“Ubi Natura Facit Circulos in Essendo, Nos Facimus in Cognoscendo.” the Demonstrative Regressus and the Beginning of Modern Science in Catholic Scholastics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

“Ubi Natura Facit Circulos in Essendo, Nos Facimus in Cognoscendo.” the Demonstrative Regressus and the Beginning of Modern Science in Catholic Scholastics CHAPTER TEN “UBI NATURA FACIT CIRCULOS IN ESSENDO, NOS FACIMUS IN COGNOSCENDO.” THE DEMONSTRATIVE REGRESSUS AND THE BEGINNING OF MODERN SCIENCE IN CATHOLIC SCHOLASTICS 10.1 Scholastic and Cartesian Logic There can be no doubt that the regressus in proof-theory was one of the most important achievements of Venetian Aristotelianism. The classic definition was given by Jacopo Zabarella: Regressus vero est inter causam, et effectum, quando reciprocantur, et effec- tus est nobis notior, quam causa, quum enim semper a notioribus nobis progrediendum sit, prius ex effectu noto causam ignotam demonstramus, deinde causa cognita ab ea ad effectum demonstrandum regredimur, ut sciamus propterquid est.1 The regressus is particularly important when historians of philosophy and science seek to emphasize the progressive significance of the Aristotelian logic of the Renaissance, which is closer to our own period. It is thus sur- prising that there is no clear presentation of the regressus proof in the rel- evant handbooks of the twentieth century.2 Obviously, this is connected both to logic and to the philosophy of science. But it is surprising3 only when one underestimates the significance for the philosophy of science and the intention of Aristotle’s Analytics, especially the Posterior Analyt- ics, and when one overlooks the double function of that logic, namely, as utens and as docens, since it both sets out how thinking functions in keeping with its own nature, and teaches how thinking ought to func- tion. Presumably under the influence of Descartes (whose Regulae see the understanding as in need of guidance), but certainly on the model of the 1 Zabarella, Liber de regress, 324. Cf. Mikkeli, An Aristotelian Response, 92–101. 2 The best presentation is Jardine, “Epistemology of the sciences;” he describes his pre- sentation as “tentative.” See also Prins, “Zabarella,” and Ganthaler, “Weiterbildung.” Regres- sus is not mentioned in the discussion of Zabarella in Kneale, The Development of Logic, 306f. 3 R. Pozzo seems to be surprised by this: see his article “Regressus/progressus.” 184 chapter ten Port-Royal Logic,4 which translates the Regulae into the genre of a hand- book, the philosophy of science—the art of thinking (L’art de penser)— was clearly regarded above all as an artificial thinking. Knowledge became the business of emending thinking that was naturally defective. Paradoxi- cally, this was done on the basis of a naïve ontology of ideas that regarded everything as real that is thought clearly and lucidly.5 Accordingly, the syllogisms become less important, since it is not they that generate knowl- edge, but rather the clear and distinct ideas and the scientific methodol- ogy in the sense of regulated induction and teaching praxis. If one looks at the scholastic treatises of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, it is at once obvious, as the present study will endeavor to show that the significance of the theory of demonstratio in the Renaissance Aris- totelians lies precisely in the link between the philosophy of science and logic. I shall show, by means of a number of examples that I have selected almost exclusively according to the criterion of easy accessibility, that the school philosophers were concerned with the substantiality of logical argumentations and with the formal comprehensibility of that which is known with certainty. The adaptation, with varying degrees of intensity, of the Renaissance-Aristotelian theory sets out some of its implications, which are of fundamental interest for logic. As we would expect from the way in which the scholastics were aware of the problem, they struggle to save their doctrine from the Scylla of being irrelevant to academic research, but without succumbing to Charybdis of the methodology of the Cartesian enlightenment. From a scholastic per- spective, the ontological status of that which has been gained epistemo- logically is the decisive problem of philosophy. Early modern scholastics are interested not only in clear ideas, but also in objectively true ideas. Naturally, every manual of philosophy contains a section on demonstra- tio, unless it is already influenced by the Port-Royal Logic. By way of expla- nation, let me recall that the manuals of Catholic scholasticism from the end of the sixteenth century onwards are constructed in accordance with a strongly topical principle, so that it is easy to find out in a schematic manner what they have to say about any particular theme. Calculability (that is to say, the stability of the horizon of expectation) was the precise goal of this genre of manuals. The proof-theory is found towards the end 4 Arnauld and Nicole, La logique. 5 See the chapter on the Pophyrian Tree in this book and the chapter on Suárez in Blum, Philosophy of Religion in the Renaissance..
