Four Condorcet-Hare Hybrid Methods for Single-Winner Elections

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Load more

Four Condorcet-Hare Hybrid Methods for Single-Winner Elections James Green-Armytage The weakness of this guideline is that it does [email protected] not specify what majority rule requires when there is no Condorcet winner. For these Abstract situations, the Smith set provides a useful This paper examines four single-winner generalization of the Condorcet winner election methods, denoted here as concept. The Smith set is the smallest set Woodall, Benham, Smith-AV, and such that any candidate in would win a one- Tideman, that all make use of both on-one race against any candidate not in . Condorcet’s pairwise comparison Thus the Smith principle, which requires voting principle and Hare’s elimination and rules to select winning candidates from the reallocation principle used in the Smith set, is an extension of the Condorcet alternative vote. These methods have principle that is applicable to all election many significant properties in common, 2 including Smith efficiency and relatively outcomes. For example, suppose that A is strong resistance to strategic manipu- preferred by a majority to B, B is preferred by a lation, though they differ with regard to majority to C, C is preferred by a majority to A, the minor properties of ‘Smith-IIA’ and and all three of these candidates are preferred ‘mono-add-plump’. by majorities to D. In this case, electing A, B, or C is consistent with the majority rule 1 Introduction guideline provided by the Smith principle, but electing D is not. Several election methods have been The concept of majority rule is trickier than proposed that satisfy the Smith principle. most people realize. When there are only two Among them are ranked pairs,3 beatpath,4 candidates in an election, then its meaning is river,5 Kemeny,6 Nanson,7 and Copeland.8 quite clear: it tells us that the candidate with the However, the four methods on which this paper most votes is elected. However, when there are focuses possess another property, in addition to more than two candidates, and no single Smith efficiency, that makes them particularly candidate is the first choice of a majority, the interesting: they appear to be unusually meaning is no longer obvious. resistant to strategic manipulation. Therefore, The Condorcet principle1 offers a plausible if a society wishes to choose among multiple guideline for the meaning of majority rule in options by majority rule given one balloting, multi-candidate elections: if voters rank and if it wishes to minimize the probability that candidates in order of preference, and these rankings indicate that there is a candidate who would win a majority of votes in a one-on-one 2 Smith (1973) refers to his idea as a generalization race against any other candidate on the ballot (a of Condorcet consistency. 3 Defined in Tideman (1987). Condorcet winner), then we may interpret 4 ‘majority rule’ as requiring his election. Defined in Schulze (2003). 5 Defined in Heitzig (2004). 6 Defined in Kemeny (1959). 7 See Tideman (2006), page 201–203. 1 Condorcet (1785) defines this principle. 8 Defined in Copeland (1951). 1 James Green-Armytage: Condorcet-Hare Hybrid Methods voters will have an incentive to behave voters who rank candidate ahead of candidate strategically, these methods are worthy of . If , then pairwise-beats . strong consideration. These four methods also share the character- Condorcet winner: A candidate who wins all istic of employing the ‘Hare principle’, that is, of his pairwise comparisons. Formally, is a the principle of eliminating the candidate with Condorcet winner if and only if the fewest first-choice votes and reallocating ,. 9 those votes to other candidates. Condorcet method: Any single-winner voting I will use the names Woodall, Benham, rule that always elects the Condorcet winner Smith-AV, and Tideman to refer to these rules, when one exists. as they do not have standard names. They are deeply similar to one another and will choose Majority rule cycle: A situation in which each the same winner in the vast majority of cases, of the candidates suffers at least one pairwise but they are not identical. The purpose of this defeat, so that there is no Condorcet winner. paper is to provide a solid understanding of Formally, , : . how these methods work, how they differ from The Alternative Vote (AV):11 The candidate one another, and how they compare to other with the fewest first choice votes (ballots single-winner methods. ranking the candidate above all others in the race) is eliminated. The process is repeated 2 Preliminary Definitions until only one candidate remains. Formally, in each round 1,…,1, we Assume that there are candidates and perform the following operations: voters. Let be a tiebreaking vector that gives 1 0 a unique score 0,1 to each candidate , : 0 ,,. 