Sexual Selection for Moral Virtues

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sexual Selection for Moral Virtues Name /jlb_qrb822_3060012/820202/Mp_97 03/07/2007 04:48PM Plate # 0 pg 97 # 1 Volume 82, No. 2 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY June 2007 SEXUAL SELECTION FOR MORAL VIRTUES Geoffrey F. Miller Psychology Department, University of New Mexico Albuquerque, New Mexico 87131 USA e-mail: [email protected] keywords agreeableness, alternative mating strategies, altruism, assortative mating, behavior genetics, commitment, conscientiousness, costly signaling theory, equilibrium selection, emotion, empathy, ethics, evolutionary psychology, fitness indicators, genetic correlations, good genes, good parents, good partners, human courtship, kin selection, kindness, individual differences, intelligence, mate choice, mental health, moral virtues, mutation load, mutual choice, person perception, personality, reciprocal altruism, sexual fidelity, sexual selection, social cognition, virtue ethics “Human good turns out to be the activity of the soul exhibiting excellence.” Aristotle (350 BC) abstract Moral evolution theories have emphasized kinship, reciprocity, group selection, and equilibrium selection. Yet, moral virtues are also sexually attractive. Darwin suggested that sexual attractiveness may explain many aspects of human morality. This paper updates his argument by integrating recent research on mate choice, person perception, individual differences, costly signaling, and virtue ethics. Many human virtues may have evolved in both sexes through mutual mate choice to advertise good genetic quality, parenting abilities, and/or partner traits. Such virtues may include kindness, fidelity, magnanimity, and heroism, as well as quasi-moral traits like conscientiousness, agreeableness, mental health, and intelligence. This theory leads to many testable predictions about the phenotypic features, genetic bases, and social-cognitive responses to human moral virtues. Introduction tility, and longevity (Langlois et al. 2000; Fink MONG HUMANS, attractive bodies may and Penton-Voak 2002). This paper explores A elicit short-term desire, but attractive the possibility that some human moral traits moral traits can inspire long-term love. Is this evolved through sexual selection to serve an a coincidence, or are there some functional analogous display function. The most roman- similarities between sexual ornaments and tically attractive mental traits (i.e., kindness, moral virtues? Many sexually attractive physi- bravery, honesty, integrity, and fidelity) often cal traits evolved to reveal phenotypic condi- have a moral dimension. tion and genetic quality, including health, fer- Recent empirical research suggests that The Quarterly Review of Biology, June 2007, Vol. 82, No. 2 Copyright ᭧ 2007 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0033-5770/2007/8202-0002$15.00 97 Name /jlb_qrb822_3060012/820202/Mp_98 03/07/2007 04:48PM Plate # 0 pg 98 # 2 98 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 82 many moral traits are sexually attractive, and (Henrich and Boyd 2001; Fehr and Fisch- may serve as mental fitness indicators: they bacher 2004); are judged as reliably revealing good mental • group selection (Sober and Wilson 1998); health, brain efficiency, genetic quality, and and capacity for sustaining cooperative sexual re- • equilibrium selection among alternative lationships as well as investing in children evolutionary strategies (Boyd and Rich- (e.g., Gurven et al. 2000; Hawkes and Bliege erson 1990; Alvard and Nolin 2002). Bird 2002; Alvard and Gillespie 2004). Thus, Each of these moral evolution models has the moral virtues that we consider sexually at- led to valuable insights and progressive re- tractive are not culturally or evolutionarily ar- search traditions. Some are better at explain- bitrary. Rather, they evolved to advertise indi- ing moral virtues such as love of children, sib- vidual fitness (including genetic quality as well lings, and parents, and righteous anger at as parenting and relationship-coordination cheaters and promise-breakers. This morality- abilities) in hard-to-fake ways that can be un- through-mate-choice model also has distinc- derstood through a combination of sexual se- tive strengths and weaknesses that can ex- lection theory (Kokko et al. 2002; Andersson plain some moral virtues—especially those and Simmons 2006) and costly signaling the- that show high sexual attractiveness, assorta- ory (Gintis et al. 2001; McAndrew 2002). tive mating, phenotypic and genetic variance, (“Fitness” here means adaptive design for re- heritability, condition-dependent costs, con- productive success, or the statistical propen- spicuous display in courtship settings, and sity to survive and reproduce successfully; it young adult age peaks in display.Yet, for each may not equal achieved reproductive success of the traditional mechanisms above, sexual under evolutionarily novel conditions, espe- selection should anticipate, sharpen, and am- cially given contraception.) plify the social selection pressures to produce The hypothesis is that sexual selection a more extreme, costly, prosocial version of shaped some of our distinctively human the moral virtue than social selection could moral virtues as reliable fitness indicators. achieve alone. The reason is that nonsexual Precursors of many human virtues, such as forms of social selection can shape morality empathy, fairness, and peacemaking, have only insofar as they confer fairly concrete sur- been discovered in other great apes (Preston vival benefits (e.g., shared food, protection and de Waal 2002; Brosnan and de Waal from predators) on the morally virtuous. 