Categorization and Concepts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Categorization and Concepts Trim Size: 7in x 10in Wixted-Vol3k c08.tex V1 - 09/30/2017 9:13 P.M. Page 275 CHAPTER 8 Categorization and Concepts ROBERT L. GOLDSTONE, ALAN KERSTEN, AND PAULO F. CARVALHO INTRODUCTION Issues related to concepts and catego- rization are nearly ubiquitous in psychology Concepts are the building blocks of thought. because of people’s natural tendency to They are critically involved when we rea- perceive a thing as something. We have a son, make inferences, and try to generalize powerful impulse to interpret our world. our previous experiences to new situations. This act of interpretation, an act of “seeing Behind every word in every language lies something as X” rather than simply seeing it a concept, although there are concepts, like (Wittgenstein, 1953), is fundamentally an act the small plastic tubes attached to the ends of categorization. of shoelaces, that we are familiar with and The attraction of research on concepts is k k can think about even if we do not know that an extremely wide variety of cognitive that they are called aglets. Concepts are acts can be understood as categorizations indispensable to human cognition because (Kurtz, 2015; Murphy, 2002). Identifying the they take the “blooming, buzzing confu- person sitting across from you at the breakfast sion” (James, 1890, p. 488) of disorganized table involves categorizing something as your sensory experiences and establish order spouse. Diagnosing the cause of someone’s through mental categories. These mental illness involves a disease categorization. categories allow us to make sense of the Interpreting a painting as a Picasso, an arti- world and predict how worldly entities will fact as Mayan, a geometry as non-Euclidean, behave. We see, hear, interpret, remember, a fugue as baroque, a conversationalist as understand, and talk about our world through charming, a wine as a Bordeaux, and a gov- our concepts, and so it is worthy of reflec- ernment as socialist are categorizations at tion time to establish where concepts come various levels of abstraction. The typically from, how they work, and how they can unspoken assumption of research on concepts best be learned and deployed to suit our is that these cognitive acts have something cognitive needs. in common. That is, there are principles that explain many or all acts of categorization. AQ1 We are grateful to Brian Rogosky, Robert Nosofsky, John This assumption is controversial (see Medin, Kruschke, Linda Smith, and David Landy for helpful Lynch, & Solomon, 2000), but is perhaps comments on earlier drafts of this chapter. This research justified by the potential payoff of discover- was funded by National Science Foundation REESE grant DRL-0910218, and Department of Education IES ing common principles governing concepts grant R305A1100060. in their diverse manifestations. 275 k Trim Size: 7in x 10in Wixted-Vol3k c08.tex V1 - 09/30/2017 9:13 P.M. Page 276 276 Categorization and Concepts The desirability of a general account of each other, and assigning values of 0 and 1 to concept learning has led the field to focus a dimension is arbitrary. For example, for a its energy on what might be called generic color dimension, red may be assigned a value concepts. Experiments typically involve arti- of 0 and blue a value 1. The exact category ficial categories that are hopefully unfamiliar structure of Table 8.1 has been used in at least to the subject. Formal models of concept 30 studies (reviewed by J. D. Smith & Minda, learning and use are constructed to be able to 2000) and instantiated by stimuli as diverse handle any kind of concept irrespective of its as geometric forms, yearbook photographs, content. Although there are exceptions to this cartoons of faces (Medin & Schaffer, 1978), general trend (Malt, 1994; Ross & Murphy, and line drawings of rocket ships. These 1999), much of the mainstream empirical researchers are not particularly interested and theoretical work on concept learning is in the category structure of Table 8.1 and concerned not with explaining how particular are certainly not interested in the catego- concepts are created, but with how concepts rization of rocket ships per se. Instead, they in general are represented and processed. choose their structures and stimuli so as to be One manifestation of this approach is that (a) unfamiliar (so that learning is required), the members of a concept are often given (b) well controlled (dimensions are approx- an abstract symbolic representation. For imately equally salient and independent), example, Table 8.1 shows a typical notation (c) diagnostic with respect to theories of used to describe the stimuli seen by a subject category learning, and (d) potentially gen- in a psychological experiment or presented eralizable to natural categories that people to a formal model of concept learning. Nine learn. Work on generic concepts is valuable k objects belong to two categories, and each if it turns out that there are domain-general k object is defined by its value