Species Selection on Variability (Hierarchical Selection Theory/Emergent Characters/Aggregate Characters/Adaptation) ELISABETH A

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Species Selection on Variability (Hierarchical Selection Theory/Emergent Characters/Aggregate Characters/Adaptation) ELISABETH A Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 90, pp. 595-599, January 1993 Evolution Species selection on variability (hierarchical selection theory/emergent characters/aggregate characters/adaptation) ELISABETH A. LLOYD* AND STEPHEN JAY GOULDt *Department of Philosophy, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720; and tMuseum of Comparative Zoology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 Contributed by Stephen Jay Gould, October 14, 1992 ABSTRACT Most analyses of species selection require Gould, and others (1-7) in several articles have defended the emergent, as opposed to aggregate, characters at the species idea that selection at a particular level requires characters to level. This "emergent character" approach tends to focus on be heritable and emergent at that level and to interact with the the search for adaptations at the species level. Such an ap- environment to cause sorting. Species-level properties are proach seems to banish the most potent evolutionary property divided into aggregate and emergent characters. Aggregate of populations-variability itself-from arguments about spe- characters are based on the inherent properties of subparts cies selection (for variation is an aggregate character). We and are simple statistics of these properties, while emergent wish, instead, to extend the legitimate domain of species characters arise from the organization among subparts (ref. 4, selection to aggregate characters. This extension of selection p. 146). Possible emergent characters among species include theory to the species level wil concentrate, instead, on the population size, distribution, and composition (4). relation between fitness and the species character, whether According to this argument, which we shall call the "emer- aggregate or emergent. Examination of the role of genetic gent character" approach, one need only show that a trait in variability in the long-term evolution of clades illustrates the question is aggregate, not emergent, in order to demonstrate cogency of broadening the definition of species selection to that species are not functioning as units of selection in a include aggregate characters. We reinterpret, in this light, a particular case (1, 2, 4). classic case presented in support of species selection. As We shall contrast the emergent character approach with an originally presented, the species selection explanation ofvolutid "emergent fitness" or "interactor approach," which empha- neogastropod evolution was vulnerable to a counterinterpre- sizes the nature of fitness values, rather than type of char- tation at the organism level. Once this case is recast within a acter. Under this approach (presented in more detail in definition of species selection that reflects the essential struc- Emergent Fitness or Interactor Approach), the relationship ture and broad applicability of hierarchical selection models, between character and environment becomes the key issue. the organism-level reinterpretation ofvariability loses its force. This relationship is represented in the fitness parameters. We conclude that species selection on variability is a major Selection processes are delineated by distinctive attributes of force of macroevolution. the fitness parameters. Interactors, and hence selection pro- cesses themselves, are individuated by the contributions of their traits to fitness values in evolutionary models; the trait Selection itself can be an emergent group property or a simple sum- mation of organismic properties. This definition of an entity We begin with some basic distinctions. Most important is the undergoing selection is much more inclusive than in the difference between a process and an outcome ofthat process; emergent character approach, since an entity might have in this case, selection is the process, and evolutionary change either aggregate or emergent characters (or both); this dis- is the outcome. The process of selection involves an inter- tinction between emergent and aggregate characters does not action between an entity and its environment or, more usually appear in quantitative models of species selection specifically, between a particular trait of an entity and (e.g., see ref. 8). The emergent fitness approach requires only particular aspects of its environment. Part of the fitness that a trait have a specified relation to fitness in order to calculated for an entity represents the particular value con- support the claim that a selection process is occurring at that ferred by having a specific trait in a specific environment. In level (cf. refs. 7, 9, and 10; see Emergent Fitness orInteractor other words, the component offitness associated with a trait Approach and Appendix). is the representation, in an evolutionary model, of the pro- cess of selection. Adaptations The selection process itself must be contrasted with the result or outcome of that process. Sorting is simply the An important component ofthe emergent character approach differential birth and death of individual entities in a popu- is its focus on adaptations. The existence of an emergent lation, while selection is a potential cause ofthat sorting (ref. character at the species level is taken as equivalent to the 1, p. 217). Sorting at a particular level has a variety of existence of a potential species-level adaptation (ref. 11, p. potential causes; it can arise from selection acting at that level 388; ref. 12, p. 132). or occur as a consequence ofchance or of selection processes The focus on characters rather than fitnesses is related to at either a higher or a lower level. this requirement for adaptations. Emergent characters are always