RUTH ANNA PUTNAM : Relegates to the Dark Shadows the Role of Women a PRAGMATIC THINKER for OUR TIME Thinkers Who Shaped the Pragmatic Movement

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

RUTH ANNA PUTNAM : Relegates to the Dark Shadows the Role of Women a PRAGMATIC THINKER for OUR TIME Thinkers Who Shaped the Pragmatic Movement RUTH ANNA PUTNAM : relegates to the dark shadows the role of women A PRAGMATIC THINKER FOR OUR TIME thinkers who shaped the pragmatic movement. We tend Richard J. Bernstein to forget that Jane Addams had an enormous influence New School for Social Research on John Dewey. And except for a few Peirce scholars, [email protected] most philosophers are unaware of the brilliant correspondence between Peirce and Lady Victoria Welby ABSTRACT : Ruth Anna Putnam is one the most imaginative and vital pragmatic thinkers of our time. Unfortunately, where we find some of Peirce’s most illuminating her philosophical work has been overshadowed by her discussions of his theory of signs and how it is related to much more famous husband, Hilary Putnam. For many philosophers Ruth Anna’s primary claim to fame is that his version of pragmatism. Their exchanges are a model she is responsible for getting Hilary to take pragmatism of philosophical dialogue. Even if we focus on the seriously—something that he has acknowledged on many occasions. But viewing her in this limited way does renaissance of pragmatism in the latter part of the a great injustice to her own originality. The aim of this twentieth century and the early decades of the twenty- paper, the first scholarly study of Ruth Anna Putnam’s work, is to challenge that view. first century, philosophers interested in the varieties of pragmatism normally direct our attention to such Keywords: Pragmatism, Ruth Anna Putnam, women in thinkers as Richard Rorty, Hilary Putnam, and Robert philosophy, women in pragmatism, Hilary Putnam Brandom. We neglect the many women philosophers Ever since I wrote my dissertation on John Dewey’s who have developed pragmatic themes in their metaphysics of experience (1957), I have always taken philosophical work. When I speak of “we” in this context, 1 “pragmatism seriously”—to use Ruth Anna Putnam’s I include myself. expression, but I have never focused on the outstanding Consequently, I want to dedicate this essay to a contributions to the pragmatic tradition by women study of Ruth Anna Putnam’s work. She is one of the thinkers. “‘Pragmatism’,” as Richard Rorty wrote in his most imaginative and vital pragmatic thinkers of our 1979 presidential address, “is a vague, ambiguous, and time. Unfortunately, the philosophical work of Ruth overworked word. Nevertheless, it names the chief glory Anna Putnam has been overshadowed by her much of our country’s intellectual tradition. No other American more famous husband, Hilary Putnam. For many writers offered so radical a suggestion for making our philosophers Ruth Anna’s primary claim to fame is that future different from our past, as have James and she is responsible for getting Hilary to take pragmatism Dewey” (Rorty 1982: 160). There is a traditional narrow seriously—something that he has acknowledged on sense of pragmatism where it is taken to be primary a many occasions. But viewing her in this limited way does “theory” of meaning and truth. If we think of a great injustice to her own originality. David Macarthur pragmatism in this way, then we do a vast injustice to has recently edited a splendid volume of essays by Ruth the richness and diversity of issues and problems treated Anna and Hilary Putnam. Pragmatism as a Way of Life: by these pragmatic thinkers, which range from The Lasting Legacy of William James and John Dewey cosmological speculations to specific aesthetic, moral, consists of twenty-seven essays made up of those social, and political questions. Furthermore, restricting written separately as well as two co-written essays. This the label “pragmatism” to this famous triad of thinkers is the first time that most of Ruth Anna’s essays on neglects the important pragmatic contributions by black pragmatic themes have been collected in one place, thinkers such as W.E B. Dubois and Alain Locke—both of although the purpose of this anthology is to display the whom studied at Harvard when William James, George mutual and interrelated interest in pragmatism by Ruth Santayana, and Josiah Royce were on the philosophy Anna and Hilary Putnam I plan, however, to concentrate faculty. The emphasis—indeed overemphasis on Peirce, James and Dewey (and sometimes Mead)—also 1 For a comprehensive discussion of pragmatism, women, and feminist philosophy see Seigfried 1996. Pragmatism Today Vol. 9, Issue 1, 2018 RUTH A NNA PUTNAM : A PRAGMATIC THINKER FOR OUR TIME Richard J. Bernstein almost exclusively on Ruth Anna’s essays. I am interested behind in the study” (p.15). 