Recommended publications
  • Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2021 M
    Z Zabarella, Jacopo chair of logic, succeeding Tomitano. On 4 January 1569 he secured the second extraordinary chair of Born: 5 September 1533, Padua natural philosophy. There was likely a pause in his Died: 15 October 1589, Padua teaching from 1574 to 1576 on account of the severity of plague in Padua. On 26 March 1577 Marco Sgarbi he acquired the first extraordinary chair of natural Ca’ Foscari University of Venice, Venice, Italy philosophy, and in 1578, he published his Opera logica in Venice, thus opening a large debate on the Abstract order and method of knowledge among his con- temporaries – especially with Francesco Jacopo Zabarella (1553–1589) is considered Piccolomini (1520–1604) and Bernardino Petrella one of the most acute and brilliant logicians (1529–1595). In 1580 Zabarella published his of all time. He made an important contribution Tabulae logicae and also founded the Accademia to the interpretation of Aristotle and developed degli Stabili. In 1584, he came under attack in two original ideas especially in the field of logic directions: from Piccolomini in his Universa and epistemology, opening up the pathway of philosophia de moribus, and from Petrella in his early modern science. Logicarum disputationum libri VII. The same year, Zabarella’s reply to Piccolomini was his De doctrina ordine apologia. In the meantime, on Biography 6 September 1585, he became professor of the second ordinary chair of natural philosophy, and He was born in Padua on 5 September 1533, the the following year he published his De naturalis eldest son of Giulio Zabarella. He was well-versed scientiae constitutione.
    [Show full text]
  • The Unity of Science in Early-Modern Philosophy: Subalternation, Metaphysics and the Geometrical Manner in Scholasticism, Galileo and Descartes
    The Unity of Science in Early-Modern Philosophy: Subalternation, Metaphysics and the Geometrical Manner in Scholasticism, Galileo and Descartes by Zvi Biener M.A. in Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2004 B.A. in Physics, Rutgers University, 1995 B.A. in Philosophy, Rutgers University, 1995 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2008 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH FACULTY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Zvi Biener It was defended on April 3, 2008 and approved by Peter Machamer J.E. McGuire Daniel Garber James G. Lennox Paolo Palmieri Dissertation Advisors: Peter Machamer, J.E. McGuire ii Copyright c by Zvi Biener 2008 iii The Unity of Science in Early-Modern Philosophy: Subalternation, Metaphysics and the Geometrical Manner in Scholasticism, Galileo and Descartes Zvi Biener, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2008 The project of constructing a complete system of knowledge—a system capable of integrating all that is and could possibly be known—was common to many early-modern philosophers and was championed with particular alacrity by Ren´eDescartes. The inspiration for this project often came from mathematics in general and from geometry in particular: Just as propositions were ordered in a geometrical demonstration, the argument went, so should propositions be ordered in an overall system of knowledge. Science, it was thought, had to proceed more geometrico. I offer a new interpretation of ‘science more geometrico’ based on an analysis of the explanatory forms used in certain branches of geometry. These branches were optics, as- tronomy, and mechanics; the so-called subalternate, subordinate, or mixed-mathematical sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy May 20, 2013
    Outline of Philosophy May 20, 2013 Contents SOCI>Philosophy .............................................................................................................................................................. 3 SOCI>Philosophy>Aesthetics ....................................................................................................................................... 3 SOCI>Philosophy>Aesthetics>Beauty .................................................................................................................... 4 SOCI>Philosophy>Aesthetics>Theory .................................................................................................................... 4 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology ................................................................................................................................. 5 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>Possibility ......................................................................................................... 6 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>World ................................................................................................................ 6 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>Object Properties .............................................................................................. 6 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>System Properties ............................................................................................. 6 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>Representation .................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Lodovico Settala's Aristotelian Problemata Commentary and Late
