Platonic Division and the Origins of Aristotelian Logic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Platonic Division and the Origins of Aristotelian Logic Platonic Division and the Origins of Aristotelian Logic By Justin Joseph Vlasits A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Timothy Clarke, Co-Chair Professor Klaus Corcilius, Co-Chair Professor John MacFarlane Professor GRF Ferrari Summer 2017 Abstract Platonic Division and the Origins of Aristotelian Logic by Justin Joseph Vlasits Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professor Timothy Clarke, Co-Chair Professor Klaus Corcilius, Co-Chair Aristotle’s syllogistic theory, as developed in his Prior Analytics, is often regarded as the birth of logic in Western philosophy. Over the past century, scholars have tried to identify important precursors to this theory. I argue that Platonic division, a method which aims to give accounts of essences of natural kinds by progressively narrowing down from a genus, influenced Aristotle’s logical theory in a number of crucial respects. To see exactly how, I analyze the method of division as it was originally conceived by Plato and received by Aristotle. I argue that, while Plato allowed that some divisions fail to rigorously investigate the essence, he began a program continued by Aristotle (and others in antiquity and the middle ages) of seeking norms for division that would apply in any domain whatsoever. This idea of a rigorous, general method was taken up and developed by Aristotle in his syllogistic. Aristotle also used Plato’s conception of predication as parthood in his semantics for syllogistic propositions. As part of my argument, I prove that a semantics based on Platonic divisional structures is sound and complete for the deduction system used in the literature to model Aristotle’s syllogistic. 1 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 The Puzzle of the Sophist 11 2.1 The Traditional View of Division and the Puzzle of the Sophist. 12 2.2 MinimalView: PredicationandTransitivity . ..... 19 2.3 AgainsttheTraditionalView . 22 2.3.1 Dichotomy.............................. 23 2.3.2 Exclusivity.............................. 25 2.3.3 EssentialPredication . 34 2.4 ThePuzzleAgain .............................. 36 3 The Goal and Norms of Platonic Division 39 3.1 Goal...................................... 40 3.2 TwoNorms ................................. 42 3.2.1 TheTortoiseNorm . .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 42 3.2.2 TheMinimizationNorm. 49 3.3 Conclusion:Plato’sProgram. 52 4 The (Ab)use of Division in the Analytics 56 4.1 APr I.31:Divisiondoesnotsyllogize . 57 4.2 APo II.5:Divisionanddemonstration . 65 4.3 APo II.13:Definingwithdivision . 68 4.3.1 EssenceandGenus . .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 70 4.3.2 Theorderofinquiry . 73 4.3.3 Definingthesimplespecies . 76 4.3.4 Theaccountofthesummumgenus . 93 4.4 Conclusion.................................. 94 5 Division, Syllogistic Method, and Science in Prior Analytics I.31 99 5.1 The Puzzle of APr I.31 ...........................100 5.1.1 Division ...............................100 5.1.2 Syllogistic ..............................101 5.1.3 ThePuzzle..............................102 5.1.4 Previousresolutionsofthepuzzle . 105 i CONTENTS 5.2 DivisionandSyllogisticasscientificmethods . .. ..108 5.2.1 EpistemicGenerality . .108 5.2.2 Rigor.................................110 5.3 InvestigatingMereologicalRelations . .112 5.4 ResolvingthePuzzle . .. .. .. .. .. .. .. ..115 6 The Influence of Platonic Division on Aristotelian Syllogistic 119 6.1 The Question of Division and the Syllogistic . .121 6.2 LogicandMethod..............................125 A Mereology in Aristotle’s Assertoric Syllogistic 129 A.1 The Mereological Interpretation of Predication . .......131 A.2 AlgebraicSemantics . .. .. .. .. .. .. .. ..133 A.2.1 Soundness..............................134 A.2.2 Completeness . .. .. .. .. .. .. .. ..135 A.2.3 ASemanticHierarchy . .137 A.3 TheMereological InterpretationVindicated . .. ..137 Bibliography 139 ii Acknowledgements The initial impetus for this dissertation came from Alan Code’s seminar “Aristotle on Definition” at Stanford in Winter 2012. There I was struck by the importance of the method of division for Aristotle’s account of essence and definition. In Fall 2012, Tim Clarke taught a seminar on Plato’s Sophist where I began to develop the ideas of Chapter 2 and realized that an interesting story could be told relating Plato and Aristotle on these issues. Discussions with Marko Malink since 2013 further spurred me to connect this work with Aristotle’s syllogistic. Philosophy in the Socratic