2 She uses a minimum of in Ruth Anna’s work because she is such an excellent technical jargon and only occasionally refers to academic philosopher, not because she is a “woman” philosopher. articles in specialized philosophical journals. What makes But the sad truth is that like so many women her prose so vivid is that she frequently gives concrete philosophers, past and present, her work has been examples from “real life” problems to illustrate her key frequently ignored or underrated precisely because she points. Any intelligent reader, regardless of background, is a woman. can read and learn from her. In this respect, she follows In his essay “Pragmatism and Moral Objectivity” in the best tradition of James and Dewey—especially Hilary Putnam indicates what he finds attractive about when they were addressing general readers. She American pragmatism. manages to do this without a loss of precision or subtlety. She is in genuine dialogue with James and What I find attractive in pragmatism is not a Dewey but clearly indicates when she agrees or systematic theory in the usual sense at all. It is disagrees with them—and why. In reading her essays, rather a certain group of theses, which can be and indeed were argued very differently by one has the experience of participating in a lively open- different philosophers with different concerns ended engaging conversation. [my italics--RJB], and which became the basis of the philosophes of Peirce, and above all James Let me illustrate her down to earth approach with and Dewey. Cursorily summarized, those theses reference to one of the most discussed issues in are (1) antiskepticism; pragmatists hold that doubt requires justification just as much as belief Anglophone philosophy during the past one hundred (recall Peirce’s famous distinction between years: the issue of realism versus anti-realism, and the “real” and “philosophical” doubt; (2) fallibilism; pragmatists hold that there is never a closely related issue of realism versus relativism. (Not all metaphysical guarantee to be had that such-and- anti-realists are relativists.) Of course, one of the things such a belief will never need revision (that one can be both fallibilistic and antiskeptical is that keep these debates going is specifying the precise perhaps the unique insight of American meaning of these contested concepts. Take, for example, pragmatism; (3) the thesis that there is no fundamental dichotomy between “facts” and the work of Hilary Putnam. He has moved from a version “values”; and (4) the thesis that, in a certain of metaphysical realism to internal realism (realism with sense, practice is primary in philosophy (Putnam: 1994: 152). a small “r”) to refining this to a form of pragmatic or common sense realism. Hilary Putnam staunchly defends Ruth Anna certainly agrees with all these theses at a realism with a small “r” because he believes that the general level. What I hope to show that she interprets alternatives—metaphysical realism or relativism—are and argues for these theses in a very distinctive manner self-defeating and ultimately incoherent. Hilary Putnam that reflect her primary concerns. frequently characterizes Rorty as the chief contemporary The initial striking impression in reading Ruth advocate of anti-realist relativism. Rorty’s responds that Anna’s essays is their lucidity, freshness and grace. Like he is not a relativist and claims that the “relativist James and Dewey, she is concerned to show that menace” is an invention of Hilary Putnam. There are philosophers do not have to focus exclusively on the good reasons why so much energy has gone into the problems of philosophy but can deal in an illuminating debates about realism and anti-realism. On the one hand fashion with the problems of human beings. “So what many philosophers (including Rorty and Hilary Putnam) does it mean to turn away from the problems of reject metaphysical realism and have taken the linguistic philosophers? It means to me—and here I am using a phrase from David Hume rather than the pragmatists— 2 Unless otherwise noted, all page references are to that I seek a philosophy that I do not have to leave essays by Ruth Anna Putnam collected in Pragmatism as a Way of Life edited by D. Macarthur (2017). 140 Pragmatism Today Vol. 9, Issue 1, 2018 RUTH A NNA PUTNAM : A PRAGMATIC THINKER FOR OUR TIME Richard J. Bernstein turn. Both Rorty and Hilary Putnam are skeptical of the does is recognize the basic insights or “intuitions” of the very idea that we can escape from language and from opposing positions and shows how from her pragmatic the descriptive functions of language. Both believe that perspective they are compatible. We may say that the we cannot make a sharp fixed distinction between basic intuition behind realism is the necessity to descriptive language and nonlinguistic fact. They both recognize that there is a common objective world that reject the idea that we can somehow directly compare constrains our warranted beliefs. On the other hand, the our ideas, concepts, thoughts, judgments or sentences insight behind many forms of anti-realism is that, as with an independent reality to see whether or not they finite human beings we are limited in knowing the world “correspond.” Both Rorty and Putnam are among those by our linguistic descriptions.