potential adaptations. Not all selection processes Species Selection produce adaptations, however. The key issue, in delineating a selection process, is the relationship between a character A number of attempts have been made to apply the basic and fitness. The emergent character approach is more re- notion of selection to the species level. Vrba, Eldredge, strictive than alternative schemas that delineate selection processes, for only some selection processes at the species The publication costs of this article were defrayed in part by page charge level (perhaps very few) result in the evolution of emergent payment. This article must therefore be hereby marked "advertisement" characters or adaptations. The emergent character approach in accordance with 18 U.S.C. §1734 solely to indicate this fact. picks out a subset of cases given by the interactor approach; 595 Downloaded by guest on September 30, 2021 596 Evolution: Lloyd and Gould Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 90 (1993) it is, to be sure, an especially interesting subset-namely, this case. This is done by describing interactors at the lower species-level adaptations. Nevertheless, if one is interested level first. If a higher-level interactor exists, the higher-level in discussing evolution by species-level selection processes correlation offitness and trait will appear as a residual fitness per se, then this approach is too restrictive.t Let us return to contribution at the lower level; we must then go to the higher the emergent fitness approach to see how aggregate traits, level in order to represent the correlation between higher- which are not adaptations, could function in a species selec- level trait and higher-level fitness. Hence, species-level fit- tion process. ness is not defined as an average or sum of the organismic fitnesses within a species (see refs. 7, 10, and 19). Emergent Fitness or Interactor Approach More simply put-the operative notion in all examples of higher-level selection is some sort of interaction effect or As the guiding idea behind our hierarchical view of selection context dependence (e.g., ref. 20; see ref. 21, chapt. 7; here, models, we hold that selection processes are best described "context" refers to the other entities in the same population in terms of interactors (see refs. 15-17). An interactor is an and not to the environment). Intuitively, the properties ofthe entity that has a trait; the interactor must interact with its other members of your group must make a difference, and environment through the trait, and the interactor's expected there must be a correlation between group type and fitness. survival and reproductive success are determined, at least One might object that the above approach to delineating partly, by this interaction. In other words, the interactor's interactors is overly reductionist. After all, it seems that this fitness covaries with the trait in question. view simply embodies G. C. Williams's famous and mislead- If we have an interactor, we should expect to find a ing maxim: don't even consider any higher level of selection correlation between the interactor's trait and the interactor's unless the lower-level model proves empirically inadequate fitness.§ For evolution by selection to occur, both the trait (ref. 22, p. 55). The problem with Williams's maxim is that and the correlation between trait and fitness must be at least different selection processes may sometimes yield identical partly heritable (in the sense of narrow heritability). Herita- gene frequency predictions. In these cases, additional infor- bility depends, in turn, on the additive genetic variance ofthe mation about population structure, group membership, and trait by definition. It should be recalled that fitness itself can group-level fitnesses is needed in order to tell which model be analyzed into components, each correlated with a trait that best fits the system at hand (see ref. 19, pp.
Recommended publications
  • Geographically Variable Biotic Interactions and Implications for Species Ranges
    ORE Open Research Exeter TITLE Geographically variable biotic interactions and implications for species ranges AUTHORS Early, R; Keith, S JOURNAL Global Ecology and Biogeography DEPOSITED IN ORE 22 November 2018 This version available at http://hdl.handle.net/10871/34864 COPYRIGHT AND REUSE Open Research Exeter makes this work available in accordance with publisher policies. A NOTE ON VERSIONS The version presented here may differ from the published version. If citing, you are advised to consult the published version for pagination, volume/issue and date of publication 1 Geographically variable biotic interactions and implications for species 2 ranges 3 Running title: Geographic variation in biotic interactions 4 Abstract: 5 The challenge: Understanding how biotic interactions affect species’ geographic ranges, biodiversity 6 patterns, and ecological responses to environmental change is one of the most pressing challenges 7 in macroecology. Extensive efforts are underway to detect signals of biotic interactions in 8 macroecological data. However, efforts are limited by bias in the taxa and spatial scale for which 9 occurrence data are available, and by difficulty in ascribing causality to co-occurrence patterns. 10 Moreover, we are not necessarily looking in the right places: analyses are largely ad hoc, depending 11 on data availability, rather than focusing on regions, taxa, ecosystems, or interaction types where 12 biotic interactions might affect species’ geographic ranges most strongly. 13 Unpicking biotic interactions: We suggest that macroecology would benefit from recognising that 14 abiotic conditions alter two key components of biotic interaction strength: frequency and intensity. 15 We outline how and why variation in biotic interaction strength occurs, explore the implications for 16 species’ geographic ranges, and discuss the challenges inherent in quantifying these effects.