tradition was always fundamentally a conversation. This dissertation itself is a product of many, many such conversations. I’m grateful to everyone who suggested new paths, pointed out my frequent missteps, and encouraged me to dig deeper. Your words have made an impression on every page. While I have been working on this project, I’ve had the benefit of incredibly helpful audiences at UC Berkeley, UC Davis, LMU-Munich, Marquette University, Northwestern University, and the West Coast Plato Workshop. For stimulating conversations and comments on papers, I am indebted to Andreas Anagnostopou- los, Michael Arsenault, Joseph Bjelde, Robert Bolton, Adam Bradley, David Bron- stein, Lara Buchak, Chris Buckels, Agnes Callard, John Campbell, Nicola Carraro, Alan Code, Michel Crubellier, Shamik Dasgupta, Huw Duffy, David Ebrey, Dan Esses, Emily Fletcher, Mary Louise Gill, Owen Goldin, Laura Grams, Mark Griffith, Verity Harte, George Harvey, Dhananjay Jagannathan, Sarah Jansen, Ethan Jerzak, Jeff Kaplan, Sean Kelsey, Alex Kerr, Elaine Landry, Richard Lawrence, Tony Long, Paolo Mancosu, Sara Magrin, Marko Malink, Richard McKirahan, Katy Meadows, Connie Meinwald, Josh Mendelsohn, Mitchell Miller, Georgia Mouroutsou, Emily Perry, Christian Pfeiffer, Kristin Primus, Christof Rapp, Jeremy Reid, Jason Rheins, George Rudebusch, David Sedley, Jan Szaif, Richard Taylor, Voula Tsouna, Daniel Warren, and John Wynne. I have been incredibly fortunate to have so many thoughtful and inspiring ad- visors. In many ways Klaus Corcilius and Tim Clarke were ideal committee chairs. They managed to simultaneously give me room to try out my latest bizarre ideas and managing to bring me back to earth. John MacFarlane and John Ferrari went above and beyond in giving feedback on work and always challenging me to con- nect my work to broader philosophical issues. Katja Vogt, while not officially on my committee, has been a mentor in so many ways since I took my first course on iii CONTENTS ancient philosophy with her in 2009. This dissertation would not have been possible without Anna Vlasits. I don’t know what I would be without her. Every day I am indebted to her energy, com- mitment, and encouragement. Her intellect and good sense have challenged me to improve myself both in my work and in our marriage. iv Chapter 1 Introduction What is Plato’s method of division? Plato himself takes the trouble to show us, at least superficially. In the dialogue Sophist, the Eleatic Visitor is trying to explain to his interlocutors how he will pursue his investigation of sophistry. While this is probably not the earliest dialogue in which the method appears,1 it is the one where we get the most thorough example of someone self-consciously carrying it out in order to show someone how it is to be done: Visitor: Well then, let’s go after the angler from this starting point. Tell me, shall we take him to be an expert at something, or a nonexpert with another sort of capacity? Theaetetus: He’s definitely not a nonexpert. V: But expertise as a whole falls pretty much into two types. T: How? V: There’s farming, or any sort of caring for any mortal body; and there’s also caring for things that are put together or fabricated, which we call equipment; and there’s imitation. The right thing would be to call all those things by a single name. T: How? What name? V: When you bring anything into being that wasn’t in being before, we say you’re a producer and that the thing you’ve brought into being is produced. T: That’s right. 1See Lukas (1888) for discussion of division in nine Platonic dialogues. However, he does not discuss the Euthyphro (see below, also Meinwald (2002)) or Cratylus (Ademollo, 2011). While the method arguably appears frequently, it is only emphasized and thoroughly described in the Phae- drus, Sophist, Statesman, and Philebus. Although I don’t need to argue for it here, the pervasiveness of division throughout the Platonic corpus puts pressure on the idea that there is some sort of de- velopment in Plato’s thinking from Socratic elenchus to the method of hypothesis to the method of collection and division. Robinson (1953) goes so far as to delimit his subject by the absence of this final stage. 