along four principles underlying human concepts that binary dimensions. In this notation, objects can be discovered. Still, there is no a pri- from Category A typically have values of 1 ori reason to assume that all concepts will on each of the four dimensions and objects follow the same principles, or that we can from Category B usually have values of 0. generalize from generic concepts to naturally The dimensions are typically unrelated to occurring concepts. Table 8.1 A Common Category Structure WHAT ARE CONCEPTS? Dimension Concepts, Categories, and Internal Category Stimulus D1 D2 D3 D4 Representations A11110 A21010A good starting place is Edward Smith’s Category A A31011(1989) characterization that a concept is “a A41101mental representation of a class or individual A50111and deals with what is being represented and B11100how that information is typically used during Category B B20110 B30001the categorization” (p. 502). It is common to B40000distinguish between a concept and a category. A concept refers to a mentally possessed idea Source: From Medin and Schaffer (1978). Copy- right 1978 by the American Psychological Association. or notion, whereas a category refers to a Reprinted with permission. set of entities that are grouped together. k Trim Size: 7in x 10in Wixted-Vol3k c08.tex V1 - 09/30/2017 9:13 P.M. Page 277 What Are Concepts? 277 The concept dog is whatever psychological particular objects belong, and how well, to state signifies thoughts of dogs. The category the concept’s extension. dog consists of all the entities in the real world that are appropriately categorized as Equivalence Classes dogs. The question of whether concepts determine categories or vice versa is an Another important aspect of concepts is that important foundational controversy. On the they are equivalence classes. In the classical one hand, if one assumes the primacy of notion of an equivalence class, distinguish- external categories of entities, then one will able stimuli come to be treated as the same tend to view concept learning as the enter- thing once they have been placed in the prise of inductively creating mental structures same category (Sidman, 1994). This kind of that predict these categories. One extreme equivalence is too strong when it comes to version of this view is the exemplar model human concepts because even when we place of concept learning (Estes, 1994; Medin & two objects into the same category, we do not Schaffer, 1978; Nosofsky, 1984), in which treat them as the same thing for all purposes. one’s internal representation of a concept is Some researchers have stressed the intrinsic nothing more than the set of all of the exter- variability of human concepts—variability nally supplied examples of the concept to that makes it unlikely that a concept has the which one has been exposed. If, on the other same sense or meaning each time it is used hand, one assumes the primacy of internal (Barsalou, 1987; Connell & Lynott, 2014; mental concepts, then one tends to view exter- Thelen & Smith, 1994). Still, the extent to nal categories as the end product of using which perceptually dissimilar things can k these internal concepts to organize observed be treated equivalently given the appropri- k entities. Some practitioners of a “concepts ate conceptualization is impressive. To the first” approach argue that the external world biologist armed with a strong “mammal” does not inherently consist of rocks, dogs, concept, even whales and dogs may be and tables; these are mental concepts that treated as commensurate in many situations organize an otherwise unstructured exter- related to biochemistry, child rearing, and nal world (Lakoff, 1987). Recent research thermoregulation. indicates that concepts’ extensions (the class Equivalence classes are relatively imper- of items to which the concept applies) and vious to superficial similarities. Once one intensions (the features that distinguish that has formed a concept that treats all skunks class of items) do not always cohere with as equivalent for some purposes, irrelevant each other (Hampton & Passanisi, 2016). variations among skunks can be greatly For example, dolphins and whales are often de-emphasized. When people are told a story judged to have many of the features charac- in which scientists discover that an animal teristic of an internal representation of fish that looks exactly like a raccoon actually con- (e.g., swims, lives in oceans, and has fins), tains the internal organs of a skunk and has but are still placed in the extensional set of skunk parents and skunk children, they often mammals rather than fish. The implication categorize the animal as a skunk (Keil, 1989; is that a complete model of concepts may Rips, 1989). When people classify objects require at least partially separate represen- into familiar, labeled categories such as chair, tations for intensions and extensions, rather then their memory for the individuating infor- than a more parsimonious model in which mation about the objects is markedly worse a concept’s intension determines whether (Lupyan, 2008a).
