Contemporary Pragmatism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Contemporary Pragmatism Contemporary Pragmatism Editors John R. Shook Center for Inquiry Transnational, USA Paulo Ghiraldelli, Jr. Centro de Estudos em Filosofia Americana, Brazil Editorial Board Susana de Castro Amaral, Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro, Brazil Randall Auxier, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale, USA James Bohman, Saint Louis University, USA Randall Dipert, University at Buffalo, USA Pascal Engel, Université Paris IV–Sorbonne, France Jose Miguel Esteban, Universidad Autonoma del Estado de Morelos, Mexico Nancy Frankenberry, Dartmouth College, USA Jim Garrison, Virginia Tech University, USA Eddie Glaude, Princeton University, USA Russell Goodman, University of New Mexico, USA Susan Haack, University of Miami, USA Leoni Henning, Universidade Estadual de Londrina, Brazil Susan Hurley, University of Warwick, Great Britain Robert Kane, University of Texas, USA Paul Kurtz, Center for Inquiry Transnational, USA John Lachs, Vanderbilt University, USA Alvaro Marquez-Fernandez, Universidad del Zulia, Venezuela Joseph Margolis, Temple University, USA James Marshall, University of Auckland, New Zealand Glenn McGee, Albany Medical Center, New York, USA Floyd Merrell, Purdue University, USA Cheryl Misak, University of Toronto, Canada Lucius Outlaw, Jr., Vanderbilt University, USA Michael Peters, University of Auckland, Austr.; University of Glasgow, Scotland Huw Price, University of Sydney, Australia Hilary Putnam, Harvard University, USA Bjørn Ramberg, University of Oslo, Norway Mike Sandbothe, Aalborg University, Denmark Jeffrey Stout, Princeton University, USA Claudine Tiercelin, L’Université de Paris-XII, France Celal Türer, Erciyes University, Turkey Bas van Fraassen, Princeton University, USA Marcus Vinícius da Cunha, Universidade de São Paulo, Ribeirão Preto, Brazil Cornel West, Princeton University, USA Contemporary Pragmatism is affiliated with the International Pragmatism Society. See information for subscribers and contributors on the inside back cover. CONTEMPORARY PRAGMATISM Edited by John R. Shook and Paulo Ghiraldelli, Jr. Volume 4 Number 2 December 2007 Amsterdam – New York, NY, 2007 The paper on which this book is printed meets the requirements of “ISO 9706:1994, Information and Documentation – Paper for documents – Requirements for permanence” ISSN: 1572-3429 ©Editions Rodopi B.V., Amsterdam – New York, NY, 2007 Printed in The Netherlands Contemporary Pragmatism Volume 4 Number 2 December 2007 Contents Symposium on Robert Westbrook’s Democratic Hope: Pragmatism and the Politics of Truth Brendan Hogan Guest Editor Introduction 1 Eric MacGilvray Pragmatism and the Epistemic Defense of Democracy 3 Brendan Hogan Translating Democracy or Democratic Acts of Translation: On Cornel West’s Democracy Matters 11 Robert Talisse Two Democratic Hopes 19 Robert Westbrook Replies to Symposium Participants 29 Articles Judith Green On The Passing of Richard Rorty and the Future of American Philosophy 35 Colin Koopman Rorty’s Moral Philosophy for Liberal Democratic Culture 45 Tom Spector Dewey and Dancy and the Moral Authority of Rules 65 Elizabeth Baeten Embedded and Embodied Moral Life 77 Rick Werner Pragmatism for Pacifists 93 Book Reviews Douglas McDermid Review of Richard Rorty, Philosophy as Cultural Politics: Philosophical Papers, Volume 4. 117 Gregory Pappas Review of John R. Shook and Joseph Margolis, eds., A Companion to Pragmatism 120 Contemporary Pragmatism Editions Rodopi Vol. 4, No. 2 (December 2007), 1–2 © 2007 Guest Editor Introduction to a Symposium on Robert Westbrook’s Democratic Hope: Pragmatism and the Politics of Truth Brendan Hogan This symposium on Robert Westbrook’s John Dewey and American Democracy explores the continuing relevance of pragmatism for democratic political theory. Robert Westbrook’s John Dewey and American Democracy, published in 1991, was a rare book insofar as it was hailed by intellectuals whose disciplinary aims were very different from each other.1 As the commentators on the back of the book indicated, scholars working in sociology, English, and philosophy all had reason to turn to this work in addition to those in Westbrook’s own field of history. Besides offering a compelling narrative, John Dewey and American Democracy also contained arguments that convincingly demonstrated theses concerning a variety of longstanding debates regarding Dewey’s theory of education, his social philosophy, and