Recommended publications
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    03/05/2017 William James (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (ca. 1895, in The Letters of William James, ed. by Henry James, Boston, 1920) William James First published Thu Sep 7, 2000; substantive revision Tue Oct 29, 2013 William James was an original thinker in and between the disciplines of physiology, psychology and philosophy. His twelve­hundred page masterwork, The Principles of Psychology (1890), is a rich blend of physiology, psychology, philosophy, and personal reflection that has given us such ideas as “the stream of thought” and the baby's impression of the world “as one great blooming, buzzing confusion” (PP 462). It contains seeds of pragmatism and phenomenology, and influenced generations of thinkers in Europe and America, including Edmund Husserl, Bertrand Russell, John Dewey, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. James studied at Harvard's Lawrence Scientific School and the School of Medicine, but his writings were from the outset as much philosophical as scientific. “Some Remarks on Spencer's Notion of Mind as Correspondence” (1878) and “The Sentiment of Rationality” (1879, 1882) presage his future pragmatism and pluralism, and contain the first statements of his view that philosophical theories are reflections of a philosopher's temperament. James hints at his religious concerns in his earliest essays and in The Principles, but they become more explicit in The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (1897), Human Immortality: Two Supposed Objections to the Doctrine (1898), The Varieties of Religious Experience (1902) and A Pluralistic Universe (1909). James oscillated between thinking that a “study in human nature” such as Varieties could contribute to a “Science of Religion” and the belief that religious experience involves an altogether supernatural domain, somehow inaccessible to science but accessible to the individual human subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Flanagan/Duke/Revised 4.2014 1
    Flanagan/Duke/Revised 4.2014 1 Curriculum Vitae Owen Flanagan Duke University 201 West Duke Building Box 90743 Durham, NC 27708 +1 919.660.3050 (office) [email protected] (email) University Appointments and Honors Duke University 1993- James B. Duke Professor of Philosophy (Distinguished University Professorship) Associate Graduate Program in Literature Steering Committee Philosophy, Arts, and Literature Initiative (PAL) Professor of Psychology & Neuroscience Professor of Neurobiology Faculty Associate Center for Cognitive Neuroscience Distinguished Visiting Professor, City University of Hong Kong, August-December 2013. Indian Council of Philosophical Research (ICPR) Distinguished Annual Lecturer 2012 (Delhi, Kolkata, Lucknow, Allahabad) Distinguished Visiting Professor, University of Vienna, Dec-Jan, 2011-2012. Jack Lynch Distinguished Professor, Wake Forest University, Winston-Salem NC, Spring 2009. Templeton Distinguished Research Fellow, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA 2006. Six Lectures on “Human Flourishing in the Age of Mind Science” Flanagan/Duke/Revised 4.2014 2 February 2006. Distinguished Fellow, Psychology & Biology of Morality, Dartmouth College, Summer 2004. John Findlay Distinguished Visiting Professor, Boston University, 2000. Romanell Phi Beta Kappa Award 1998-1999. Three Lectures on “Science and the Human Image.” Wellesley College 1978-1993 Class of 1919 Reunion Professor of Philosophy, 1989-1993 Professor of Philosophy 1988-89; Assistant Professor 1978-1983; Associate Professor 1983-88. Administrative Experience
    [Show full text]
  • Hilary Putnam
    111 Hilary Putnam 011 111 A beautiful statement of almost all the ideas that I take to be of lasting value and vital importance Hilary Putnam Hilary Putnam is one of the most famous and influential living philosophers. In Hilary Putnam: Pragmatism and Realism, Putnam responds to ten new papers exam- ining his central ideas, written by highly respected Putnam scholars especially 0111 for this volume. Putnam’s work touches on almost every area of interest in contemporary Anglo- American philosophy. His ideas have had repercussions in the philosophy of language and the philosophy of mind, as well as countless areas of metaphysics. Many of Putnam’s most influential ideas can be traced back to his two key commit- ments: to pragmatism and to realism. In this book, well-known top scholars examine these two fundamental positions and their place in Putnam’s work. In