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Archivio istituzionale della ricerca - Università degli Studi di Venezia Ca' Foscari Lodovico Settala’s Aristotelian Problemata Commentary and Late-Renaissance Hippocratic Medicine Craig Martin Key phrases Aristotelian Problemata; Hippocratic Airs, Waters, Places; Renaissance humanism; Lodovico Settala; Girolamo Cardano Abstract Renaissance physicians, influenced by humanism and spurred by their increased knowledge of Hippocratic and Galenic writings, attempted to assimilate these medical works with Aristotelian thought. The similarities between the Aristotelian Problemata and the Hippocratic Airs, Waters, Places allowed Girolamo Cardano and Lodovico Settala, among others, to blur the distinctions between natural philosophical and medical authorities. Philological and historical considerations of these texts as well as judgments about authenticity were colored by the belief that these works were useful for humoral physiology and offered insights into the unity of ancient and modern knowledge. 1 Introduction Late-Renaissance Italian intellectual debate often involved attempts to change or defend the status of particular disciplines. The hierarchy of subjects was frequently a matter for dispute, and leading intellectual figures attempted to raise the status of their particular fields. Just as this was true for mixed mathematics, it was also true for medicine. A number of physicians attempted 1 to promote the status of medicine by defining it as part
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTLE 2400 YEARS PROGRAMME.Pdf
    1 PROGRAMME Presentations’ Duration: • Invited Speakers in Plenary Sessions: 45΄ presentation & 15΄ discussion • Invited Speakers in Concurrent Sessions: 40΄ presentation & discussion • All Participants with contributed papers: 20΄ presentation & discussion 2 World Congress “Aristotle 2400 Years” Programme Schedule Monday May 23, 2016 8:00 Registration 10:30-12:30 Welcome City Tour 13:00-14:30 Concurrent Sessions A Invited Speaker Session A • Robert Bolton (USA) Techne and Empeiria: Aristotle's Contributions to the Tradition 14:30-16:00 Break / Free time 16:00-17:30 Concurrent Sessions B Invited Speaker Session B • George Contogeorgis (Greece) Ο Αριςτοτζλθσ και θ δθμοκρατία (Aristotle and Democracy) 17:30-18:00 Break 18:00-20:00 Opening Ceremony - Welcoming Remarks Inaugural Address • Evanghelos Moutsopoulos (Greece) Plenary Lecture A • Demetra Sfendoni-Mentzou (Greece) Aristotle’s Dynamic Vision of Nature and Contemporary Physics 20:00 Welcome Reception 3 World Congress “Aristotle 2400 Years” Tuesday May 24, 2016 8:00 Registration 9:00-10:30 Concurrent Sessions C Invited Speaker Session C • Dermot Moran (Ireland) Aristotle’s Conception of Ousia in the Medieval Christian Tradition: Some Neoplatonic Reflections 10:30-11:00 Break 11:00-12:00 Plenary Lecture B • Abraham Bos (The Netherlands) Aristotle on God’s Life-Generating Power and on Pneuma 12:00 Departure for ancient Mieza 13:30 Arrival to ancient Mieza 13:30-14:30 Welcoming Reception of the Mayor of Naoussa 14:30-15:30 Plenary Lecture C • Lambros Couloubaritsis (Belgium/Greece) The Complex Organisation of Aristotle's Thought 15:30-17:30 Guided Tour 17:30 Departure for Thessaloniki 19:00 Arrival to Thessaloniki 19:30-21:00 Plenary Lecture / Public Event: Armand Marie Leroi (UK) Aristotle & the New Biology 4 World Congress “Aristotle 2400 Years” Wednesday May 25, 2016 8:00 Registration 9:00-10:30 Concurrent Sessions D Invited Speaker Session D • Loucas G.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Philosophy
    Natural philosophy Natural philosophy or philosophy of nature (from Latin philosophia naturalis) was the philosophical study of nature and the physical universe that was dominant before the development of modern science. It is considered to be the precursor of natural science. From the ancient world, starting with Aristotle, to the 19th century, the term "natural philosophy" was the common term used to describe the practice of studying nature. It was in the 19th century that the A celestial map from the 17th century, by the concept of "science" received its modern shape with Dutch cartographer Frederik de Wit new titles emerging such as "biology" and "biologist", "physics" and "physicist" among other technical fields and titles; institutions and communities were founded, and unprecedented applications to and interactions with other aspects of society and culture occurred.[1] Isaac Newton's book Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687 ), whose title translates to "Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy", reflects the then-current use of the words "natural philosophy", akin to "systematic study of nature". Even in the 19th century, a treatise by Lord Kelvin and Peter Guthrie Tait, which helped define much of modern physics, was titled Treatise on Natural Philosophy (1867 ). In the German tradition, Naturphilosophie (philosophy of nature) persisted into the 18th and 19th century as an attempt to achieve a speculative unity of nature and spirit. Some of the greatest names in German philosophy are associated with this movement, including Goethe, Hegel and Schelling. Naturphilosophie was associated with Romanticism and a view that regarded the natural world as a kind of giant organism, as opposed to the philosophical approach of figures such as John Locke and Isaac Newton who espoused a more mechanical view of the world, regarding it as being like a machine.