2003). My claim is not that sexual selection Mate choice can shape morality much more created our moral virtues from scratch in our powerfully and broadly because it demands species alone; rather, sexual selection ampli- only that moral behaviors carry some signal- fied our standard social-primate virtues into ing value about a potential mate’s good genes uniquely elaborated human forms. and/or parent/partner abilities. In general, This mate choice model is intended to sexual selection can “supercharge” other evo- complement, not replace, other models of lutionary processes by adding positive feed- human moral evolution. Besides sexual selec- back dynamics that tend to trigger evolution- tion, various forms of social selection proba- ary innovation and speciation (Miller and bly shaped human morality, including: Todd 1995; Crespi 2004). If a moral virtue be- comes useful in kinship, reciprocity, or group • kin selection (Hamilton 1964); prosperity, our ancestors probably did not ig- • reciprocal altruism (Trivers 1971; Ridley nore it when choosing mates. 1996; Sugiyama et al. 2002); Some moral virtues may be attractive as sig- • discriminative parental solicitude (Triv- nals (e.g., heroism as a signal of compe- ers 1974; Mock and Parker 1997); tence), whereas others may seem attractive as • commitment mechanisms (Frank 1988; traits in their own right (e.g., fairness as an Nesse 2001); intrinsically valuable trait in a long-term sex- • risk-sharing mechanisms (Boone 1998; ual relationship). This distinction requires Sugiyama and Sugiyama 2003); caution, however, because there is almost al- • social norm and punishment mechanisms ways scope for misrepresenting one’s traits Name /jlb_qrb822_3060012/820202/Mp_99 03/07/2007 04:48PM Plate # 0 pg 99 # 3 June 2007 SEXUAL SELECTION FOR MORAL VIRTUES 99 during courtship. A potential mate may act behavior genetics, and moral philosophy. It agreeable and easygoing during courtship, goes beyond my book, The Mating Mind then become irritable and cantankerous af- (Miller 2000a), by emphasizing relevant em- ter a couple years. In this case, courtship- pirical and theoretical work since 2000. For agreeableness was valued as a signal of likely example, it connects recent person percep- future relationship-agreeableness, but it proved tion research with person-level approaches to unreliable. Sexual commitment often brings moral philosophy, especially virtue ethics moral disappointment. The costly signaling (Flanagan 1991; Stohr and Wellman 2002) perspective is helpful in identifying such and naturalistic approaches to understanding pitfalls—not only situations where one trait is moral intuitions (e.g., Nesse 2001; Dennett unreliably correlated with another, but also 2003). situations where the present value of a trait is I do not assume that the “virtues” histori- unreliably correlated with its future value. cally identified by philosophers will equal the From this viewpoint, all moral virtues dis- moral adaptations that can be identified in played during sexual courtship are poten- humans using standard adaptationist criteria tially fallible signals of other traits or future of special design (e.g., Andrews et al. 2002). traits, so their reliability and stability must be Nor do I assume that the idealistic reasons for analyzed in a costly signaling framework. advocating certain virtues in normative ethics To propose that human moral virtues will have anything to do with the selection evolved through mate choice is not to suggest pressures that may have actually shaped those that human morality is sexually motivated at virtues phylogenetically. So why mention vir- the level of individual behavior. Evolutionary tue ethics at all? First, virtue ethics provides a functions do not equal proximate motivations useful counterbalance to the traditional con- (Radcliffe Richards 2000; Pinker 2002). Even sequentialist (utilitarian, payoff-based) ethics if the evolutionary payoffs for moral behavior that have influenced previous
Recommended publications
  • Reflections on the Evolution of Morality Christine M. Korsgaard