Recommended publications
  • Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Library Philosophy and Practice (e-journal) Libraries at University of Nebraska-Lincoln July 2005 Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information Ken R. Herold Hamilton College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/libphilprac Part of the Library and Information Science Commons Herold, Ken R., "Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information" (2005). Library Philosophy and Practice (e-journal). 27. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/libphilprac/27 Library Philosophy and Practice Vol. 3, No. 2 (Spring 2001) (www.uidaho.edu/~mbolin/lppv3n2.htm) ISSN 1522-0222 Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information Ken R. Herold Systems Manager Burke Library Hamilton College Clinton, NY 13323 “My purpose is to tell of bodies which have been transformed into shapes of a different kind.” Ovid, Metamorphoses Part I. Library Philosophy Provocation Information seems to be ubiquitous, diaphanous, a-categorical, discrete, a- dimensional, and knowing. · Ubiquitous. Information is ever-present and pervasive in our technology and beyond in our thinking about the world, appearing to be a generic ‘thing’ arising from all of our contacts with each other and our environment, whether thought of in terms of communication or cognition. For librarians information is a universal concept, at its greatest extent total in content and comprehensive in scope, even though we may not agree that all information is library information. · Diaphanous. Due to its virtuality, the manner in which information has the capacity to make an effect, information is freedom. In many aspects it exhibits a transparent quality, a window-like clarity as between source and patron in an ideal interface or a perfect exchange without bias.
    [Show full text]
  • Misunderstanding Davidson by Martin Clifford Rule
    MISUNDERSTANDING DAVIDSON BY MARTIN CLIFFORD RULE Submitted to the graduate degree program in Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. _________________________________ Chairperson Dr. John Bricke, Professor of Philosophy Emeritus. _________________________________ Ben Eggleston, Professor. _________________________________ Eileen Nutting, Assistant Professor. _________________________________ Clifton L. Pye, Associate Professor. _________________________________ John Symons, Professor. Date Defended: 07/12/2016 ii The Dissertation Committee for Martin Clifford Rule Certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: MISUNDERSTANDING DAVIDSON ________________________________ Chairperson Dr. John Bricke, Professor of Philosophy Emeritus. Date approved: 07/12/2016 iii ABSTRACT The main aim of this dissertation is to offer, and to defend, an interpretation of Donald Davidson’s classic paper “Mental Events” which interpretation I take to be identical to Davidson’s intended interpretation. My contention is that many readers misunderstand this paper. My method for showing this will be, first, to give a brief summary of the surface structure, and the core concepts, of “Mental Events”. I will then begin to canvas exemplars of the main lines of (alleged) objection to what “Mental Events” has been supposed to contend. I intend to argue that these objections misunderstand either Davidson’s conclusions, or his arguments, or they require material additional to the position that Davidson actually lays out and argues for in “Mental Events” in order to follow. In the latter case I shall attempt to show that these additions are not contentions which Davidson shares by referencing further materials from Davidson’s work.
    [Show full text]
  • Dual Categorization and the Role of Aristotle's Categories
    Dual Categorization and the Role of Aristotle's Categories Mark Ressler August 6, 2008 Abstract In the Categories, Aristotle addresses two different cases of dual cat- egorization, cases in which the same thing might appear in two different categories: relatives and secondary substances in the first case, qualities and relatives in the second. His treatment of these two cases is markedly different. Ackrill thinks dual categorization poses a dilemma for Aris- totle's project as a whole, but I argue that there is a dilemma only on particular understandings of Aristotle's purpose in compiling the list of categories. I investigate various interpretations of the categories to find one that explains Aristotle's reactions to dual categorization, and sug- gest an interpretation of the peculiar four-fold system of classification in Chapter 2. Can one thing appear in two separate categories? It seems to me that this question cannot be answered without determining the purpose for which the categories are established. If such dual categorization causes no problems ac- cording to the intended purpose of the categorial scheme, then there seems to be no reason for complaint. This is the approach that I take with regard to Aris- totle's categorial scheme in the Categories. In this work, Aristotle addresses two separate instances of dual categorization with regard to his list of ten cate- gories, but his reaction in these cases is surprisingly different, taking great pains to avoid dual categorization in one case, but showing a marked lack of concern in the other case. This indifference in the second case leads John Ackrill to criticize Aristotle's categorial project in general; however, it seems to me that if Aristotle's reaction to dual categorization in one case seems contrary to some conception of Aristotle's purpose in developing the categorial scheme, then per- haps that conception of the purpose of the Categories may not be a conception that Aristotle himself held.