addition to responding to each paper, there is a new essay by Putnam himself on pragmatism and nonscientific knowledge. The insight into Putnam’s work provided by the contributions to his work, 0111 combined with Putnam’s extensive and detailed responses, make this essential reading for anyone with an interest in the ideas and influence of Hilary Putnam. Contributors: Ruth Anna Putnam, Hilary Putnam, Richard Warner, Robert Brandom, Nicholas Rescher, John Haldane, Tadeusz Szubka, John Heil, Wolfgang Künne, Gary Ebbs and Charles Travis. James Conant is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Chicago. He is the editor of Putnam’s collected papers. Urszula M. Z˙eglen´ is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Turon´, Poland.
    [Show full text]
  • 6 X 10.Long New.P65
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-69746-0 - The Cambridge Companion to Dewey Edited by Molly Cochran Frontmatter More information the cambridge companion to DEWEY Each volume of this series of companions to major philoso- phers contains specially commissioned essays by an inter- national team of scholars, together with a substantial bibliography, and will serve as a reference work for students and non-specialists. One aim of the series is to dispel the intimidation such readers often feel when faced with the work of a difficult and challenging thinker. John Dewey (1859–1952) was a major figure of the American cultural and intellectual landscape in the first half of the twentieth century. While not the originator of American pragmatism, he was instrumental to its articula- tion as a philosophy and the spread of its influence beyond philosophy to other disciplines. His prolific writings encom- pass metaphysics; philosophy of mind; cognitive science; psychology; moral philosophy; the philosophies of religion, art, and education; and democratic political and international theory. The contributors to this Companion examine the wide range of Dewey’s thought and provide a critical evalua- tion of his philosophy and its lasting influence. New readers will find this the most convenient, accessible guide to Dewey currently available. Advanced students and specialists will find a conspectus of recent developments in the interpretation of Dewey. molly cochran is Associate Professor of International Affairs in the Sam Nunn School of International Affairs at the Georgia Institute of Technology. She is the author of Normative Theory in International Relations: A Pragmatic Approach (1999). © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-69746-0 - The Cambridge Companion to Dewey Edited by Molly Cochran Frontmatter More information other volumes in the series of cambridge companions ABELARD Edited by jeffrey e.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism: an Old Name for Some New Ways of Thinking? Author(S): James T
    Pragmatism: An Old Name for Some New Ways of Thinking? Author(s): James T. Kloppenberg Source: The Journal of American History, Vol. 83, No. 1 (Jun., 1996), pp. 100-138 Published by: Organization of American Historians Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2945476 . Accessed: 27/07/2011 13:56 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=oah. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Organization of American Historians is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of American History. http://www.jstor.org Pragmatism:An Old Name forSome New Waysof Thinking? JamesT.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography of the Writings of Hilary Putnam
    PART THREE BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE WRITINGS OF HILARY PUTNAM Compiled and Edited by John R. ShooK with the assistance of Hilary Putnam anD Joseph PalenCIK Putnam Bibliography.indd 891 1/24/2015 4:09:12 PM Putnam Bibliography.indd 892 1/24/2015 4:09:12 PM BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE WRITINGS OF Hilary Putnam This bibliography lists books and then shorter writings, in chronological order of their first publication. Chapters of books are accompanied by a year of first publication; those chapters lacking a year were first published in that book. Only selected reprintings of shorter writings are mentioned, to clarify multiple versions. A translation of a shorter item is included if that was its first publication; any later publication in English is mentioned. BOOKS The Meaning of the Concept of Probability in Application to Finite Sequences. Ph.D. dis- sertation, University of California, Los Angeles, 1951. New York: Garland, 1990. The 1990 reprinting includes “Introduction Some Years Later,” 1–12. Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings. Edited with Paul Benacerraf. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1964. Includes an “Introduction” with Paul Benacerraf, 1–27. The 2nd edition (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1983) adds two chapters by Putnam: “Mathematics without Foundations” (1967), 295–313; and “Models and Reality” (1980), 421–45. Philosophy of Logic. New York: Harper and Row, 1971. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1972. Translated into Italian (1975), Japanese (1975), Chinese (1984). Repr. in Math- ematics, Matter and Method, 2nd ed. (1985), 323–57. Repr., London: Routledge, 2010. CONTENTS Preface, vii 1. What Logic Is, 3–7 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Towards Metaphysics of Religious Diversity: a Jamesian
    Towards Metaphysics of Religious Diversity: A Jamesian Investigation Christian Polke Georg-August-University of Goettingen What kind of diversity? Which kind of metaphysics? I start with some personal remarks: Since last year I am a member of our diversity committee in my faculty in Goettingen. Whereas in former times it was mainly the duty of such commissions to be mainly aware of gender problems and thereby to help installing affirmative actions in direction of gender equality, it is now no less part of our daily tasks to sensitize for questions of all kind of diversity, including different cultural and ethnic backgrounds and of course issues of disability access. But why am I telling you that? Because during the last 12 months I start to think about the concept of “diversity” which is used or better is underlying all different programs we are organizing. What is its inner meaning? And, moreover, why do we usually value diversity in an affirmative way, not only in “diversity policies”, but within our schools and universities, not forget in international business companies? The term “diversity” is originally taken from biology. In that area, biodiversity means variety of species within a genus. According to the United Nations Environment Programme (UNEP), biodiversity is typically measured by the variation of genetic type, species, and even on the general level of our ecosystem. Following this description, the maintenance of biodiversity becomes more and more a central task for our contemporary age. However, 1 already the transmission of our key term “diversity” from the world of non-human animals and living beings to the world of humans is at first glance in no sense plausible because as a species the homo sapiens sapiens does not show any longer a variation of either, its genetic type or its physiology.
    [Show full text]
  • Front Matter
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-82242-8 - The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy Edited by Donald Rutherford Frontmatter More information THE CAMBRIDGE COMPANION TO EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy is a comprehensive introduction to the central topics and changing shape of philosophical inquiry in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. It explores one of the most in- novative periods in the history of Western philosophy, extending from Montaigne, Bacon, and Descartes through Hume and Kant. During this period, philosophers initiated and responded to major intellectual developments in natural science, religion, and politics, transforming in the process concepts and doctrines inherited from ancient and medieval philosophy. In this Companion, leading specialists examine early modern treatments of the methodological and concep- tual foundations of natural science, metaphysics, philoso- phy of mind, logic and language, moral and political philosophy, and theology. A final chapter looks forward to the philosophy of the Enlightenment. This will be an in- valuable guide for all who are interested in the philosophical thought of the early modern period. DONALD RUTHERFORD is Professor of Philosophy at the Uni- versity of California, San Diego. He is the author of Leibniz and the Rational Order of Nature (1995), editor (with J. A. Cover) of Leibniz: Nature and Freedom (2005), and editor and translator (with Brandon Look) of The Leibniz– Des Bosses Correspondence (2007). © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-82242-8 - The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy Edited by Donald Rutherford Frontmatter More information OTHER VOLUMES IN THE SERIES OF CAMBRIDGE COMPANIONS ABELARD Edited by JEFFREY E.