his political theory. Far from being a strictly historical document, the text showed the relevance of Dewey’s philosophy to contemporary democratic theory. Specifically, by relating Dewey to issues that have emerged in the New Left and more generally in political discourse concerning the norms of democracy, as well as by emphasizing Dewey’s pluralism, did John Dewey and American Democracy serve as a major touchstone in pragmatism’s “renewal.” These democratic theoretic strands of this rich work are most pertinent in approaching Westbrook’s latest effort at working out the consequences of pragmatism, Democratic Hope: Pragmatism and the Politics of Truth.2 In Democratic Hope, Westbrook extends the investigation into pragma- tism and the relationship between democracy and philosophy. Specifically, two questions, regarding the political valence of pragmatism and the relationship of truth to politics, and more specifically to democracy, drive this text. These questions are asked of the classical pragmatists Peirce, James, and Dewey, and brought into a more contemporary context through Sidney Hook and the question of pragmatism’s relationship to Marxism. Westbrook extends these questions of democracy and philosophy to contemporary neopragmatism. Cornel 2 BRENDAN HOGAN West, Hilary Putnam, Cheryl Misak, and the late Richard Rorty are all brought into the conversation by Westbrook’s inquiry into the resources that contemporary thinkers in the pragmatic vein have to address the problems of humans and not just the problems of philosophers. Specifically, Westbrook employs Cheryl Misak’s arguments for the “truth-aptness” of moral claims in his argument for a political valence to philosophical pragmatism. In addition he argues for a commitment to a set of practices that foster the habits necessary to carry out the kind of discourse that achieving the truth claims that a truth apt moral discourse is committed. These practices bear a normative family resemblance to those put forward by advocates of fostering the public virtues of civic republicanism. The critics assembled for this symposium are reflective of the interdisciplinary scope and impact of Westbrook’s work. That a historian has produced such a rich source of reflection on themes central to pragmatic self- understanding as truth, democracy, and politics is another testament to the author’s ongoing ability to contribute to the discourse of pragmatism in varying registers in the same book. It is also fitting given the varieties of interests and contributions the classical pragmatists made to American intellectual life. Eric MacGilvray and Brendan Hogan both query the role, resources, and desirability for the epistemological justification in democratic theory, and specifically in Democratic Hope. Robert Talisse argues that the resources for pragmatic democratic theory cannot be drawn from the Deweyan stream of pragmatism given its commitment to both substantive goods on the one hand, and pluralism on the other. Robert Westbrook’s replies take into consideration these criticisms, extending his argument for democratic hope that is supportable by practices committed to the implicit commitment to moral claims that are truth-apt. NOTES 1. Robert Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1991). 2. Robert Westbrook, Democratic Hope: Pragmatism and the Politics of Truth (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 2005). Brendan Hogan Assistant Professor of Philosophy Philosophy Department Harstad 112 Pacific Lutheran University Tacoma, Washington 98447 United States Contemporary Pragmatism Editions Rodopi Vol. 4, No. 2 (December 2007), 3–9 © 2007 Pragmatism and the Epistemic Defense of Democracy Eric MacGilvray Robert Westbrook argues in Democratic Hope that for the pragmatist “all believers [must] be democrats simply by virtue of their desire to assert their beliefs as true,” and that they must therefore “open their beliefs to the widest possible range of experience and inquiry.” I argue against this view that doubt, not belief, lies at the center of the pragmatic theory of inquiry, and that our beliefs can be placed into doubt only by those whom we consider to be epistemically reliable. It follows that any connection between pragmatism and democracy must be empirical and not conceptual in nature. When I first became interested in pragmatism more than ten years ago, one of the first books that I turned to was Robert Westbrook’s seminal intellectual biography of John Dewey, John Dewey and American Democracy.1 It provided me with an invaluable road map through Dewey’s dauntingly large and wide- ranging corpus, the dauntingly wide range of political movements and figures that he was associated with, and the dauntingly complicated question of the relationship between his life and his thought. As I worked my way through Dewey’s writings over the next several years, I would often turn to Westbrook’s book for help in clarifying Dewey’s ideas, placing them within their proper context, and getting a sense of what I should look at next. It is still not at all uncommon for me to reach for it when I need to brush up on some point of