1,…,; can be random, predetermined, or determined by a tie-breaking ranking of ∑ ,. candidates.10 Let be a vector of candidate argmin. ∞. Ω . eliminations, such that is initially set to zero for each candidate 1,…,. Let denote After round 1, argmin, and Ω . the winning candidate. Let be the utility of Here, is a by matrix indicating voter for candidate . Let be the ranking that voter gives to candidate (such that individual voters’ top choices. is a length- lower-numbered rankings are better). All vector of the candidates’ first choice vote totals, voting methods described in this paper, with the which incorporates the unique fractional values exception of approval voting and range voting, in the tiebreaking vector in order to ensure begin with the voters ranking the candidates in that there will not be a tie for plurality loser. order of preference. Infinity can be added to the values of eliminated candidates to prevent them from Pairwise comparison: An imaginary head-to- being identified as the plurality loser in head contest between two candidates, in which subsequent rounds. The vector Ω gives an each voter is assumed to vote for the candidate ‘elimination score’ for each candidate, which whom he gives a better ranking to. Formally, will be used by the Woodall method. let ∑ 1 be the number of Smith set:12 Or, the ‘minimal dominant set’. The smallest set of candidates such that every 9 Thomas Hare offered the first voting procedure that included the iterative transfer of votes from plurality 11 Also known as instant runoff voting (IRV) and as losers to candidates ranked next on ballots. See the Hare method, the alternative vote (AV) is the Hoag and Hallett (1926, 162–95). The first person application of proportional representation by the to apply the ‘Hare principle’ to the election of a single transferable vote (STV) to the case of electing single candidate was Robert Ware, in 1871. See one candidate. Reilly (2001, 33–34). 12 This is so named because of Smith (1973). 10 See Zavist and Tideman (1989). Schwartz (1986) refers to the Smith set as the Voting matters, Issue 29 2 James Green-Armytage: Condorcet-Hare Hybrid Methods candidate inside the set is preferred by some process repeats until there is such a candidate, majority of the voters to every candidate who is then declared the winner. outside the set. When there is a Condorcet Formally, in each round we determine winner, it is the only member of the Smith set. whether Formally, the Smith set is the set of candidates such that these conditions hold: : ,: 0 0. If so, then , and the process stops. Other- , , . wise, we perform these calculations: :, , . 1 0 , : 0 , , . 3 Method Definitions ∑ ,. Woodall method:13 Score candidates according argmin. ∞. to their elimination scores, and choose the Then, we proceed to the next round. Smith set candidate with best score. 15 That is, define each candidate’s elimination Smith-AV method: Eliminate candidates not in the Smith set, and then conduct an AV tally score as the round in which he is eliminated by among remaining candidates. AV. (The AV winner is not eliminated, so we set his score to .) If the Smith set has only one Tideman method:16 Alternate between elimin- member, then this is the Woodall winner; ating all candidates outside the Smith set, and otherwise, the winner is the candidate from eliminating the plurality loser, until one inside the Smith set who has the best candidate remains. elimination score. That is, as in Smith-AV, we begin by Formally, we begin with the definitions of eliminating all candidates outside the Smith set. the AV method and Smith set as given above. If this leaves only one candidate (a Condorcet Then, Υ 1 Ω ,, and winner), then he is elected. Otherwise, we eliminate the candidate with the fewest first argmaxΥ. choice votes. Then, we recalculate the Smith Benham method:14 Eliminate the plurality set, and eliminate any candidates who were in it loser until there is a Condorcet winner. before but are no longer in it as a result of the That is, if there is a Condorcet winner, he is plurality loser elimination. These two steps also the Woodall winner. Otherwise, the repeat until only one candidate (the winner) method eliminates the candidate with the remains. fewest first-choice votes, and checks to see Formally, in stage 1, we define or re-define whether there is a candidate who beats all other according to the following conditions: non-eliminated candidates pairwise. This , : 0, . , 0. : GETCHA set, and also defines another set called the GOCHA set, which is now also known as the ,: 0, . Schwartz set. The Schwartz set is the union of Then, we make the following adjustment to the minimal undominated sets, where an undominated vector: ∞. set is a set such that no member of the set is In stage 2, we perform the following pairwise-defeated by a non-member.
Recommended publications
  • A Generalization of the Minisum and Minimax Voting Methods