    [Show full text]
  • The Flight of the Locus of Selection Some Intricate Relationships
    Behavioural Processes 161 (2019) 31–44 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Behavioural Processes journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/behavproc The flight of the locus of selection: Some intricate relationships between evolutionary elements T ⁎ April M. Becker University of North Texas, Department of Behavior Analysis, United States ARTICLE INFO ABSTRACT Keywords: Selection has enriched our understanding of the world since it was first applied to the evolution of species. Behavior Selection stands as an alternative to essentialist thinking, as a generalized and multiply applicable concept, and Selection as a causal explanation for current forms within biology and behavior. Attempts to describe selection processes Ontogenetic in a generalizable way have provided clarity about their minimal elements, such as replicators and interactors. Phylogenetic This paper discusses the interconnectedness among different levels of selection using evidence garnered from Interdisciplinary evolutionary biology, development, epigenetics, neuroscience, and behavior analysis. Currently, it appears that Evolutionary dynamics replicators and interactors may be more fluid than previously supposed and that selection for particular traits may rely on both multiple levels of interaction and multiple levels of replication. Replicators, interactors, and environment share influence on one another, and different replicators may exchange critical control over similar interactor variation as evolution proceeds. Our current understanding of selection continues to undergo revision, and reference to a number of disparate fields can help to account for the complexity of these processes. An understanding of their interconnectedness may help resolve some mysteries that develop in fields that ex- clusively focus on one or a few, such as the focused study of behavior. 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Holobionts As Units of Selection and a Model of Their Population Dynamics and Evolution
    Biological Theory https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-017-0287-1 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Holobionts as Units of Selection and a Model of Their Population Dynamics and Evolution Joan Roughgarden1,6 · Scott F. Gilbert2 · Eugene Rosenberg3 · Ilana Zilber‑Rosenberg4 · Elisabeth A. Lloyd5 Received: 15 January 2017 / Accepted: 5 September 2017 © Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research 2017 Abstract Holobionts, consisting of a host and diverse microbial symbionts, function as distinct biological entities anatomically, metabolically, immunologically, and developmentally. Symbionts can be transmitted from parent to offspring by a variety of vertical and horizontal methods. Holobionts can be considered levels of selection in evolution because they are well- defined interactors, replicators/reproducers, and manifestors of adaptation. An initial mathematical model is presented to help understand how holobionts evolve. The model offered combines the processes of horizontal symbiont transfer, within-host symbiont proliferation, vertical symbiont transmission, and holobiont selection. The model offers equations for the popula- tion dynamics and evolution of holobionts whose hologenomes differ in gene copy number, not in allelic or loci identity. The model may readily be extended to include variation among holobionts in the gene identities of both symbionts and host. Keywords Holobiont · Holobiont model · Hologenome · Level of selection · Microbiome · Microbiota · Symbiont Introduction also provides a model for the evolution of a holobiont that combines microbe and host population processes. This article discusses the concept of a holobiont—an ani- Following Lederberg and McCray (2001), a microbiome mal or plant host together with all the microbes living on or refers to an “ecological community of commensal, symbi- in it, exosymbionts and endosymbionts, respectively.
    [Show full text]
  • Individuality and Adaptation Across Levels of Selection: How Shall We Name and Generalize the Unit of Darwinism?