    [Show full text]
  • The Preservation of the Whole and the Teleology of Nature in Late Medieval, Renaissance and Early Modern Debates on the Void
    Manzo, Silvia The Preservation of the Whole and the Teleology of Nature in Late Medieval, Renaissance and Early Modern Debates on the Void Journal of Early Modern Studies 2013, vol. 2, nro. 2, p. 9-34 Manzo, S. (2013). The Preservation of the Whole and the Teleology of Nature in Late Medieval, Renaissance and Early Modern Debates on the Void. Journal of Early Modern Studies, 2 (2), 9-34. En Memoria Académica. Disponible en: http://www.memoria.fahce.unlp.edu.ar/art_revistas/pr.10044/pr.10044.pdf Información adicional en www.memoria.fahce.unlp.edu.ar Esta obra está bajo una Licencia Creative Commons Atribución-NoComercial-CompartirIgual 4.0 Internacional https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/ ������������������������ �������� � ������������������������������� � ������������������������ �������������������������� ����������������� ��������������������������� ����� ����������������� ����������� ������������������ ������������������ ���������������������������� ����������������������������� ������������������������ ������������ � ������������������������ �������� � � ����������� � � ����������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������� ������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������� ����������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������� ����� �������������� ������������ ���� ���� �������� �������� ���� ��������� ��������� �������� ��� �� ���������������������������������������������������������������������������������������
    [Show full text]
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West
    03/05/2017 Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West First published Fri Sep 19, 2008; substantive revision Tue Mar 18, 2014 The Arabic­Latin translation movements in the Middle Ages, which paralleled that from Greek into Latin, led to the transformation of almost all philosophical disciplines in the medieval Latin world. The impact of Arabic philosophers such as al­Fārābī, Avicenna and Averroes on Western philosophy was particularly strong in natural philosophy, psychology and metaphysics, but also extended to logic and ethics. Among the influential Arabic theories are: the logical distinction between first and second intentions; the intension and remission of elementary forms; the soul's faculty of estimation and its object, the intentions; the conjunction between human intellect and separate active intellect; the unicity of the material intellect (Averroism); naturalistic theories of miracles and prophecy; the eternity of the world and the concept of eternal creation; the active intellect as giver of forms; the first cause as necessary existent; the emanation of intelligences from the first cause; the distinction between essence and existence; the theory of primary concepts; the concept of human happiness as resulting from perfect conjunction of the human intellect with the active intellect. 1. Transmission 2. Division of the Sciences 3. Logic 4. Natural Philosophy 4.1 Eternity of the World 4.2 The Elements in a Compound 4.3 Spontaneous Generation 5. Psychology 5.1 Estimation 5.2 Active Intellect 5.3 The Four Intellects 5.4 Averroes' Unicity Thesis 5.5 Naturalistic Theories of Prophecy 6.
    [Show full text]
  • Renaissance Aristotelianism OSKAR KRISTELLER, PAUL Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Summer 1965; 6, 2; Proquest Pg
    Renaissance Aristotelianism OSKAR KRISTELLER, PAUL Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Summer 1965; 6, 2; ProQuest pg. 157 Renaissance Aristotelianism Paul Oskar Kristeller HEN we try to understand the historical significance of W Renaissance Aristotelianism, we have to face very great difficulties. The number of its representatives and the variety of their views seems to defy any common description, and this situation is further complicated by the persistent attack to which the school was subjected from different quarters. Moreover, the Aristotel­ ians were in many ways influenced by ideas and methods that origin­ ated outside their own tradition, and on the other hand, most of the avowed opponents of Aristotelianism were more deeply influenced by it than they knew. We must add that Renaissance Aristotelianism has been neglected by most historians and is still unexplored in many of its sectors. Humanism and Platonism have long been considered peculiar to the Renaissance period, and their mediaeval antecedents have but recently received some scholarly attention. Aristotelianism, on the other hand, is so clearly a heritage and continuation of the mediaeval period that most scholars concerned with the Renaissance have tended to treat it as an unimportant residue of the preceding age and have uncritically repeated the charges made against it by its Renaissance opponents, whereas most students of mediaeval philos­ ophy have focused their attention on the twelfth and thirteenth centuries and have tended to sacrifice the supposedly decadent scholasticism of the following centuries to the scorn of its enemies. Thus Renaissance Aristotelianism is a historical phenomenon which we are just beginning to understand in its proper significance.1 The intrinsic importance and historical influence of Aristotle are such an obvious fact that we may be surprised to learn that during the later centuries of classical antiquity his authority and influence were 1 B.