Recommended publications
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    03/05/2017 William James (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (ca. 1895, in The Letters of William James, ed. by Henry James, Boston, 1920) William James First published Thu Sep 7, 2000; substantive revision Tue Oct 29, 2013 William James was an original thinker in and between the disciplines of physiology, psychology and philosophy. His twelve­hundred page masterwork, The Principles of Psychology (1890), is a rich blend of physiology, psychology, philosophy, and personal reflection that has given us such ideas as “the stream of thought” and the baby's impression of the world “as one great blooming, buzzing confusion” (PP 462). It contains seeds of pragmatism and phenomenology, and influenced generations of thinkers in Europe and America, including Edmund Husserl, Bertrand Russell, John Dewey, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. James studied at Harvard's Lawrence Scientific School and the School of Medicine, but his writings were from the outset as much philosophical as scientific. “Some Remarks on Spencer's Notion of Mind as Correspondence” (1878) and “The Sentiment of Rationality” (1879, 1882) presage his future pragmatism and pluralism, and contain the first statements of his view that philosophical theories are reflections of a philosopher's temperament. James hints at his religious concerns in his earliest essays and in The Principles, but they become more explicit in The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (1897), Human Immortality: Two Supposed Objections to the Doctrine (1898), The Varieties of Religious Experience (1902) and A Pluralistic Universe (1909). James oscillated between thinking that a “study in human nature” such as Varieties could contribute to a “Science of Religion” and the belief that religious experience involves an altogether supernatural domain, somehow inaccessible to science but accessible to the individual human subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow*
    1 Metaphysics Today and Tomorrow* Raphaël Millière École normale supérieure, Paris – October 2011 Translated by Mark Ohm with the assistance of Leah Orth, Jon Cogburn, and Emily Beck Cogburn “By metaphysics, I do not mean those abstract considerations of certain imaginary properties, the principal use of which is to furnish the wherewithal for endless dispute to those who want to dispute. By this science I mean the general truths which can serve as principles for the particular sciences.” Malebranche Dialogues on Metaphysics and Religion 1. The interminable agony of metaphysics Throughout the twentieth century, numerous philosophers sounded the death knell of metaphysics. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Rudolf Carnap, Martin Heidegger, Gilbert Ryle, J. L. Austin, Jacques Derrida, Jürgen Habermas, Richard Rorty, and, henceforth, Hilary Putnam: a great many tutelary figures have extolled the rejection, the exceeding, the elimination, or the deconstruction of first philosophy. All these necrological chronicles do not have the same radiance, the same seriousness, nor the same motivations, but they all agree to dismiss the discipline, which in the past was considered “the queen of the sciences”, with a violence at times comparable to the prestige it commanded at the time of its impunity. Even today, certain philosophers hastily spread the tragic news with contempt for philosophical inquiry, as if its grave solemnity bestowed upon it some obviousness. Thus, Franco Volpi writes: ‘Grand metaphysics is dead!’ is the slogan which applies to the majority of contemporary philosophers, whether continentals or of analytic profession. They all treat metaphysics as a dead dog.1 In this way, the “path of modern thought” would declare itself vociferously “anti- metaphysical and finally post-metaphysical”.