    A Generalization of the Minisum and Minimax Voting Methods

    A Generalization of the Minisum and Minimax Voting Methods Shankar N. Sivarajan Undergraduate, Department of Physics Indian Institute of Science Bangalore 560 012, India [email protected] Faculty Advisor: Prof. Y. Narahari Deparment of Computer Science and Automation Revised Version: December 4, 2017 Abstract In this paper, we propose a family of approval voting-schemes for electing committees based on the preferences of voters. In our schemes, we calcu- late the vector of distances of the possible committees from each of the ballots and, for a given p-norm, choose the one that minimizes the magni- tude of the distance vector under that norm. The minisum and minimax methods suggested by previous authors and analyzed extensively in the literature naturally appear as special cases corresponding to p = 1 and p = 1; respectively. Supported by examples, we suggest that using a small value of p; such as 2 or 3, provides a good compromise between the minisum and minimax voting methods with regard to the weightage given to approvals and disapprovals. For large but finite p; our method reduces to finding the committee that covers the maximum number of voters, and this is far superior to the minimax method which is prone to ties. We also discuss extensions of our methods to ternary voting. 1 Introduction In this paper, we consider the problem of selecting a committee of k members out of n candidates based on preferences expressed by m voters. The most common way of conducting this election is to allow each voter to select his favorite candidate and vote for him/her, and we select the k candidates with the most number of votes.
  • 1 Introduction 2 Condorcet and Borda Tallies

    1 Introduction 2 Condorcet and Borda Tallies

    1 Introduction General introduction goes here. 2 Condorcet and Borda Tallies 2.1 Definitions We are primarily interested in comparing the behaviors of two information aggregation methods, namely the Condorcet and Borda tallies. This interest is motivated by both historical and practical concerns: the relative merits of the two methods have been argued since the 18th century, and, although variations on the Borda tally are much more common in practice, there is a significant body of theoretical evidence that the Condorcet tally is in many cases superior. To begin, we provide formal definitions of both of these methods, and of a generalized information aggregation problem. An information aggregation problem, often referred to simply as a voting problem, is a problem which involves taking information from a number of disparate sources, and using this information to produce a single output. Problems of this type arise in numerous domains. In political science, they are common, occurring whenever voters cast votes which are used to decide 1 the outcome of some issue. Although less directly, they also occur in fields as diverse as control theory and cognitive science. Wherever there is a system which must coalesce information from its subsystems, there is potentially the need to balance conflicting information about a single topic. In any such circumstance, if there is not reason to trust any single source more than the others, the problem can be phrased as one of information aggregation. 2.1.1 Information Aggregation Problems To facilitate the formalization of these problems, we only consider cases in which a finite number of information sources (which shall henceforth be re- ferred to as voters) provide information regarding some contested issue.
  • Are Condorcet and Minimax Voting Systems the Best?1

