of two clauses: search and seizure, establishment of religion, and constitutional reason. Dane, Perry https://scholarship.libraries.rutgers.edu/discovery/delivery/01RUT_INST:ResearchRepository/12663159610004646?l#13663159600004646 Dane, P. (2018). A tale of two clauses: search and seizure, establishment of religion, and constitutional reason. The William and Mary Bill of Rights Journal, 26(4), 939–993. https://doi.org/10.7282/00000106 Document Version: Version of Record (VoR) Published Version: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj/vol26/iss4/3/ This work is protected by copyright. You are free to use this resource, with proper attribution, for research and educational purposes. Other uses, such as reproduction or publication, may require the permission of the copyright holder. Downloaded On 2021/10/01 10:03:14 -0400 William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal Volume 26 (2017-2018) Issue 4 Article 3 May 2018 A Tale of Two Clauses: Search and Seizure, Establishment of Religion, and Constitutional Reason Perry Dane Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, First Amendment Commons, and the Fourth Amendment Commons Repository Citation Perry Dane, A Tale of Two Clauses: Search and Seizure, Establishment of Religion, and Constitutional Reason, 26 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 939 (2018), https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/ wmborj/vol26/iss4/3 Copyright c 2018 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj A TALE OF TWO CLAUSES: SEARCH AND SEIZURE, ESTABLISHMENT OF RELIGION, AND CONSTITUTIONAL REASON Perry Dane* ABSTRACT This Article dissects two developments in widely separate areas of American constitutional law—the “reasonable expectation of privacy” test for the Fourth Amendment’s Search and Seizure Clause and the “endorsement” test for the First Amendment’s Establishment Clause.
    [Show full text]