    Individuality and adaptation across levels of selection: How shall we name and generalize the unit of Darwinism? Stephen Jay Gould*† and Elisabeth A. Lloyd‡ *Museum of Comparative Zoology, Harvard University, 26 Oxford Street, Cambridge, MA 02138; and ‡History and Philosophy of Science, Indiana University, 130 Goodbody Hall, Bloomington, IN 47405 Contributed by Stephen Jay Gould, June 2, 1999 Two major clarifications have greatly abetted the understanding and none more pressing than learning how to think about the viscerally fruitful expansion of the theory of natural selection in recent years: unfamiliar (and in many ways counterintuitive) supraorganismal the acknowledgment that interactors, not replicators, constitute the levels of organization and selection. (Given the reductionist tradi- causal unit of selection; and the recognition that interactors are tions of Western science, we are naturally more comfortable with Darwinian individuals, and that such individuals exist with potency at suborganismal units of genes and cell lineages.) We claim that several levels of organization (genes, organisms, demes, and species evolutionists have generally not appreciated the importance of in particular), thus engendering a rich hierarchical theory of selection higher levels, particularly the species level of selection, because in contrast with Darwin’s own emphasis on the organismic level. But species-individuals may not build many adaptations of their own. a piece of the argument has been missing, and individuals at levels False emphasis on adaptation therefore leads biologists to down- distinct from organisms have been denied potency (although granted grade the species level as only weakly operative in the processes of existence within the undeniable logic of the theory), because they do selection.
    [Show full text]
  • Ideas Are Not Replicators but Minds Are
    Ideas are Not Replicators but Minds Are To appear in vol. 19(1) of Biology and Philosophy (ms # BIPH264-02). Liane Gabora [email protected] Department of Psychology University of California, Berkeley 3210 Tolman Hall, Berkeley CA 94720-1650 USA CONTENTS 1 Does Culture Evolve like Biological Lineages Do? ..................................................................... 2 2 Two Kinds of Replicators ............................................................................................................. 3 2.1 Coded Replicators ................................................................................................................. 4 2.2 Primitive Replicators ............................................................................................................. 5 3 Does Anything in Culture Constitute a Replicator? ..................................................................... 7 3.1 Ideas and Artifacts are not Coded Replicators ...................................................................... 8 3.1.1 Are Cultural Entities Interpreted ?.................................................................................. 8 3.1.2 Are Cultural Entities Copied (without Interpretation)? .................................................. 9 3.2 Interconnected Worldview as Primitive Replicator ............................................................. 10 3.2.1 Conceptual Closure ...................................................................................................... 11 4 Implications for the Evolution
    [Show full text]
  • Replicator-Interactor in Experimental Cultural Knowledge Evolution
    Replicator-Interactor in Experimental Cultural Knowledge Evolution Jérôme EUZENAT a;1 a Univ. Grenoble Alpes, Inria, CNRS, Grenoble INP, LIG, F-38000 Grenoble France Abstract. Cultural evolution may be studied at a ‘macro’ level, inspired from pop- ulation dynamics, or at a ‘micro’ level, inspired from genetics. The replicator- interactor model generalises the genotype-phenotype distinction of genetic evolu- tion. Here, we consider how it can be applied to cultural knowledge evolution ex- periments. In particular, we consider knowledge as replicator and the behaviour it induces as interactor. We show that this requires to address problems concern- ing transmission. We discuss the introduction of horizontal transmission within the replicator-interactor model and/or differential reproduction within cultural evolu- tion experiments. Keywords. evolution, cultural evolution, experimental knowledge evolution, replicator-interactor 1. Introduction: the replicator-interactor model Natural selection has been uncovered in the zoological domain at a moment when genet- ics did not exists. Since then it has gained in depth, by better understanding of the mech- anisms at stake, and in breadth, by its application to many other domains. We discuss this hereafter. 1.1. Evolution principles Natural selection can be thought of as a control mechanism based on variation, selec- tion and transmission ‘operations’ [1]. This can be implemented in computers as it had already been done for genetic programming. One of the problem with this characterisation is that it does not tell what is affected by or what performs each operation. For instance, in life sciences, there are variations of the genotype which generate variations of the phenotype in an individual.