    [Show full text]
  • Rorty's Moral Philosophy for Liberal Democratic Culture
    Contemporary Pragmatism Editions Rodopi Vol. 4, No. 2 (December 2007), 45–64 © 2007 Rorty’s Moral Philosophy for Liberal Democratic Culture Colin Koopman Richard Rorty’s moral writings offer a cogent summary of the moral content of contemporary liberal democratic culture. Rorty insists on a divide between our public and private lives, yet he claims that moral progress (a seemingly public affair) is primarily driven by the imagination of great poetry and philosophy (which Rorty claims are private projects). A pressing tension thus emerges between private imagination and public moral justification, which is also very real in contemporary liberal democratic culture itself. I sketch a way out of this problem, which fits well with the pragmatism he shares with William James and John Dewey. One question immediately provoked by my title concerns the status of Richard Rorty’s moral vision as specifically philosophical. Critics will wonder whether Richard Rorty really has a philosophical account of moral thought and practice. It is of course true that Rorty has not engaged with moral philosophy in the systematic manner common amongst leading contemporary moral philosophers. Even in those areas to which Rorty has devoted consistent systematic attention, such as philosophy of language and metaphilosophy, he has always been hesi- tant to apply the label of “philosophy” to whatever it is he sees himself as doing. Rorty has, however, written a number of pieces which indicate the kind of moral philosophical vision we might expect of ourselves if our liberal democratic culture can ever figure out a way to take seriously the pragmatist experimentalism and meliorism that he, following William James and John Dewey, urges us to.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Pragmatism
    Contemporary Pragmatism Editors John R. Shook Center for Inquiry Transnational, USA Paulo Ghiraldelli, Jr. Centro de Estudos em Filosofia Americana, Brazil Editorial Board Susana de Castro Amaral, Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro, Brazil Randall Auxier, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale, USA James Bohman, Saint Louis University, USA Randall Dipert, University at Buffalo, USA Pascal Engel, Université Paris IV–Sorbonne, France Jose Miguel Esteban, Universidad Autonoma del Estado de Morelos, Mexico Nancy Frankenberry, Dartmouth College, USA Jim Garrison, Virginia Tech University, USA Eddie Glaude, Princeton University, USA Russell Goodman, University of New Mexico, USA Susan Haack, University of Miami, USA Leoni Henning, Universidade Estadual de Londrina, Brazil Susan Hurley, University of Warwick, Great Britain Robert Kane, University of Texas, USA Paul Kurtz, Center for Inquiry Transnational, USA John Lachs, Vanderbilt University, USA Alvaro Marquez-Fernandez, Universidad del Zulia, Venezuela Joseph Margolis, Temple University, USA James Marshall, University of Auckland, New Zealand Glenn McGee, Albany Medical Center, New York, USA Floyd Merrell, Purdue University, USA Cheryl Misak, University of Toronto, Canada Lucius Outlaw, Jr., Vanderbilt University, USA Michael Peters, University of Auckland, Austr.; University of Glasgow, Scotland Huw Price, University of Sydney, Australia Hilary Putnam, Harvard University, USA Bjørn Ramberg, University of Oslo, Norway Mike Sandbothe, Aalborg University, Denmark Jeffrey Stout, Princeton University, USA Claudine Tiercelin, L’Université de Paris-XII, France Celal Türer, Erciyes University, Turkey Bas van Fraassen, Princeton University, USA Marcus Vinícius da Cunha, Universidade de São Paulo, Ribeirão Preto, Brazil Cornel West, Princeton University, USA Contemporary Pragmatism is affiliated with the International Pragmatism Society. See information for subscribers and contributors on the inside back cover.