1 Chapter 1. Introduction V: And all the things we went through just now have their own capacity for that. T: Yes. V: Let’s put them under the heading of production. T: All right. V: Next, consider the whole type that has to do with learning, recogni- tion, commerce, combat, and hunting. None of these creates anything. They take things that are or have come into being, and they take pos- session of some of them with words and actions, and they keep other things from being taken possession of. For that reason it would be ap- propriate to call all the parts of this type acquisition. T: Yes, that would be appropriate. V: If every expertise falls under acquisition or production, Theaetetus, which one shall we put angling in? T: Acquisition, obviously. V: Aren’t there two types of expertise in acquisition? ...... V: So now we’re in agreement about the angler’s expertise, not just as to its name; in addition we’ve also sufficiently grasped a verbal expla- nation concerning the thing itself. Within expertise as a whole one half was acquisitive; half of the acquisitive was taking possession; half of possession-taking was hunting; half of hunting was animal hunting; half of animal hunting was aquatic hunting; all of the lower portion of aquatic hunting was fishing; half of fishing was hunting by strik- ing; and half of striking was hooking.
Recommended publications
  • The Coherence of Stoic Ontology
    The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Prof. Dorothea Frede, Co-chair Prof. Klaus Corcilius, Co-chair Prof. A.A. Long Spring 2012 Abstract The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professors Dorothea Frede and Klaus Corcilius, Co-chairs Any thoroughgoing physicalist is challenged to give an account of immaterial entities such as thoughts and mathematical objects. The Stoics, who eagerly affirmed that only bodies exist, crafted an elegant solution to this challenge: not everything that is Something (ti) exists. Rather, some things have a derivative mode of reality they call subsistence: these entities are non-existent in that they are not themselves solid bodies, but they are nonetheless Something physical because they depend on bodies for their subsistence. My dissertation uncovers the unifying principles of Stoic subsistence, and shows how they can account for thoughts and other immaterial entities without running afoul of their physicalist commitments. While all commentators agree that the Stoics posited Something as the highest category of being, they have failed to find a coherent physicalist account of Stoic ontology. For instance, (1) a canonical set of incorporeals (time, place, void, and what is sayable (lekton)) is well attested, but there is little agreement as to what these entities have in common as incorporeals, which makes the category look like an ad hoc collection of left-over entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Platons Raumbegriff Verständlich, Desgleichen Der Umstand, Daß Timaios Grenzen Einer Erklärung Der Welt Und Schwierigkeiten Einer Konsistenten Darstellung Hervorhebt
    Der Begriff des Raumes im „Timaios“ im Zusammenhang mit der Naturphilosophie und der Metaphysik Platons Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades der Philosophie der Philosophischen Fakultät der Universität Konstanz vorgelegt von Kyung Jik Lee aus Seoul Referent: Prof. Dr. Jürgen Mittelstraß Korreferent: Prof. Dr. Gereon Wolters Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 19. Juli 1999 Diese Arbeit erscheint im Mai 2000 auch als Buchhandelsausgabe im Verlag Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg Meinen Eltern gewidmet Inhaltsverzeichnis Vorwort 9 I Die Erklärung der Welt als wahrscheinliche Erklärung (eikôs logos) 11 1 Einleitung 2 Die Synonymität von eikôs mythos und eikôs logos 3 Der eikôs logos als nicht-philosophische Erklärung 4 Der eikôs logos 4.1 Akribês logos? 4.2 Das Wahrscheinliche und das Historische 4.3 Das Wahrscheinliche und das Notwendige 4.4 Die wahrscheinliche Rede als inkonsistente Rede 4.5 Die wahrscheinliche Rede als hypothetische Anwendung einer exakten Erklärung auf sinnliche Gegenstände 4.6 Die wahrscheinliche Rede als Begrenzung der Anwendung einer exakten Erklärung auf sinnliche Gegenstände II Der Demiurg und der Logos der Welt 38 1 Einleitung 2 Wer ist der Demiurg im „Timaios“? 3 Demiurg und Gott 4 Demiurg und Weltseele 5 Demiurg und Idee des Guten 6 Demiurg und transzendente Vernunft 7 Schwierigkeiten der Rede vom Demiurgen 7.1 Zur Suche nach dem Demiurgen 7.2 Logos und Ergon 7.3 Demiurg und Timaios 7.3.1 Einleitung 7.3.2 Poiêtês 7.3.3 Weitere Parallelen zwischen Demiurg und Timaios 7.3.4 Gott und Götter 7.4 Der Demiurg
    [Show full text]
  • Interpretation: a Journal of Political Philosophy