    [Show full text]
  • Perspectives on Ethical Leadership: an Overview Drs Ir Sophia Viet MTD
    Perspectives on ethical leadership: an overview drs ir Sophia Viet MTD Paper submitted to the International Congress on Public and Political Leadership 2016 Draft version. Do not site or quote without the author’s permission Abstract There is a growing scientific interest in ethical leadership of organizations as public confidence in organizational leaders continues to decline. Among scholarly communities there is considerable disagreement on the appropriate way to conceptualize, define and study ethical leadership. This disagreement is partly due to the ontological and epistemological differences between the scholarly communities, resulting in different views of organizations, on the role of organizational leadership in general, and on ethical leadership of organizations in particular. Because of the differences in their ontological and epistemological assumptions scholars endlessly debate the concept of ethical leadership. This paper provides a comprehensive overview of the academic concepts of ethical leadership by classifying these concepts in terms of their ontological and epistemological assumptions and views of organizations into the modern, symbolic and the critical perspectives of postmodernism and communitarianism. Each category represents a particular set of perspectives on organizations, business ethics, and ethical leadership. The overview can serve as a guide to decode the academic debate and to determine the positions of the scholars participating in the debate. In addition it can serve as a multi-perspective-framework to study lay concepts of ethical leadership of (executive) directors of contemporary organizations. In this article the overview serves as a guide of how to classify some of the most common concepts in the debate on ethical leadership. Introduction There is a growing scientific interest in ethical leadership of organizations as public confidence in organizational leaders continues to decline.
    [Show full text]
  • Cultural Naturalism and the Market God David Timothy Denenny Southern Illinois University Carbondale, [email protected]
    Southern Illinois University Carbondale OpenSIUC Theses Theses and Dissertations 12-1-2018 Cultural Naturalism and the Market God David Timothy Denenny Southern Illinois University Carbondale, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/theses Recommended Citation Denenny, David Timothy, "Cultural Naturalism and the Market God" (2018). Theses. 2464. https://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/theses/2464 This Open Access Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at OpenSIUC. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of OpenSIUC. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CULTURAL NATURALISM AND THE MARKET GOD by David Denenny B.A. Eastern Washington University, 2015 A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Master of Arts Degree Department of Philosophy in the Graduate School Southern Illinois University Carbondale December 2018 Copyright by David Denenny, 2018 All Rights Reserved THESIS APPROVAL CULTURAL NATURALISM AND THE MARKET GOD by David Denenny A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the field of Philosophy Approved by: Kenneth William Stikkers, Chair Randall Auxier Alfred Frankowski Graduate School Southern Illinois University Carbondale November 8, 2018 AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF David Denenny, for the Master of Arts degree in Philosophy, presented on November 8, 2018, at Southern Illinois University Carbondale. TITLE: CULTURAL NATURALISM AND THE MARKET GOD MAJOR PROFESSOR: Dr. Kenneth William Stikkers This work employs John Dewey's cultural naturalism to explore how and why the orthodox economic tradition functions as a religious faith.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemology After the Modal Turn Traditionally