    [Show full text]
  • Integrating Non-Feeding Interactions Into Food Webs
    Ecology Letters, (2012) 15: 291–300 doi: 10.1111/j.1461-0248.2011.01732.x IDEA AND PERSPECTIVE More than a meal… integrating non-feeding interactions into food webs Abstract Sonia Ke´ fi,1,2* Eric L. Berlow,3,4,5 Organisms eating each other are only one of many types of well documented and important interactions among Evie A. Wieters,6,7 Sergio A. species. Other such types include habitat modification, predator interference and facilitation. However, Navarrete,6 Owen L. Petchey,8,9 ecological network research has been typically limited to either pure food webs or to networks of only a few Spencer A. Wood,10 Alice Boit,11 (<3) interaction types. The great diversity of non-trophic interactions observed in nature has been poorly Lucas N. Joppa,12 Kevin D. addressed by ecologists and largely excluded from network theory. Herein, we propose a conceptual framework Lafferty,13 Richard J. Williams,12 that organises this diversity into three main functional classes defined by how they modify specific parameters Neo D. Martinez,4 Bruce A. in a dynamic food web model. This approach provides a path forward for incorporating non-trophic Menge,14 Carol A. Blanchette,15 interactions in traditional food web models and offers a new perspective on tackling ecological complexity that Alison C. Iles14 and Ulrich Brose1 should stimulate both theoretical and empirical approaches to understanding the patterns and dynamics of diverse species interactions in nature. Keywords Ecological network, ecosystem engineering, facilitation, food web, interaction modification, non-trophic interactions, trophic interactions. Ecology Letters (2012) 15: 291–300 nesting habitat for birds.
    [Show full text]
  • Generative Replication and the Evolution of Complexity
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Hertfordshire Research Archive Generative Replication and the Evolution of Complexity Geoffrey M. Hodgson and Thorbjørn Knudsen The Business School, University of Hertfordshire, De Havilland Campus, Hatfield, Hertfordshire AL10 9AB, UK [email protected] and Strategic Organization Design Unit (SOD), Department of Marketing & Management, University of Southern Denmark, Odense Campus, DK-5230, Odense M, Denmark KEY WORDS: replication, replicators, information, complexity, automata JEL classification: B52, D83 ABSTRACT This paper identifies generative replication as a form of replication which has the potential to enhance complexity in social and biological evolution, including the wondrous complexity in the biological world, and complex social institutions such as human language and business corporations. We draw inspiration from the literature on self-reproducing automata to clarify the notion of information transfer in replication processes. To enhance complexity, developmental instructions must be part of the information that is transmitted in replication. In addition to the established triple conditions of causality, similarity and information transfer, a generative replicator involves a conditional generative mechanism that can use signals from an environment and create developmental instructions. We develop a simple model, a one dimensional linear automaton that is consistent with our four proposed conditions for a generative replicator. We show that evolution within this model will indeed approach maximal complexity, but only if our four proposed conditions are not violated. Generative Replication and the Evolution of Complexity When does replication lead to greater complexity? As the origin of complex forms of organization is one of the most fundamental problems in science, this question is of considerable importance, in particular in the natural sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • The Replicator in Retrospect
    The Replicator in Retrospect Peter Godfrey-Smith Harvard University Biology and Philosophy 15 (2000): 403-423. Written for a special issue in honor of David Hull. 1. Introduction David Hull has always headed unerringly for big issues. This drive towards the fundamental is evident in his work on the nature of species, on the most general features of evolution by natural selection, and on the role of social structure in scientific change. Fittingly, given his interest in the social structure of inquiry, Hull has also contributed enormously to the social life and organization of philosophy of biology. Twenty years ago, Hull’s "Individuality and Selection" (1980) introduced his distinction between "replicators and interactors." The distinction has had several roles. One role has been to clear up misunderstandings in the "units of selection" debates. Hull also uses this framework in his selectionist account of scientific change (1988). In the present paper, my main focus will be biological. I will survey Hull's and other central discussions (section 2), then discuss recent criticisms of the replicator concept (section 3), and finally (sections 4 and 5) sketch my own view of how to understand the replicator concept and its role within evolutionary theory. 2. The Original Role of the Replicator/Interactor Distinction Let us look first at the debate to which Hull was most directly responding. In The Selfish Gene (1976), Richard Dawkins had argued that individual genes must be seen as the units of selection in evolutionary processes within sexual populations. This is primarily because the other possible candidates, notably whole organisms and groups, do not "replicate." Organisms and groups are ephemeral, like clouds in the sky or dust storms in 1 the desert.