    [Show full text]
  • The Importance of Categorization
    CHAPTER 1 The Importance of Categorization Many readers, I suspect, will take the title of this book as suggesting that women, fire , and dangerous things have something in common-say, that women are fiery and dangerous. Most feminists I've mentioned it to have loved the title for that reason, though some have hated it for the same rea­ son. But the chain of inference-from conjunction to categorization to commonality-is the norm. The inference is based on the common idea of what it means to be in the same category: things are categorized together on the basis of what they have in common. The idea that categories are defined by common properties is not only our everyday folk theory of what a category is , it is also the principaltechnicaltheory-one that has been with us for more than two thousand years . The classical view that categories are based on shared properties is not entirely wrong. We often do categorize things on that basis. But that is only a small part of the story. In recent years it has become clear that categorization is far more complex than thaI. A new theory of categoriza­ tion, called prototype theory, has emerged. It shows that human categori­ zation is based on principles that extend far beyond those envisioned in the classical theory. One of our goals is to survey the complexities of the way people really categorize. For example, the title of this book was in­ spired by the Australian aboriginal language Dyirbal, which haS a cate­ gory, balan, that actually includes women, fire , and dangerous things.
    [Show full text]
  • Dharmakirti, Davidson, and Knowing Reality
    Comparative Philosophy Volume 3, No. 1 (2012): 30-57 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 www.comparativephilosophy.org DHARMAKĪRTI, DAVIDSON, AND KNOWING REALITY LAJOS L. BRONS ABSTRACT: If we distinguish phenomenal effects from their noumenal causes, the former being our conceptual(ized) experiences, the latter their grounds or causes in reality ‘as it is’ independent of our experience, then two contradictory positions with regards to the relationship between these two can be distinguished: either phenomena are identical with their noumenal causes, or they are not. Davidson is among the most influential modern defenders of the former position, metaphysical non-dualism. Dharmakīrti’s strict distinction between ultimate and conventional reality, on the other hand, may be one of the most rigorously elaborated theories of the opposite position, metaphysical dualism. Despite this fundamental difference, their theories about the connection between phenomena and their noumenal causes are surprisingly similar in important respects. Both Dharmakīrti in his theory of ‘apoha’ and Davidson in his theory of ‘triangulation’ argued that the content of words or concepts depends on a process involving at least two communicating beings and shared noumenal stimuli. The main point of divergence is the nature of classification, but ultimately Dharmakīrti’s and Davidson’s conclusions on the noumenal-phenomenal relationship turn out to be complementary more than contradictory, and an integrative reconstruction suggests a ‘middle path’ between dualism and non-dualism. Keywords: Dharmakīrti, Donald Davidson, apoha, triangulation, reality, meta-ontology, subjectivity, metaphysical dualism 1. INTRODUCTION What can we know about reality? If two communicating beings are both aware of a certain black queen chess piece as evidenced by their reference(s) to that black queen chess piece in their communication, does that imply that there ‘really’ is (something that is) that black queen chess piece? At least there must be something causing the shared awareness.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Representation in Leibniz
    PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ by Stephen Montague Puryear B.S., Mechanical Engineering, North Carolina State University, 1994 M.A., Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2004 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY This dissertation was presented by Stephen Montague Puryear It was defended on December 5, 2005 and approved by Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy Stephen Engstrom Associate Professor of Philosophy J. E. McGuire Professor of History and Philosophy of Science Dissertation Director: Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright °c by Stephen Montague Puryear 2006 iii PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ Stephen Montague Puryear, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Though Leibniz’s views about perception and representation go to the heart of his philosophy, they have received surprisingly little attention over the years and in many ways continue to be poorly understood. I aim to redress these shortcomings. The body of the work begins with an exploration of Leibniz’s proposed analysis of representation (Chapter 2). Here I argue that on this analysis representation consists in a kind of structural correspondence— roughly an isomorphism—between representation and thing represented. Special attention is given to the application of this analysis to the challenging cases of linguistic and mental representation. The next two chapters concern what I take to be the central issue of the work: the nature of distinct perception.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Eastern Division New York December 2009
    APA Eastern Division New York December 2009 LATE MEDIEVAL NOMINALISM AND NONVERIDICAL CONCEPTS Claude Panaccio University of Quebec at Montreal Content externalism, as promoted by Hilary Putnam, Tyler Burge and many other prominent analytic philosophers in the last three or four decades, is the thesis that the content of our thoughts at a given moment is not uniquely determined by our internal states at that moment. In its causalist versions, it has often been presented as a deep revolution in philosophy of mind. Yet a number of medievalists (e.g. Peter King, Calvin Normore, Gyula Klima, and myself) have recently stressed the presence of significant externalist tendencies in fourteenth century nominalism, especially in William of Ockham and John Buridan. I have tried to round up the case for this interpretation of Ockham in a forthcoming paper entitled “ Ockham‟s externalism ”. Let me simply mention here, to give the most salient example, that Ockham insists, in Book II of his Commentary on the Sentences, that an intuitive cognition, whether intellectual or sensitive, always has a determinate singular thing as its object, although taken in itself it resembles a plurality of singular things, and that what fixes which singular object it is that a given intuitive cognition is a cognition of, is not the internal shape of this cognition, but which determinate thing caused it [Reportatio II, quest. 12-13, Op. Theol. V, 287-288]. Two intuitive cognitions, then, could be maximally similar to each other to the point of being indistinguishable by an observing angel ; yet, they would have different singular objects if they were caused by different singular things.