    Reflections on the Evolution of Morality Christine M. Korsgaard Harvard University1 All instincts that do not discharge themselves outwardly turn inward – this is what I call the internalization of man: thus it was that man first developed what was later called his “soul.” The entire inner world, originally as thin as if it were stretched between two membranes, expanded and extended itself, acquiring depth, breadth, and height, in the same measure as outward discharge was inhibited. - Nietzsche 1. Introduction In recent years there has been a fair amount of speculation about the evolution of morality, among scientists and philosophers alike. From both points of view, the question how our moral nature might have evolved is interesting because morality is one of the traditional candidates for a distinctively human attribute, something that makes us different from the other animals. From a scientific point of view, it matters whether there are any such attributes because of the special burden they seem to place on the theory of evolution. Beginning with Darwin’s own efforts in The Descent of Man, defenders of the theory of evolution have tried to show either that there are no genuinely distinctive human attributes – that is, that any differences between human beings and the other animals are a matter of degree – or that apparently distinctive human attributes can be explained in terms of the 1 Notes on this version are incomplete. Recommended supplemental reading: “The Activity of Reason,” APA Proceedings November 09, pp. 30-38. In a way, these papers are companion pieces, or at least their final sections are.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution and Ethics 2
    It is still disputed, however, why moral behavior extends beyond a close circle of kin and reciprocal relationships: e.g., most people think stealing from anyone is wrong, not just stealing from family and friends. For moral behavior to evolve as we understand it today, there likely had to be selective pressures that pushed people to disregard their own 1000wordphilosophy.com/2018/10/11/evolution- interests in favor of their group’s interest.[3] Exactly and-ethics/ how morality extended beyond this close circle is debated, with many theories under consideration.[4] Evolution and Ethics 2. What Should We Do? Author: Michael Klenk Suppose our ability to understand and apply moral Category: Ethics, Philosophy of Science rules, as typically understood, can be explained by Word Count: 999 natural selection. Does evolution explain which rules We often follow what are considered basic moral we should follow?[5] rules: don’t steal, don’t lie, help others when we can. Some answer, “yes!” “Greed captures the essence of But why do we follow these rules, or any rules the evolutionary spirit,” says the fictional character understood as “moral rules”? Does evolution explain Gordon Gekko in the 1987 film Wall Street: “Greed why? If so, does evolution have implications for … is good. Greed is right.”[6] which rules we should follow, and whether we genuinely know this? Gekko’s claims about what is good and right and what we ought to be comes from what he thinks we This essay explores the relations between evolution naturally are: we are greedy, so we ought to be and morality, including evolution’s potential greedy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolution of Animal Play, Emotions, and Social Morality: on Science, Theology, Spirituality, Personhood, and Love
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 12-2001 The Evolution of Animal Play, Emotions, and Social Morality: On Science, Theology, Spirituality, Personhood, and Love Marc Bekoff University of Colorado Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/acwp_sata Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Behavior and Ethology Commons, and the Comparative Psychology Commons Recommended Citation Bekoff, M. (2001). The evolution of animal play, emotions, and social morality: on science, theology, spirituality, personhood, and love. Zygon®, 36(4), 615-655. This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Evolution of Animal Play, Emotions, and Social Morality: On Science, Theology, Spirituality, Personhood, and Love Marc Bekoff University of Colorado KEYWORDS animal emotions, animal play, biocentric anthropomorphism, critical anthropomorphism, personhood, social morality, spirituality ABSTRACT My essay first takes me into the arena in which science, spirituality, and theology meet. I comment on the enterprise of science and how scientists could well benefit from reciprocal interactions with theologians and religious leaders. Next, I discuss the evolution of social morality and the ways in which various aspects of social play behavior relate to the notion of “behaving fairly.” The contributions of spiritual and religious perspectives are important in our coming to a fuller understanding of the evolution of morality. I go on to discuss animal emotions, the concept of personhood, and how our special relationships with other animals, especially the companions with whom we share our homes, help us to define our place in nature, our humanness.