    [Show full text]
  • Darwinism in Economics and the Evolutionary Theory of Policy-Making
    # 0910 Darwinism in Economics and the Evolutionary Theory of Policy-Making by Christian Schubert The Papers on Economics and Evolution are edited by the Evolutionary Economics Group, MPI Jena. For editorial correspondence, please contact: [email protected] Max Planck Institute of Economics ISSN 1430-4716 Evolutionary Economics Group Kahlaische Str. 10 © by the author 07745 Jena, Germany Fax: ++49-3641-686868 #0910 Darwinism in Economics and the Evolutionary Theory of Policy-Making Christian Schubert Max Planck Institute of Economics Evolutionary Economics Group Kahlaische Strasse 10 07745 Jena, Germany phone: +49-3641-686 810 fax: +49-3641-686 868 [email protected] Abstract. According to the advocates of a “Generalized Darwinism” (GD), the three core Darwinian principles of variation, selection and retention (or inheritance) can be used as a general framework for the development of theories explaining evolutionary processes in the socioeconomic domain. Even though these are originally biological terms, GD argues that they can be re-defined in such a way as to abstract from biological particulars. We argue that this approach does not only risk to misguide positive theory development, but that it may also impede the construction of a coherent evolutionary approach to “policy implications”. This is shown with respect to the positive, instrumental and normative theories such an approach is supposed to be based upon. JEL: A1, B4, B52, D6 Keywords: Evolution, Selection, Darwinism, Ontology, Continuity Hypothesis, Evolutionary Theory of Policy-Making 1 #0910 1. Introduction Evolutionary Economics is a rapidly expanding field of research that develops and applies a multitude of theoretical tools and empirical methods to explain processes of technological, organizational, institutional and commercial change (Nelson, 1995; Witt, 2008b).
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 8 the Units and Levels of Selection Samir Okasha
    Chapter 8 The Units and Levels of Selection samir okasha 1. Introduction The “units of selection” question is one of the most fundamental in evolutionary biology. Though the debate it has generated is multifaceted and complex, the basic issue is straightforward. Consider a paradigmatic Darwinian explanation – of why the average running speed in a zebra population has increased over time, for example. The explana- tion might go as follows: “in the ancestral population, zebras varied with respect to running speed. Faster zebras were better at avoiding predators than slower ones, so on average left more offspring. And running speed was heritable – the offspring of fast zebras tended to be fast runners themselves. So over time, average running speed in the population increased.” In this explanation, the “unit of selection” is the individual organism. It is the differential survival and reproduction of individual zebras that causes the evolutionary change from one generation to the next. We could also express this by saying that natural selection “acts at the level of the individual organism.” Traditional Darwinian theory treats the individual organism as the basic unit of selection. But in theory at least, there are other possibilities. For the principle of natural selection can be formulated wholly abstractly – it involves no essential reference to organisms or any other biological units. The principle tells us that if a population of entities vary in some respect, and if different variants leave different numbers of off- spring, and if offspring entities resemble their parents, then over time the composition of the population will change, ceteris paribus.
    [Show full text]
  • Replicator-Interactor in Experimental Cultural Knowledge Evolution Jérôme Euzenat
    Replicator-interactor in experimental cultural knowledge evolution Jérôme Euzenat To cite this version: Jérôme Euzenat. Replicator-interactor in experimental cultural knowledge evolution. WINKS 2019 - 2nd JOWO workshop on Interaction-Based Knowledge Sharing, Sep 2019, Graz, Austria. pp.1-11. hal-02414736 HAL Id: hal-02414736 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02414736 Submitted on 16 Dec 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution| 4.0 International License Replicator-interactor in experimental cultural knowledge evolution Jérôme EUZENAT a;1 a Univ. Grenoble Alpes, Inria, CNRS, Grenoble INP, LIG, F-38000 Grenoble France Abstract. Cultural evolution may be studied at a ‘macro’ level, inspired from pop- ulation dynamics, or at a ‘micro’ level, inspired from genetics. The replicator- interactor model generalises the genotype-phenotype distinction of genetic evolu- tion. Here, we consider how it can be applied to cultural knowledge evolution ex- periments. In particular, we consider knowledge as replicator and the behaviour it induces as interactor. We show that this requires to address problems concern- ing transmission. We discuss the introduction of horizontal transmission within the replicator-interactor model and/or differential reproduction within cultural evolu- tion experiments.
    [Show full text]