    [Show full text]
  • Short Essay Deadline: Thursday 29Th November (Thursday Week 10)
    DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY PHIL 320 PRAGMATISM Autumn SEMESTER 2012 Chris Hookway Email [email protected] Office Hours: Monday 11am., Friday 11 pm. Lecture times Monday 2 pm Hicks – LTD Wednesday 11 am. Hicks - LT4 Seminar times Tues 3-4, BA SR AG14 Wed 12pm, BA SR AG14 PHI6500: seminar times to be arranged early in the course. Short Essay deadline: Thursday 29th November (Thursday week 10) Long essay deadline 25 January, 4pm Plan for long essay must be submitted by Wednesday November 14th There will be a MOLE site for this course. If you are registered for the course, you will automatically be registered to use this site and there should be a link on your MUSE page. Other people attending the course should ask me to give them the right to use this. I. INTRODUCTION I. Pragmatism is a philosophical tradition which emerged in the United States in the later years of the nineteenth century. The three major 'Classical Pragmatists' were Charles Peirce (1839-1914), William James (1842-1910) and John Dewey (1859-1952). James and Dewey took further some ideas about truth, inquiry and pragmatism which Peirce defended in the 1870s, often taking them in directions of which Peirce would have disapproved. During the last decade, pragmatism has become an important player on the philosophical stage once again. In part, this reflects our growing understanding of the subtlety and interest of the work of these 'classical pragmatists'. In part, it involves a recognition that Pragmatism was linked to other philosophical movements of the time: they joined with Nietzsche, existentialists like Heidegger, and Wittgenstein (for example) in questioning traditional philosophical ideas and forging a philosophical understanding of human life which emphasized the fact that knowers were agents and emphasized the role of values and interests in shaping our knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • The Revival of Pragmatism NEW ESSAYS
    Duke University Press Durham and London, 1998 The Revival of Pragmatism NEW ESSAYS Edited by Morris Dickstein ON SOCIAL THOUGHT, LAW, AND CULTURE Contents Acknowledgments ix Introduction: Pragmatism Then and Now, Morris Dickstein 1 WHAT DIFFERENCE DOES PRAGMATISM MAKE? THE VIEW FROM PHILOSOPHY Pragmatism as Romantic Polytheism, Richard Rorty 21 Pragmatism and Realism, Hilary Putnam 37 Response to Hilary Putnam's "Pragmatism and Realism" Sidney Morgenbesser 54 The Moral Impulse, Ruth Anna Putnam 62 What's the Use of Calling Emerson a Pragmatist? Stanley Cave11 72 PRAGMATISM AND THE REMAKING OF SOCIAL THOUGHT Pragmatism: An Old Name for Some New Ways of Thinking? James T. Kloppenberg 83 Pragmatism and Democracy: Reconstructing the Logic of John Dewey's Faith, Robert B. Westbrook 128 Community in the Pragmatic Tradition, Richard J. Bernstein 141 Another Pragmatism: Alain Locke, Critical "Race" Theory, and the When Mind Is a Verb: Thomas Eakins and the Work of Doing Politics of Culture, Nancy Fraser 157 Ray Carney 377 Going Astray, Going Forward: Du Boisian Pragmatism Religion and the Recent Revival of Pragmatism and Its Lineage, Ross Posnock 176 Giles Gunn 404 The Inspiration of Pragmatism: Some Personal Remarks AFTERWORD Hans Joas 190 The Missing Pragmatic Revival in American Social Science Alan Wolfe 199 Pragmatism and Its Limits, John Patrick Diggins 207 PRAGMATISM AND LAW Pragmatic Adjudication, Richard A. Posner 235 Freestanding Legal Pragmatism, Thomas C. Grey 254 What's Pragmatic about Legal Pragmatism?, David Luban 275 Pragmatism and Law: A Response to David Luban, Richard Rorty 304 It's a Positivist, It's a Pragmatist, It's a Codifier! Reflections on Nietzsche and Stendhal, Richard H.
    [Show full text]