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago Kant's Conception of Logic
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO KANT’S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC VOLUME ONE A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY CLINTON TOLLEY CHICAGO, ILLINOIS JUNE 2007 © 2007, Clinton Tolley TABLE OF CONTENTS VOLUME ONE List of Tables....................................................................................................................... v Acknowledgements ........................................................................................................... vi Abstract.............................................................................................................................. xii INTRODUCTION: WHY KANT’S LOGIC NOW?................................................ 1 §I. Rethinking Kant’s Debt to Aristotle............................................................. 1 §II. Avoiding Anachronism and Compartmentalism ...................................... 5 §III. Kant’s Logic: Influence and Prospects ................................................... 17 §IV. The Historical Context of Kant’s Logical Doctrines............................ 25 §V. Kant’s ‘Writings’ on Logic .......................................................................... 38 CHAPTER I: THE PLACE OF LOGIC IN KANT’S ARCHITECTONIC...... 45 A. Preliminary Remarks (§1).............................................................................. 45 B. Pre-Kantian Disciplinary Classifications of Logic (§§2-3)....................... 52 C. Logic in the
    [Show full text]
  • Induction Before Hume
    INDUCTION BEFORE HUME J. R. Milton The word ‘Induction’ and its cognates in other languages, of which for present purposes the most important is Latin ‘inductio’, have a complex semantic history, as does the Greek ἐπαγωγή from which they were derived. Though some of these uses — electromagnetic induction, or the induction of a clergyman into a new benefice — are manifestly irrelevant, others that still diverge significantly from any of the uses current among present-day philosophers and logicians are not. As will soon become apparent, any attempt to write a history that focused solely on the direct ancestors of modern usage would be arduous if not impossible to execute, and deeply unsatisfactory if it could brought to a conclusion. The net must, at least initially, be cast more widely. Another potential problem is that there may have been philosophers who dis- cussed problems of inductive inference without using the word ‘induction’ (or its equivalents) at all. The most conspicuous suspect here is David Hume, who has been widely seen — in the twentieth century at least 1 — as an inductive scep- tic, even though it is notorious that he rarely used the word, and never in the passages where his inductive scepticism has been located. Whether or not this interpretation of Hume is correct lies outside the scope of this chapter, but it is at least entirely clear that the issue cannot be decided simply from an analysis of Hume’s vocabulary. In the Hellenistic era discussions of non-deductive inference were centred on what became known as inference from signs ( semeiosis ).
    [Show full text]
  • Jacopo Zabarella Was One of the Most Important and Influential Thinkers Working Within the Aristotelian Tradition in the Sixteen
    STUDI ZABARELLA AND THE INTENTIONALITY OF SENSATION1 di James B. South Jacopo Zabarella was one of the most important and influential thinkers working within the Aristotelian tradition in the Sixteenth Century2. In this pa- per, I discuss the approach he takes to one of the most controversial issues in Aristotle’s thought, namely, the nature of sensory experience. Aristotle’s theory of sensation has been at the center of recent scholarship and the inter- pretive lines are clearly drawn. On the one hand, there are those who believe that Aristotle holds that sensation is a material process, while others hold that he believes it is a spiritual or immaterial one3. The purpose of this paper is not to develop a new interpretation of Aristotle, but to show how one important sixteenth century Aristotelian thinker dealt with the ambiguities in Aristotle’s texts. Now, one important aspect in the development of interpretations of Aristo- tle’s account of sensation was the introduction by Avicenna of the notion of “intention” in the context of sensation. These intentions, or meanings, stand at 1. An early version of this paper was read at the 2000 meeting of The Renaissance So- ciety of America in Florence, Italy and audience questions and comments provided me with helpful feedback. I want to thank the Marquette University Philosophy Department for granting me a reduced course load in the Fall 2000 semester that allowed me time to com- plete the paper. Also, I would like to thank Prof. Edward P. Mahoney both for his encoura- gement and for many helpful conversations about Renaissance Aristotelianism.
    [Show full text]