    Are Condorcet and Minimax Voting Systems the Best?1

    1 Are Condorcet and Minimax Voting Systems the Best?1 Richard B. Darlington Cornell University Abstract For decades, the minimax voting system was well known to experts on voting systems, but was not widely considered to be one of the best systems. But in recent years, two important experts, Nicolaus Tideman and Andrew Myers, have both recognized minimax as one of the best systems. I agree with that. This paper presents my own reasons for preferring minimax. The paper explicitly discusses about 20 systems. Comments invited. [email protected] Copyright Richard B. Darlington May be distributed free for non-commercial purposes Keywords Voting system Condorcet Minimax 1. Many thanks to Nicolaus Tideman, Andrew Myers, Sharon Weinberg, Eduardo Marchena, my wife Betsy Darlington, and my daughter Lois Darlington, all of whom contributed many valuable suggestions. 2 Table of Contents 1. Introduction and summary 3 2. The variety of voting systems 4 3. Some electoral criteria violated by minimax’s competitors 6 Monotonicity 7 Strategic voting 7 Completeness 7 Simplicity 8 Ease of voting 8 Resistance to vote-splitting and spoiling 8 Straddling 8 Condorcet consistency (CC) 8 4. Dismissing eight criteria violated by minimax 9 4.1 The absolute loser, Condorcet loser, and preference inversion criteria 9 4.2 Three anti-manipulation criteria 10 4.3 SCC/IIA 11 4.4 Multiple districts 12 5. Simulation studies on voting systems 13 5.1. Why our computer simulations use spatial models of voter behavior 13 5.2 Four computer simulations 15 5.2.1 Features and purposes of the studies 15 5.2.2 Further description of the studies 16 5.2.3 Results and discussion 18 6.
  • Free PDF Version

    Free PDF Version

    TONY CZARNECKI POSTHUMANS - II Democracy For a Human Federation REFORMING DEMOCRACY FOR HUMANITY’S COEXISTENCE WITH SUPERINTELLIGENCE London, July 2020 Democracy for a Human Federation Reforming Democracy for Humanity’s Coexistence with Superintelligence © Tony Czarnecki 2020 The right of Tony Czarnecki to be identified as the author of this book has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. This edition, July 2020 First published in 2019 by Sustensis ISBN: 9781689622332 London, July 2020 For any questions or comments please visit: http://www.sustensis.co.uk 2 For my grandson Leon 3 TABLE OF CONTENTS POSTHUMANS - II ................................................................................................................................ 1 FOREWORD TO POSTHUMANS SERIES ........................................................................................ 7 INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................................... 8 PART 1 A PERILOUS ROAD TOWARDS A HUMAN FEDERATION ........................................ 11 CHAPTER 1 HUMANITY AT A TURNING POINT ........................................................................ 12 WHAT MAKES US HUMAN? ................................................................................................................. 12 LIVING IN THE WORLD OF EXPONENTIAL CHANGE ............................................................................. 13 IS THIS THE END OF HISTORY? ...........................................................................................................
  • Stable Voting

    Stable Voting

    Stable Voting Wesley H. Hollidayy and Eric Pacuitz y University of California, Berkeley ([email protected]) z University of Maryland ([email protected]) September 12, 2021 Abstract In this paper, we propose a new single-winner voting system using ranked ballots: Stable Voting. The motivating principle of Stable Voting is that if a candidate A would win without another candidate B in the election, and A beats B in a head-to-head majority comparison, then A should still win in the election with B included (unless there is another candidate A0 who has the same kind of claim to winning, in which case a tiebreaker may choose between A and A0). We call this principle Stability for Winners (with Tiebreaking). Stable Voting satisfies this principle while also having a remarkable ability to avoid tied outcomes in elections even with small numbers of voters. 1 Introduction Voting reform efforts in the United States have achieved significant recent successes in replacing Plurality Voting with Instant Runoff Voting (IRV) for major political elections, including the 2018 San Francisco Mayoral Election and the 2021 New York City Mayoral Election. It is striking, by contrast, that Condorcet voting methods are not currently used in any political elections.1 Condorcet methods use the same ranked ballots as IRV but replace the counting of first-place votes with head- to-head comparisons of candidates: do more voters prefer candidate A to candidate B or prefer B to A? If there is a candidate A who beats every other candidate in such a head-to-head majority comparison, this so-called Condorcet winner wins the election.
  • Single-Winner Voting Method Comparison Chart