    [Show full text]
  • How Morality Evolved Doug Mann
    HANNAH WALLACE: CRISIS IN TURKISH EDUCATION CELEBRATING REASON AND HUMANITY February/March 2019 Vol. 39 No. 2 HOW MORALITY EVOLVED DOUG MANN LINDA KAY KLEIN Dissects the Christian Purity Movement F/M 17 $5.95 CDN $5.95 US $5.95 Tom Flynn | Faisal Saeed Al Mutar 03 Robert M. Price | S. T. Joshi Poetry by Max Jacob Published by the Center for Inquiry in association 0 74470 74957 8 with the Council for Secular Humanism For many, mere atheism (the absence of belief in gods and the supernatural) or agnosticism (the view that such questions cannot be answered) aren’t enough. It’s liberating to recognize that supernatural beings are human creations … that there’s no such thing as “spirit” or “transcendence”… that people are undesigned, unintended, and responsible for themselves. But what’s next? Atheism and agnosticism are silent on larger questions of values and meaning. If Meaning in life is not ordained from on high, what small-m meanings can we work out among ourselves? If eternal life is an illusion, how can we make the most of our only lives? As social beings sharing a godless world, how should we coexist? For the questions that remain unanswered after we’ve cleared our minds of gods and souls and spirits, many atheists, agnostics, skeptics, and freethinkers turn to secular humanism. Secular. “Pertaining to the world or things not spiritual or sacred.” Humanism. “Any system of thought or action concerned with the interests or ideals of people … the intellectual and cultural movement … characterized by an emphasis on human interests rather than … religion.” — Webster’s Dictionary Secular humanism is a comprehensive, nonreligious life stance incorporating: A naturalistic philosophy A cosmic outlook rooted in science, and A consequentialist ethical system in which acts are judged not by their conformance to preselected norms but by their consequences for men and women in the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution of Morality Debate on Philosophy Forum, Mar 2004 This Discussion Eventually Wanders Into a Debate on Absolute Certainty
    Evolution of Morality Debate on Philosophy Forum, Mar 2004 This discussion eventually wanders into a debate on absolute certainty. All quotations are in red. All responses to quotations by John Donovan unless otherwise noted. Quote: Originally Posted by Mariner I much prefer Dennett's "Darwin's Dangerous Idea" to Dawkins' "The Blind Watchmaker" by the way. Dawkins is too fond of hyperboles, and his arguments are often weak. Unlike Dennett's. I enjoy both authors immensely, though it is true that Dawkins sometimes writes in a somewhat pugalistic and shall we say, exuberant tone. But it makes for entertaining reading, for example have you read this very funny piece? http://www.physics.nyu.edu/faculty/sokal/dawkins.html In any case, both Dawkins and Dennett are clearly philosophical "soulmates". I can't imagine two men more in tune with each others ideas on so many issues. Just look at how Dennett has latched on to Dawkins' "memes" concept and applied it to his theory of consciousness. There is a discussion on this here for those interested in the link between language and the evolution of consciousness: http://forums.philosophyforums.com/...read.php?t=6031 Apologies in advance for the thread promotion. By Probeman (John Donovan) Quote: Originally Posted by jamespetts A characteristic, no doubt, with a strong genetic influence ;-) Seriously, I think there is something to this. Although I would say a strong "memetic" influence, instead. It makes sense to consider the idea that religious beliefs, such as the idea that we are the apple of God's eye, or the chosen people or that the universe was created just for us, etc., are all evolved memes that enhance human (social?) survival.
    [Show full text]
  • The Biological Sciences Can Act As a Ground for Ethics” in Ayala, Francisco and Arp, Robert, Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology
    1 This chapter to be published as: Ruse, Michael (2009). “The Biological Sciences Can Act as a Ground for Ethics” in Ayala, Francisco and Arp, Robert, Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. The Biological Sciences Can Act as a Ground for Ethics Michael Ruse Ethics is an illusion put in place by natural selection to make us good cooperators. – Michael Ruse and Edward O. Wilson (1985) This paper is interested in the relationship between evolutionary thinking and moral behavior and commitments, ethics. There is a traditional way of forging or conceiving of the relationship. This is traditional evolutionary ethics, known as Social Darwinism. Many think that this position is morally pernicious, a re- description of the worst aspects of modern, laissez-faire capitalism in fancy biological language. It is argued that, in fact, there is much more to be said for Social Darwinism than many think. In respects, it could be and was an enlightened position to take; but it flounders on the matter of justification. Universally, the appeal is to progress—evolution is progressive and, hence, morally we should aid its success. I argue, however, that this progressive nature of evolution is far from obvious and, hence, traditional social Darwinism fails. There is another way to do things. This is to argue that the search for justification is mistaken. Ethics just is. It is an adaptation for humans living socially and has exactly the same status as other adaptations, like hands and teeth and genitalia. As such, ethics is something with no standing beyond what it is.