    [Show full text]
  • Four Meanings of Categorization: a Conceptual Analysis of Research on Person Perception
    DOI: 10.1111/spc3.12336 ARTICLE Four meanings of “categorization”: A conceptual analysis of research on person perception Andre Klapper1 | Ron Dotsch1,2 | Iris van Rooij1 | Daniel Wigboldus1 1 Radboud University Nijmegen Abstract 2 Utrecht University It is widely assumed that people tend to “categorize” other people. Correspondence “ ” Andre Klapper, Donders Institute for Brain, However, the term categorization has been used with qualitatively Cognition and Behaviour, Radboud University different underlying definitions in the person perception literature. Nijmegen, Nijmegen, The Netherlands. We present a conceptual analysis in which we disentangle four Email: [email protected] existing definitions: (a) categorization as representing, (b) categori- zation as dichotomizing, (c) categorization as organizing, and (d) Funding information categorization as grouping. Subsequently, we show that seemingly Nederlandse Organisatie voor Wetenschappelijk Onderzoek, Grant/Award antagonistic viewpoints in the literature may be reconciled by Number: 464‐11‐036 disentangling these definitions. Furthermore, we argue that disentangling these definitions is vital for theoretical interpretations of (past and future) empirical findings. Overall, our work aims to contribute to the clarity of person perception theories, provide novel perspectives on existing debates, and serve as a stepping stone for more differentiated models of person perception. KEYWORDS categorization, conceptual analysis, social perception, stereotyping 1 | INTRODUCTION People spontaneously categorize other people and use the knowledge that is associated with those categories to guide their behavior. For example, upon encountering another person, we may immediately categorize the person as a “policeman,” infer that the person may have a relatively dominant personality, and adjust our behavior to be respectful to the other person. This is how the person perception process has been characterized by social categori- zation models.
    [Show full text]
  • Forum: the Philosophy of Classification
    Knowl. Org. 39(2012)No.1 29 Forum: The Philosophy of Classification Forum: The Philosophy of Classification The Concept of Concept: Concepts and Terms† Alberto Marradi University of Florence and Buenos Aires <[email protected]> Since 1986 Alberto Marradi has been professor of Methodology of the Social Sciences in the University of Florence. From 1981-86 he was professor of Methodology of the Political Sciences in the University of Bologna. He is a regular visiting professor in social sciences at the University of Buenos Aires. His research interests lie in philosophy of knowledgeand the social sciences, methodology of social re- search, and cultural anthropology. He was responsible for the Schools of Excellence programme of the Italian Sociological Association (2000-2008). Since 2004 he has chaired Paideia, an association of Italian academicians and intellectuals who denounce the present lamentable state of education and culture in Italy. Marradi, Alberto. The Concept of Concept: Concepts and Terms. Knowledge Organization, 39(1), 29-54. 221 references. ABSTRACT: The concept of concept has seldom been examined in its entirety, and the term very seldom defined. The rigidity, or lack thereof, and the homogeneity, or lack thereof, of concepts, are only two of their characteristics that have been debated. These issues are reviewed in this paper, namely: 1) does a concept represent its referent(s), or is it a free creation of the mind?; 2) can a concept be analyzed in parts or elements?; 3) must a concept be general, i.e., refer to a category or a type, or can it refer to a single object, physical or mental?; 4) are concepts as clearly delimited as terms are? Are concepts voiceless terms?; and, 5) what do terms contribute to an individual’s and a community’s conceptual richness? As regards the relationship of concepts with their referents in the stage of formation, it seems reasonable to conclude that said relationship may be close in some concepts, less close in others, and lacking altogether in some cases.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Violence in the Philosophy of Aristotle