    Philosophy 513/Topics in Recent and Contemporary Philosophy: Epistemology after the Modal Turn Princeton University Spring 2019 Tuesdays 7-9:50 Marx 201 Professor Thomas Kelly 221 1879 Hall [email protected] Traditionally, philosophers have often given a starring role to notions like evidence and reasons for belief when theorizing about knowledge. However, in the last decades of the twentieth century and the opening decades of the twentieth-first, this traditional paradigm has been largely supplanted by alternative approaches. There are at least two complementary sources for this relatively recent, radical break with tradition. First, Edmund Gettier’s apparent refutation of “the traditional analysis of knowledge,” along with the failure of early, theoretically conservative attempts to “patch” that analysis, loosened the hold of the traditional paradigm on the philosophical imagination and created a demand for novel theoretical frameworks. More constructively, that demand for innovative approaches was met when the modal revolution, which had first entered analytic philosophy through logic and metaphysics (think Kripke, Lewis) hit epistemology. When epistemology took the modal turn, the result was an entirely new set of intriguing frameworks and powerful conceptual tools for theorizing about knowledge and related notions. Among these are the ideas that that we should think of knowledge in terms of the elimination of contextually salient possibilities (Lewis), that it consists in tracking facts (Nozick, Roush), and the increasingly influential picture of knowledge as safe belief (Williamson, Sosa). We will critically examine this currently flourishing tradition, beginning with seminal accounts by Lewis and Nozick, and continuing up to some of the latest developments.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom and Determinism (Topics in Contemporary Philosophy)
    1 Determinism: What We Have Learned and What We Still Don’t Know John Earman 1 Introduction The purpose of this essay is to give a brief survey of the implications of the theories of modern physics for the doctrine of determinism. The survey will reveal a curious feature of determinism: in some respects it is fragile, re- quiring a number of enabling assumptions to give it a fighting chance; but in other respects it is quite robust and very difficult to kill. The survey will also aim to show that, apart from its own intrinsic interest, determinism is an excellent device for probing the foundations of classical, relativistic, and quantum physics. The survey is conducted under three major presuppositions. First, I take a realistic attitude toward scientific theories in that I assume that to give an interpretation of a theory is, at a minimum, to specify what the world would have to be like in order for the theory to be true. But we will see that the demand for a deterministic interpretation of a theory can force us to abandon a naively realistic reading of the theory. Second, I reject the “no laws” view of science and assume that the field equations or laws of motion of the most fundamental theories of current physics represent science’s best guesses as to the form of the basic laws of nature. Third, I take deter- minism to be an ontological doctrine, a doctrine about the temporal evo- lution of the world. This ontological doctrine must not be confused with predictability, which is an epistemological doctrine, the failure of which need not entail a failure of determinism.
    [Show full text]
  • |||GET||| Euthyphro 1St Edition
    EUTHYPHRO 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE Plato | 9781605977409 | | | | | Euthyphro dilemma Tsedeq is something that happens here, and can be seen, and recognized, and known. Practical Ethics 3d ed. Related topics Criticism of religion Ethics in religion Exegesis Faith and rationality History of religions Religion and science Religious philosophy Theology. Roughly, it is the view that there are independent moral standards: some actions are right or wrong in themselves, independent of God's commands. Euthyphro's final suggestion is that holiness is a kind of trading with Euthyphro 1st edition gods, where we give them sacrifices and they grant our prayers. Socrates points out that if both options were true, they together would yield a vicious circle, with the gods loving the pious because it is the Euthyphro 1st edition, and the pious being the pious because the gods love it. Positions Aesthetics Formalism Institutionalism Aesthetic response. At this point the dilemma surfaces. Early life. Euthyphro's first definition of piety is what he is doing now, that is, prosecuting his father for manslaughter 5d. Clearly, the answer is again the latter, something becomes beloved when it is loved. Something is a meter long inasmuch as it is the same length as the standard meter bar, and likewise, something is good inasmuch as it approximates God. Essentialists apply labels to things because they possess certain essential qualities that make them what they are. Is something "beloved" in and of itself like being big or redor does it become beloved when it is loved by someone? Emrys Westacott is a professor Euthyphro 1st edition philosophy at Alfred University.