    Interpretation A JOURNAL J_OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY Winter 1998 Volume 26 Number 2 149 Jules Gleicher Moses Politikos 183 Tucker Landy The Limitations of Political Philosophy: An Interpretation of Plato's Charmides 201 Jason A. Tipton Love of Gain, Philosophy and Tyranny: A Commentary on Plato's Hipparchus 217 Larry Peterman Changing Titles: Some Suggestions about the "Prince" Use of in Machiavelli and Others 239 Catherine H. Zuckert Leadership Natural and Conventional in Melville's "Benito Cereno" 257 Jon Fennell Harry Neumann and the Political Piety of Rorty's Postmodernism Book Reviews 275 George Anastaplo Aristotle's "Physics": A Guided Study, by Joe Sachs 285 Michael P. Zuckert Shakespeare and the Good Life, by David Lowenthal 295 Joan Stambaugh Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil, by Rudiger Safranski 299 Patrick Coby Hypocrisy and Integrity: Machiavelli, Rousseau and the Ethics of Politics, by Ruth Grant 305 Susan Orr Leo Strauss and the American Right, by Shadia Drury 309 Will Morrisey Public Morality and Liberal Society: Essays on Decency, Law, and Pornography, by Harry M. Clor Interpretation Editor-in-Chief Hilail Gildin, Dept. of Philosophy, Queens College Executive Editor Leonard Grey General Editors Seth G. Benardete Charles E. Butterworth Hilail Gildin Robert Horwitz (d. 1987) Howard B. White (d. 1974) Consulting Editors Christopher Bruell Joseph Cropsey Ernest L. Fortin John Hallowell (d. 1992) Harry V. Jaffa David Lowenthal Muhsin Mahdi Harvey C. Mansfield Arnaldo Momigliano (d. 1987) Michael Oakeshott (d. 1990) Ellis Sandoz Leo Strauss (d. 1973) Kenneth W. Thompson International Editors Terence E. Marshall Heinrich Meier Editors Wayne Ambler Maurice Auerbach Fred Baumann Amy Bonnette Patrick Coby Elizabeth C de Baca Eastman Thomas S.
    [Show full text]
  • Marvelling at a Youth's Good Looks
    Marvelling at a youth’s good looks The gaze and Classical pederastic culture in ancient Greece MA thesis in Ancient History By: Nicky Schreuder (s1342460) Supervisor: Dr. K. Beerden Date: 26/07/2019 Cover: Drinking cup (kylix) with youth running, attributed to the Triptolemos Painter (c. 500 BC). Museum of Fine Arts Boston, inv. 13.81. 1 Contents Introduction ........................................................................................................................3 Historiography and inquiry .............................................................................................4 Methodology and sources ...............................................................................................7 Chapter 1. Gaze theory ...................................................................................................... 10 1.1 The psychoanalytical approach ............................................................................... 10 1.2 The feminist take .................................................................................................... 12 1.3 Criticisms and reactions.......................................................................................... 14 1.4 Relativity and application to ancient Greece ........................................................... 15 Chapter 2. Catching the eye of Sokrates. Plato, Xenophon and the pederastic gaze ............ 19 2.1 Ancient theories of sight ......................................................................................... 20 2.2 Plato
    [Show full text]
  • Citations in Classics and Ancient History
    Citations in Classics and Ancient History The most common style in use in the field of Classical Studies is the author-date style, also known as Chicago 2, but MLA is also quite common and perfectly acceptable. Quick guides for each of MLA and Chicago 2 are readily available as PDF downloads. The Chicago Manual of Style Online offers a guide on their web-page: http://www.chicagomanualofstyle.org/tools_citationguide.html The Modern Language Association (MLA) does not, but many educational institutions post an MLA guide for free access. While a specific citation style should be followed carefully, none take into account the specific practices of Classical Studies. They are all (Chicago, MLA and others) perfectly suitable for citing most resources, but should not be followed for citing ancient Greek and Latin primary source material, including primary sources in translation. Citing Primary Sources: Every ancient text has its own unique system for locating content by numbers. For example, Homer's Iliad is divided into 24 Books (what we might now call chapters) and the lines of each Book are numbered from line 1. Herodotus' Histories is divided into nine Books and each of these Books is divided into Chapters and each chapter into line numbers. The purpose of such a system is that the Iliad, or any primary source, can be cited in any language and from any publication and always refer to the same passage. That is why we do not cite Herodotus page 66. Page 66 in what publication, in what edition? Very early in your textbook, Apodexis Historia, a passage from Herodotus is reproduced.