    SHS Web of Conferences 72, 01024 (2019) https://doi.org/10.1051/shsconf /20197201024 APPSCONF-2 019 The concept of violence in the philosophy of Aristotle Sergei Borisov, Viktor Rimsky, Roman Ivashina, Igor Lyashenko Belgorod State National Research University, 308015, Belgorod, Russia Abstract. The idea that the concept of 'violence' was part and is still viewed as part of a broad philosophical category may seem strange. However, the problem is resolved by referring to the concept of 'force,' which is lost in modern philosophy. The exception was the works in which we find some “traces” of this concept, including the works of Aristotle, which need to be free from modernizing interpretations. Still, in the translations of Aristotle, the Greek word δύναμις, used in its traditional meaning of potentiality, lost its connotations of force (movement, capability, function); in turn, 'force' was no longer linked with 'violence' (βια) and 'necessity.' Violence is seen as a kind of necessity, which is associated with the suppression of 'will,' freedom, something 'frustrating desire' and contrary to 'common sense,' as well as the absence of 'good.' Violence is presented not only in an ontological sense, but also existentially, as the opposite of 'good' and one's own 'desire.' Force stays in the background of 'necessity' as 'potentiality', 'potential energy' and 'movement', and violence loses the opposition that has arisen in the ontological mode. Introduction Initially, we turned to the hermeneutics of the texts of Aristotle in the existing Russian translations, trying to give our own understanding of violence in the modern philosophical context in view of its categorical inadequacy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of the Nominalist Movement on the Scientific Thought of Bacon, Boyle? and Locke
    The Influence of the Nominalist Movement on the Scientific Thought of Bacon, Boyle? and Locke by John Richard Milton A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of the University of London, Department of Humanities, Imperial College of Science and Technology September 1982 - 2 - Abstract This thesis is an investigation of the influence of the nominalist philosophy of the later Middle Ages on the natural philosophy (including metaphysics) and epistemology of Francis Bacon, Robert Boyle and John Locke. Because of the general reluctance of any of these thinkers to quote or make other references to any medieval or modern authors it is impossible to establish with any useful degree of probability which nominalist philosophers they had read. It can, however, be shown that Bacon, Boyle and Locke all accepted the kind of basic nominalist principles which William of Ockham and his successors had enunciated, and moreover that their acceptance of these principles influenced many of their other philosophical and scientific beliefs. Chapter 1 contains a general discussion of the traditional problem of universals and its philosophical implications. Chapter 2 is concerned with ancient and medieval nominalist theories and with their subsequent influence. Chapters 3 and 4 deal respectively with Bacon and Boyle; the former shows the connection between Bacon's inductive theory of method and his nominalist metaphysics; the latter discusses the influence of nominalist and voluntarist ideas on Boyle's conception of nature. Chapter 5 discusses nominalist influences in Locke's early work, up to and including the Drafts for the Essay written in 1671. Chapter 6 is concerned with the develop- ment of Locke's thought between 1671 and 1690, and with the general question of Locke's sources.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Introduction Smiles, talks, runs, arrivals and departures, births and deaths, thunder and lightning: the va- riety of the world seems to lie not only in the assortment of its ordinary and less ordinary inhabitants—animals and physical objects, or perhaps minds, sets, atoms—but also in the sort of things that happen to or are performed by them. In the last three decades this view has been a focus of considerable debate in philosophy, with implications reaching far into the concern of other disciplines as well (above all linguistics and cognitive science). It is a view that many authors have accepted, mostly on account of the prominent role played by the concept of event in the formulation and analysis of a wide variety of philosophical is- sues. However, there has not been much agreement as to the precise nature of such entities, and a range of alternative theories (along with a corresponding variety of identity and indi- viduation criteria for events) have been put forward. This volume brings together a selection of essays that have deeply influenced this debate, paving the way to an understanding of the role played by events in our representation of the world. The material is organized in five sections: (i) the role of events in the logical analysis of natural language; (ii) the metaphysical status of events; (iii) their identity and individua- tion criteria; (iv) their role in the analysis of space, time and causality; and (v) the distinction and classification of various types of events and event-like entities (such as processes and states).
    [Show full text]