    Single-Winner Voting Method Comparison Chart

    Single-winner Voting Method Comparison Chart This chart compares the most widely discussed voting methods for electing a single winner (and thus does not deal with multi-seat or proportional representation methods). There are countless possible evaluation criteria. The Criteria at the top of the list are those we believe are most important to U.S. voters. Plurality Two- Instant Approval4 Range5 Condorcet Borda (FPTP)1 Round Runoff methods6 Count7 Runoff2 (IRV)3 resistance to low9 medium high11 medium12 medium high14 low15 spoilers8 10 13 later-no-harm yes17 yes18 yes19 no20 no21 no22 no23 criterion16 resistance to low25 high26 high27 low28 low29 high30 low31 strategic voting24 majority-favorite yes33 yes34 yes35 no36 no37 yes38 no39 criterion32 mutual-majority no41 no42 yes43 no44 no45 yes/no 46 no47 criterion40 prospects for high49 high50 high51 medium52 low53 low54 low55 U.S. adoption48 Condorcet-loser no57 yes58 yes59 no60 no61 yes/no 62 yes63 criterion56 Condorcet- no65 no66 no67 no68 no69 yes70 no71 winner criterion64 independence of no73 no74 yes75 yes/no 76 yes/no 77 yes/no 78 no79 clones criterion72 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 monotonicity yes no no yes yes yes/no yes criterion80 prepared by FairVote: The Center for voting and Democracy (April 2009). References Austen-Smith, David, and Jeffrey Banks (1991). “Monotonicity in Electoral Systems”. American Political Science Review, Vol. 85, No. 2 (June): 531-537. Brewer, Albert P. (1993). “First- and Secon-Choice Votes in Alabama”. The Alabama Review, A Quarterly Review of Alabama History, Vol. ?? (April): ?? - ?? Burgin, Maggie (1931). The Direct Primary System in Alabama.
  • Who Gains from Apparentments Under D'hondt?

    Who Gains from Apparentments Under D'hondt?

    CIS Working Paper No 48, 2009 Published by the Center for Comparative and International Studies (ETH Zurich and University of Zurich) Who gains from apparentments under D’Hondt? Dr. Daniel Bochsler University of Zurich Universität Zürich Who gains from apparentments under D’Hondt? Daniel Bochsler post-doctoral research fellow Center for Comparative and International Studies Universität Zürich Seilergraben 53 CH-8001 Zürich Switzerland Centre for the Study of Imperfections in Democracies Central European University Nador utca 9 H-1051 Budapest Hungary [email protected] phone: +41 44 634 50 28 http://www.bochsler.eu Acknowledgements I am in dept to Sebastian Maier, Friedrich Pukelsheim, Peter Leutgäb, Hanspeter Kriesi, and Alex Fischer, who provided very insightful comments on earlier versions of this paper. Manuscript Who gains from apparentments under D’Hondt? Apparentments – or coalitions of several electoral lists – are a widely neglected aspect of the study of proportional electoral systems. This paper proposes a formal model that explains the benefits political parties derive from apparentments, based on their alliance strategies and relative size. In doing so, it reveals that apparentments are most beneficial for highly fractionalised political blocs. However, it also emerges that large parties stand to gain much more from apparentments than small parties do. Because of this, small parties are likely to join in apparentments with other small parties, excluding large parties where possible. These arguments are tested empirically, using a new dataset from the Swiss national parliamentary elections covering a period from 1995 to 2007. Keywords: Electoral systems; apparentments; mechanical effect; PR; D’Hondt. Apparentments, a neglected feature of electoral systems Seat allocation rules in proportional representation (PR) systems have been subject to widespread political debate, and one particularly under-analysed subject in this area is list apparentments.
  • A Canadian Model of Proportional Representation by Robert S. Ring A