    [Show full text]
  • The Prosecutors of Socrates and the Political Motive Theory
    Portland State University PDXScholar Dissertations and Theses Dissertations and Theses 2-1981 The prosecutors of Socrates and the political motive theory Thomas Patrick Kelly Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/open_access_etds Part of the Intellectual History Commons, and the Political History Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Kelly, Thomas Patrick, "The prosecutors of Socrates and the political motive theory" (1981). Dissertations and Theses. Paper 2692. https://doi.org/10.15760/etd.2689 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF Thomas Patrick Kelly for the Master of Arts in History presented February 26, 1981. Title: The Prosecutors of Socrates and The Political Motive Theory. APPROVED BY MEMBERS OF THE THESIS CO~rnITTEE: ~~varnos, Cha1rman Charles A. Le Guin Roderlc D1man This thesis presents a critical analysis of the histor- ical roles assigned to the prosecutors of Socrates by modern historians. Ancient sources relating to the trial and the principles involved, and modern renditions, especially those of John Burnet and A. E. Taylor, originators of the theory that the trial of Socrates was politically motivated, are critically 2 analyzed and examined. The thesis concludes that the political motive theory is not supported by the evidence on which it relies. THE PROSECUTORS OF SOCRATES AND THE POLITICAL MOTIVE THEORY by THOMAS PATRICK KELLY A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS in HISTORY Portland State University 1981 TO THE OFFICE OF GRADUATE STUDIES AND RESEARCH: The members of the Committee approve the thesis of Thomas Patrick Kelly presented February 26, 1981.
    [Show full text]
  • The Family Connection of Alcibiades and Axiochus , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 27:2 (1986:Summer) P.173
    STANLEY, PHILLIP V., The Family Connection of Alcibiades and Axiochus , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 27:2 (1986:Summer) p.173 The Family Connection of Alcibiades and Axiochus Phillip V. Stanley LTHOUGH THE ANCESTRY of the Athenian general Alcibiades A III remains obscure for the sixth century, his genealogy is as­ sumed to be secure for the fifth. The descent of the family from Alcibiades I to Alcibiades IV has been reconstructed by Vander­ pool in the following way:l Alcibiades J2 I Cleinias I I Alcibiades II I I Axiochus Cleinias II I I I I Cleinias III Alcibiades III Cleinias IV I Alcibiades IV I E. Vanderpool, "The Ostracism of the Elder Alcibiades," Hesperia 21 (I952) 1-8, esp. 6. Cr. M. B. Wallace, "Early Greek Proxenoi," Phoenix 24 (I 970) 196f; 1. K. DAVIES, Athenian Propertied Families (Oxford 1971 [hereafter APF)) 10-12. According to Isoc. 16.25f (delivered by Alcibiades IV, son of the general), Alcibiades I, the ally of Cleisthenes when he expelled Hippias from Athens, was the great-grandfather (1TpO- 1Ta1T1To~) of Alcibiades III. The general difficulty stems from the apparent need to reduce the number of generations separating Alcibiades I from Alcibiades III, believed to be five: if the number is not reduced, Alcibiades I would actually be the great-great­ grandfather of the general. 2 Roman numerals are those assigned in PA and APF. These numerals will continue to be used even when homonyms are added to the family's genealogy. In order to avoid the confusion that might result if a major overhaul of the numerical system for this family were attempted, and to preserve the numerical descent established for the branch of the family to which Alcibiades III belongs, the newly identified individual will be assigned the next available Roman numeral, even though he may be earlier than an individual with the same name whose number is lower.