    [Show full text]
  • Minutes of the 2013 Business Meeting
    Minutes of the Business Meeting Charles Sanders Peirce Society 21 February 2013 Following the annual scholarly meeting, with papers by President Claudine Tiercelin ( “The Relevance of Peirce’s Scientific Metaphysics”) and Essay Contest winner Masato Ishida ( “Revisiting Convergence: A Peircean Reply to Quine’s Two Problems”), President Tiercelin called the meeting to order at 7:00 pm at the New Orleans Hilton Riverside. 1. Claudine Tiercelin asked for approval of the minutes of the 2010-11 business meeting. The minutes were approved. (Moved by Robert Lane, seconded by Cornelis de Waal.) 2. Claudine Tiercelin delivered the following report from the President and the Executive Committee: The committee met from 10:00am until about 11:30 am on the morning of Thursday February 21. Presentweree Robert Lane, Cornelis de Waal, Richard Atkins, Claudine Tiercelin (President), James Liszka (Vice-President), Shannon Dea (Secretary-Treasurer). We received regrets from Daniel Campos and Giovanni Maddalena, who were unable to attend. Chief among the issues discussed by the Executive Committee were the following. a) Bob Lane raised an issue brought to his attention by an electronic subscriber. It turns out that JSTOR only allows electronic subscribers access to 75 back issue articles per year. More seriously, these articles must be viewed as html files; they cannot be downloaded as pdfs. This is highly inconvenient, and may serve as a disincentive to our electronic subscribers. At a minimum, this limitation on electronic subscriptions should be made clear to people at the time they subscribe. Ideally, though, we would persuade IU Press/JSTOR to change this practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Approaching Contemporary Philosophy Historically
    APPROACHING CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS HISTORICALLY: On IDEALISMS, REALISMS, and PRAGMATISMS, Combining Undergraduate Teaching & Research Cinzia Ferrini University of Trieste [email protected] Abstract: As guest editor of this special issue of Esercizi Filosofici, the author introduces Kenneth R. Westphal’s and Paolo Parrini’s position papers on pragmatism, idealism and realism by elucidating the background and rationale of the workshop she organized on 29 April, 2015 at the Department of Humanities of the University of Trieste, within the frame- work of her undergraduate course in «History of Modern and Contemporary Philosophy». The Appendix lists questions posed by students and by the audience, to which the invited speakers replied in discussion following the presentations; their respective replies follow their main papers. Key Words: Teaching systematic philosophy historically; research and teaching for under- graduates; contemporary issues and modern philosophy; pragmatism. 1. Background The workshop, «A Real Dialogue on an Ideal Topic», with Kenneth R. Westphal1 and Paolo Parrini2 on idealism, realism and pragmatism took 1 Kenneth Westphal has held (full) professorships in philosophy in England (Norwich, Canterbury), visiting professorships at Northwestern University and at the Martin Luther Universität Halle (a.d.Salle), and research fellowships in Heidelberg, Bielefeld (twice) and Göttingen. He has now settled in Istanbul as Professor of Philosophy at Boðaziçi Üniversi- tesi. The main focus of his research is on the character
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Curriculum Vitae Benoit Gaultier (40 y/o) ⚫ Postdoctoral Research Fellow (Fonds zur Förderung des akademischen Nachwuchses), University of Zurich ⚫ Director of the Epistemology Research Group (GRÉ) of the Collège de France Email addresses: [email protected] [email protected] Phone: +33 645 80 10 42 Areas of speciality Epistemology ⚫ Pragmatism Areas of competence Philosophy of action ⚫ Metaphysics ⚫ Philosophy of mind ⚫ Current positions 2020-2024 Co-Director of the SNF-research project Suspension of judgement. Its nature and its norms, University of Zurich 2019-2021 Postdoc-Forschung of the Fonds zur Förderung des akademischen Nachwuchses, University of Zurich 2015– Director of the Epistemology Research Group (GRÉ) of the Chair in Metaphysics and Philosophy of Knowledge, Collège de France, Paris Previous positions 2018-2019 Postdoctoral Research Fellow, University of Zurich 2016–2020 Chargé de cours (Lecturer), University of Aix-Marseille, France 2013-2015 Postdoctoral Research Fellow, University of Helsinki (DiaMind project) 2011–2013 ATER (Lecturer), Chair in Metaphysics and Philosophy of Knowledge, Collège de France, Paris 2011–2013 Postdoc affiliate, Jean Nicod Institute, Paris Education 2020-2022 Habilitation à diriger des recherches 2014; 2018-… Qualification à la fonction de maître de conférences en philosophie 2004–2011 PhD in Philosophy (graduated with highest honors), Jean Nicod Institute & Univ. Paris-Est: Théorie et pratique dans la tradition pragmatiste. Supervisor: Claudine Tiercelin. 2003 Master of Research (with Class I Honours) in Philosophy, Univ. Paris I Panthéon-Sorbonne 2001–2002 Agrégation de philosophie: bi-admissibilité Scholarships 2003 Bourse de Master (Graduate Scholarship), Univ. Paris I Panthéon- Sorbonne 2002 Bourse d’agrégation, Univ.