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolved Functions of Procedural Fairness: an Adaptation for Politics
    March 2015 The Evolved Functions of Procedural Fairness: An Adaptation for Politics Troels Bøggild Department of Political Science Aarhus University, Denmark E-mail: [email protected] Michael Bang Petersen Department of Political Science Aarhus University, Denmark E-mail: [email protected] Chapter accepted for publication in Todd K. Shackelford & Ranald D. Hansen (Eds.), The Evolution of Morality, New York: Springer. 1 Abstract: Politics is the process of determining resource allocations within and between groups. Group life has constituted a critical and enduring part of human evolutionary history and we should expect the human mind to contain psychological adaptations for dealing with political problems. Previous research has in particular focused on adaptations designed to produce moral evaluations of political outcomes: is the allocation of resources fair? People, however, are not only concerned about outcomes. They also readily produce moral evaluations of the political processes that shape these outcomes. People have a sense of procedural fairness. In this chapter, we identify the adaptive functions of the human psychology of procedural fairness. We argue that intuitions about procedural fairness evolved to deal with adaptive problems related to the delegation of leadership and, specifically, to identify and counter-act exploitative leaders. In the chapter, we first introduce the concept of procedural fairness, review extant social psychological theories and make the case for why an evolutionary approach is needed. Next, we dissect the evolved functions of procedural fairness and review extant research in favor of the evolutionary account. Finally, we discuss how environmental mismatches between ancestral and modern politics make procedural fairness considerations even more potent in modern politics, creating a powerful source of moral outrage.
    [Show full text]
  • The Natures of Universal Moralities, 75 Brook
    Brooklyn Law Review Volume 75 Issue 2 SYMPOSIUM: Article 4 Is Morality Universal, and Should the Law Care? 2009 The aN tures of Universal Moralities Bailey Kuklin Follow this and additional works at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/blr Recommended Citation Bailey Kuklin, The Natures of Universal Moralities, 75 Brook. L. Rev. (2009). Available at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/blr/vol75/iss2/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at BrooklynWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Brooklyn Law Review by an authorized editor of BrooklynWorks. The Natures of Universal Moralities Bailey Kuklin† One of the abiding lessons from postmodernism is that reason does not go all the way down.1 In the context of this symposium, one cannot deductively derive a universal morality from incontestible moral primitives,2 or practical reason alone.3 Instead, even reasoned moral systems must ultimately be grounded on intuition,4 a sense of justice. The question then † Professor of Law, Brooklyn Law School. I wish to thank the presenters and participants of the Brooklyn Law School Symposium entitled “Is Morality Universal, and Should the Law Care?” and those at the Tenth SEAL Scholarship Conference. Further thanks go to Brooklyn Law School for supporting this project with a summer research stipend. 1 “Simplifying to the extreme, I define postmodern as incredulity toward metanarratives.” JEAN-FRANCOIS LYOTARD, THE POSTMODERN CONDITION: A REPORT ON KNOWLEDGE xxiv (Geoff Bennington & Brian Massumi trans., 1984). “If modernity is viewed with Weberian optimism as the project of rationalisation of the life-world, an era of material progress, social emancipation and scientific innovation, the postmodern is derided as chaotic, catastrophic, nihilistic, the end of good order.” COSTAS DOUZINAS ET AL., POSTMODERN JURISPRUDENCE 16 (1991).