    A Canadian Model of Proportional Representation by Robert S. Ring A

    Proportional-first-past-the-post: A Canadian model of Proportional Representation by Robert S. Ring A thesis submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Political Science Memorial University St. John’s, Newfoundland and Labrador May 2014 ii Abstract For more than a decade a majority of Canadians have consistently supported the idea of proportional representation when asked, yet all attempts at electoral reform thus far have failed. Even though a majority of Canadians support proportional representation, a majority also report they are satisfied with the current electoral system (even indicating support for both in the same survey). The author seeks to reconcile these potentially conflicting desires by designing a uniquely Canadian electoral system that keeps the positive and familiar features of first-past-the- post while creating a proportional election result. The author touches on the theory of representative democracy and its relationship with proportional representation before delving into the mechanics of electoral systems. He surveys some of the major electoral system proposals and options for Canada before finally presenting his made-in-Canada solution that he believes stands a better chance at gaining approval from Canadians than past proposals. iii Acknowledgements First of foremost, I would like to express my sincerest gratitude to my brilliant supervisor, Dr. Amanda Bittner, whose continuous guidance, support, and advice over the past few years has been invaluable. I am especially grateful to you for encouraging me to pursue my Master’s and write about my electoral system idea.
  • A Brief Introductory T T I L C T Ti L Tutorial on Computational Social Choice

    A Brief Introductory T T I L C T Ti L Tutorial on Computational Social Choice

    A Brief Introductory TtTutori ilal on Compu ttitationa l Social Choice Vincent Conitzer Outline • 1. Introduction to votinggy theory • 2. Hard-to-compute rules • 3. Using computational hardness to prevent manipulation and other undesirable behavior in elections • 4. Selected topics (time permitting) Introduction to voting theory Voting over alternatives voting rule > > (mechanism) determines winner based on votes > > • Can vote over other things too – Where to ggg,jp,o for dinner tonight, other joint plans, … Voting (rank aggregation) • Set of m candidates (aka. alternatives, outcomes) •n voters; each voter ranks all the candidates – E.g., for set of candidates {a, b, c, d}, one possible vote is b > a > d > c – Submitted ranking is called a vote • AvotingA voting rule takes as input a vector of votes (submitted by the voters), and as output produces either: – the winning candidate, or – an aggregate ranking of all candidates • Can vote over just about anything – pppolitical representatives, award nominees, where to go for dinner tonight, joint plans, allocations of tasks/resources, … – Also can consider other applications: e.g., aggregating search engines’ rankinggggs into a single ranking Example voting rules • Scoring rules are defined by a vector (a1, a2, …, am); being ranked ith in a vote gives the candidate ai points – Plurality is defined by (1, 0, 0, …, 0) (winner is candidate that is ranked first most often) – Veto (or anti-plurality) is defined by (1, 1, …, 1, 0) (winner is candidate that is ranked last the least often) – Borda is defined by (m-1, m-2, …, 0) • Plurality with (2-candidate) runoff: top two candidates in terms of plurality score proceed to runoff; whichever is ranked higher than the other by more voters, wins • Single Transferable Vote (STV, aka.
  • Generalized Scoring Rules: a Framework That Reconciles Borda and Condorcet