    [Show full text]
  • John William Miller and Josiah Royce
    Idealist Affinities: John William Miller and Josiah Royce By Mark D. Moorman [Posted with permission of Mark D. Moorman. Presented at the 39th annual meeting of the Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy, New York City, March 15-17, 2012.] This paper will compare the philosophies of John William Miller and Josiah Royce with regard to philosophical idealism. We hope to highlight the idealist strain in Miller’s thought by showing some affinities with similar themes in Royce. The relaxed term “affinity” suits the vagaries of the term “idealism” itself.(1) Royce was well aware of this malleable breadth. Post-Kantian idealism, viewed in its whole range of manifestation, is not any one theory so much as a tendency, a spirit, a disposition to interpret life and human nature and the world in a certain general way—a tendency, meanwhile, so plastic, so manifold, so lively, as to be capable of appealing to extremely different minds, and of expressing itself in numerous hostile teachings.(2) The equivocity of the term idealism renders our comparison more a matter of loose ‘family resemblances’ than of clear cut categories. There is second difficulty with idealism as a point of comparison, its reputation. Discussing certain impediments to the reception of Miller’s work, Vincent Colapietro points out that Miller’s idealism is “likely to make him seem outdated and even quaint.”(3) Much of the revolt against idealism in the Twentieth century took the form of hasty ab extra dismissals which left caricatures and low regard in their wake.(4) Association with German idealism came to imply, not depth, but a lack of rigor.
    [Show full text]
  • “Poverty and Justice: Two Public Symposia Concerning Shelter and Food Security for the Poor”
    The Society for Philosophers in America (SOPHIA) Grant Application Submitted for the American Philosophical Association Grant Fund RFP June 27, 2013 “Poverty and Justice: Two Public Symposia Concerning Shelter and Food Security for the Poor” I. Names and Affiliations II. Abstract III. Account of the Project’s Purpose and Timeline IV. Project Budget Narrative V. Designation of the Fiscal Agent VI. Information about Other Funding Obtained or Sought VII. Promotion Plan VIII. Assessment plan IX. Photo collage from previous APA sponsored SOPHIA symposia X. Curriculum Vitae for Each Member of the Project Steering Committee I. Names and Affiliations The SOPHIA project steering committee for this grant proposal consists of: Dr. Douglas Anderson, Trustee of SOPHIA and Professor of Philosophy at Southern Illinois University Carbondale, Carbondale, IL. Dr. Jackie Kegley, Trustee of SOPHIA and Professor of Philosophy at California State University, Bakersfield, Bakersfield, CA. Dr. John J. McDermott, Trustee of SOPHIA, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Humanities and Abell Professor of Liberal Arts, Texas A & M University, College Station, TX. Dr. Eric Thomas Weber, Executive Director and Trustee of SOPHIA and Principal Investigator for this proposal, Associate Professor, Department of Public Policy Leadership, The University of Mississippi, 105 Odom Hall, University, MS, 38677, 662.915.1336 (office), 662.915.1954 (fax), [email protected]. If you have any questions regarding this proposal, please contact Dr. Weber. If you would like to learn more about SOPHIA, visit our Web site at http://www.philosophersinamerica.com. II. Abstract In 2014, SOPHIA will engage in dialogue with the communities surrounding our organizers’ universities, this year focusing on poverty and justice.
    [Show full text]