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Two: the Evolution of Morality: the Emergence of Personhood
    HTS Teologiese Studies/Theological Studies ISSN: (Online) 2072-8050, (Print) 0259-9422 Page 1 of 11 Original Research Lecture two: The evolution of morality: The emergence of personhood Author: In a series of three articles, presented at the Goshen Annual Conference on Science and Religion 1,2 J. Wentzel van Huyssteen in 2015, with the theme ‘Interdisciplinary Theology and the Archeology of Personhood’, J. Affiliations: Wentzel van Huyssteen considers the problem of human evolution – also referred to as ‘the 1Princeton Theological archaeology of personhood’ – and its broader impact on theological anthropology. This Seminary, United States trajectory of lectures tracks a select number of challenging contemporary proposals for the evolution of crucially important aspects of human personhood. Lecture Two argues that, on a 2Faculty of Theology, postfoundationalist view, some of our religious beliefs are indeed more plausible and credible Stellenbosch University, South Africa than others. This also goes for our tendency to moralise and for the strong moral convictions, we often hold. It demonstrates that, in spite of a powerful focus on the evolutionary origins of Corresponding author: moral awareness, ethics emerge on a culturally autonomous level, which means that the J. Wentzel van Huyssteen, wentzel.vanhuyssteen@ epistemic standing of the particular moral judgements human beings make is independent of ptsem.edu whatever the natural sciences can says about their genesis. Dates: Received: 09 Dec. 2016 Accepted: 21 Aug. 2017 Introduction Published: 30 Nov. 2017 As we saw in the first lecture, it is the materiality of our embodied existence that has come about through the long process of biological evolution and has given us what seems to be a unique How to cite this article: Van Huyssteen, J.W., 2017, human sense of self.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Reputation: an Evolutionary and Cognitive Perspective
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Goldstone Research Unit Philosophy, Politics and Economics 10-29-2012 Moral Reputation: An Evolutionary and Cognitive Perspective Dan Sperber Nicolas Baumard Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/goldstone Part of the Cognitive Psychology Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, and the Theory and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Sperber, D., & Baumard, N. (2012). Moral Reputation: An Evolutionary and Cognitive Perspective. Mind & Language, 27 (5), 495-518. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/mila.12000 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/goldstone/8 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Moral Reputation: An Evolutionary and Cognitive Perspective Abstract From an evolutionary point of view, the function of moral behaviour may be to secure a good reputation as a co-operator. The best way to do so may be to obey genuine moral motivations. Still, one's moral reputation maybe something too important to be entrusted just to one's moral sense. A robust concern for one's reputation is likely to have evolved too. Here we explore some of the complex relationships between morality and reputation both from an evolutionary and a cognitive point of view. Disciplines Cognitive Psychology | Ethics and Political Philosophy | Theory and Philosophy This journal article is available at ScholarlyCommons: https://repository.upenn.edu/goldstone/8 Moral reputation: An evolutionary and cognitive perspective* Dan SPERBER and Nicolas BAUMARD Abstract: From an evolutionary point of view, the function of moral behaviour may be to secure a good reputation as a co-operator. The best way to do so may be to obey genuine moral motivations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Morality of Evolutionarily Self-Interested Rescues
    Brooklyn Law School BrooklynWorks Faculty Scholarship 2006 The orM ality of Evolutionarily Self-Interested Rescues Bailey Kuklin Follow this and additional works at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/faculty Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons, and the Torts Commons Recommended Citation 40 Ariz. St. L. J. 453 (2008) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by BrooklynWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of BrooklynWorks. THE MORALITY OF EVOLUTIONARILY SELF- INTERESTED RESCUES Bailey Kuklint Introduction ................................................................................................ 453 I. The Rescue Doctrine and Evolutionary Psychology ............................ 456 A . "Peril Invites R escue" ................................................................... 456 B. Evolutionary Psychology ............................................................... 457 1. Kin Selection ............................................................................ 458 2. R eciprocal A ltruism ................................................................. 459 3. Sexual Selection ....................................................................... 466 C. Evolutionary Behavioral Maxims .................................................. 469 II. M orality of R escue ............................................................................... 473 A . U tilitarianism .................................................................................. 477
    [Show full text]
  • The Question of Non Human Primates Morality
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Mateusz Stępień provided by Jagiellonian Univeristy Repository THE QUESTION OF NON HUMAN PRIMATES MORALITY He who understands baboons would do more toward metaphysics than Locke. Ch. Darwin, Notebook Introduction Walking in Darwin’s footsteps, numerous researchers have turned toward evolutionary theory for “the examination of a hypothesis concerning the factual matter of whether, and in what sense, and to what degree, human morality is the product of the process of biological natural selection.”1 The questions of morality have been partly taken over from the hands of philosophers and “biologized” as E.O. Wilson already recommended more than three decades ago.2 In spite of the fundamental disputes undertaken in general evolutionary theory, many specifi c empirical disciplines work on the adequate description and explication of partic- ular morality-related issues. Neuroscience tries to map the “moral brain,” mean- while by examining children in their earliest years, developmental psychology studies ontogenetic changes in the processes of moral reasoning and the emer- gence of the distinction between moral and other norms. Moral psychology stud- ies universal cognitive and emotional psychological mechanisms related with morality (e.g. moral judgments, moral dilemmas) and “universal across cultures moral domains.” Recently, primatology has also contributed to the “biologizing of morality” enterprise, mainly by searching for and examining “proto-morality” or “the evolutionary building blocks of morality” in non human primates (hereafter termed NHP). The primatological studies are a part of the emerging literature on the “animal morality” question,3 but without a doubt research on NHP cur- 1 R.
    [Show full text]