    Generalized Scoring Rules: a Framework That Reconciles Borda and Condorcet

    Generalized Scoring Rules: A Framework That Reconciles Borda and Condorcet Lirong Xia Harvard University Generalized scoring rules [Xia and Conitzer 08] are a relatively new class of social choice mech- anisms. In this paper, we survey developments in generalized scoring rules, showing that they provide a fruitful framework to obtain general results, and also reconcile the Borda approach and Condorcet approach via a new social choice axiom. We comment on some high-level ideas behind GSRs and their connection to Machine Learning, and point out some ongoing work and future directions. Categories and Subject Descriptors: J.4 [Computer Applications]: Social and Behavioral Sci- ences|Economics; I.2.11 [Distributed Artificial Intelligence]: Multiagent Systems General Terms: Algorithms, Economics, Theory Additional Key Words and Phrases: Computational social choice, generalized scoring rules 1. INTRODUCTION Social choice theory focuses on developing principles and methods for representation and aggregation of individual ordinal preferences. Perhaps the most well-known application of social choice theory is political elections. Over centuries, many social choice mechanisms have been proposed and analyzed in the context of elections, where each agent (voter) uses a linear order over the alternatives (candidates) to represent her preferences (her vote). For historical reasons, we will use voting rules to denote social choice mechanisms, though we need to keep in mind that the application is not limited to political elections.1 Most existing voting rules fall into one of the following two categories.2 Positional scoring rules: Each alternative gets some points from each agent according to its position in the agent's vote. The alternative with the highest total points wins.
  • Legislature by Lot: Envisioning Sortition Within a Bicameral System

    Legislature by Lot: Envisioning Sortition Within a Bicameral System

    PASXXX10.1177/0032329218789886Politics & SocietyGastil and Wright 789886research-article2018 Special Issue Article Politics & Society 2018, Vol. 46(3) 303 –330 Legislature by Lot: Envisioning © The Author(s) 2018 Article reuse guidelines: Sortition within a Bicameral sagepub.com/journals-permissions https://doi.org/10.1177/0032329218789886DOI: 10.1177/0032329218789886 System* journals.sagepub.com/home/pas John Gastil Pennsylvania State University Erik Olin Wright University of Wisconsin–Madison Abstract In this article, we review the intrinsic democratic flaws in electoral representation, lay out a set of principles that should guide the construction of a sortition chamber, and argue for the virtue of a bicameral system that combines sortition and elections. We show how sortition could prove inclusive, give citizens greater control of the political agenda, and make their participation more deliberative and influential. We consider various design challenges, such as the sampling method, legislative training, and deliberative procedures. We explain why pairing sortition with an elected chamber could enhance its virtues while dampening its potential vices. In our conclusion, we identify ideal settings for experimenting with sortition. Keywords bicameral legislatures, deliberation, democratic theory, elections, minipublics, participation, political equality, sortition Corresponding Author: John Gastil, Department of Communication Arts & Sciences, Pennsylvania State University, 232 Sparks Bldg., University Park, PA 16802, USA. Email: [email protected] *This special issue of Politics & Society titled “Legislature by Lot: Transformative Designs for Deliberative Governance” features a preface, an introductory anchor essay and postscript, and six articles that were presented as part of a workshop held at the University of Wisconsin–Madison, September 2017, organized by John Gastil and Erik Olin Wright.
  • Approval-Based Elections and Distortion of Voting Rules

    Approval-Based Elections and Distortion of Voting Rules

    Proceedings of the Twenty-Eighth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-19) Approval-Based Elections and Distortion of Voting Rules Grzegorz Pierczynski , Piotr Skowron University of Warsaw, Warsaw, Poland [email protected], [email protected] Abstract voters and the candidates are represented by points in a metric space M called the issue space. The optimal candidate is the We consider elections where both voters and can- one that minimizes the sum of the distances to all the voters. didates can be associated with points in a metric However, the election rules do not have access to the met- space and voters prefer candidates that are closer to ric space M itself but they only see the ranking-based profile those that are farther away. It is often assumed that induced by M: in this profile the voters rank the candidates the optimal candidate is the one that minimizes the by their distance to themselves, preferring the ones that are total distance to the voters. Yet, the voting rules of- closer to those that are farther. Since the rules do not have ten do not have access to the metric space M and full information about the metric space they cannot always only see preference rankings induced by M. Con- find optimal candidates. The distortion quantifies the worst- sequently, they often are incapable of selecting the case loss of the utility being effect of having only access to optimal candidate. The distortion of a voting rule rankings. Formally, the distortion of a voting rule is the max- measures the worst-case loss of the quality being imum, over all metric spaces, of the following ratio: the sum the result of having access only to preference rank- of the distances between the elected candidate and the vot- ings.