    [Show full text]
  • John P. Burgess Department of Philosophy Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544-1006, USA [email protected]
    John P. Burgess Department of Philosophy Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544-1006, USA [email protected] LOGIC & PHILOSOPHICAL METHODOLOGY Introduction For present purposes “logic” will be understood to mean the subject whose development is described in Kneale & Kneale [1961] and of which a concise history is given in Scholz [1961]. As the terminological discussion at the beginning of the latter reference makes clear, this subject has at different times been known by different names, “analytics” and “organon” and “dialectic”, while inversely the name “logic” has at different times been applied much more broadly and loosely than it will be here. At certain times and in certain places — perhaps especially in Germany from the days of Kant through the days of Hegel — the label has come to be used so very broadly and loosely as to threaten to take in nearly the whole of metaphysics and epistemology. Logic in our sense has often been distinguished from “logic” in other, sometimes unmanageably broad and loose, senses by adding the adjectives “formal” or “deductive”. The scope of the art and science of logic, once one gets beyond elementary logic of the kind covered in introductory textbooks, is indicated by two other standard references, the Handbooks of mathematical and philosophical logic, Barwise [1977] and Gabbay & Guenthner [1983-89], though the latter includes also parts that are identified as applications of logic rather than logic proper. The term “philosophical logic” as currently used, for instance, in the Journal of Philosophical Logic, is a near-synonym for “nonclassical logic”. There is an older use of the term as a near-synonym for “philosophy of language”.
    [Show full text]
  • Mythologies and Partisan Constructions of the Good Philosopher in Plato
    Article Hic Sunt Leones: Mythologies and Partisan Constructions of the Good Philosopher in Plato Sergio Alloggio https://orcid.org/0000-0002-7273-3954 University of Pretoria [email protected] Abstract Plato constructs the philosopher in contrast to the sophist. Both sophistical and rhetorical logos, in their epistemic closeness to philosophical logos, require a constant act of demarcation throughout Plato’s works. The challenge posed by the sophists creates a structural, instable tension in several Platonic dialogues. Why is the Athenian philosopher obsessed by a different yet comparable approach to virtue, knowledge and social order? Why does the Athenian philosopher need and, at the same time, reject the sophist when it comes to shaping his own self-image? To try to answer these questions, I will go back to a foundational moment where the Platonic philosopher is theoretically constructed and conceptually produced against the sophist, namely, Plato’s Sophist, Statesman, Protagoras, Gorgias and Phaedrus. The aim of the article is to show how the Platonic philosopher is conveniently defined through a series of partisan demarcations grounded on ontological privilege, epistemic exclusion, ethical circularity and, ultimately, political delegitimation. Keywords: Plato; dialectic; demarcation; partisanship; sophistics; agonistics; delegitimation Decolonization was the preoccupation of two [T]he unconscious has first and foremost to do with groups that propelled the nationalist movement: the grammar … This also has a bit to do, or much to intelligentsia and the political class. They set out to do, or everything to do, with repetition, that is, create the nation, the former to give the with the aspect that is entirely the opposite of what independent state a history and the latter to create a a dictionary is used for … Grammar and repetition common citizenship as the basis of national constitute a completely different aspect from what sovereignty.
    [Show full text]
  • Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2021 M
    Z Zabarella, Jacopo chair of logic, succeeding Tomitano. On 4 January 1569 he secured the second extraordinary chair of Born: 5 September 1533, Padua natural philosophy. There was likely a pause in his Died: 15 October 1589, Padua teaching from 1574 to 1576 on account of the severity of plague in Padua. On 26 March 1577 Marco Sgarbi he acquired the first extraordinary chair of natural Ca’ Foscari University of Venice, Venice, Italy philosophy, and in 1578, he published his Opera logica in Venice, thus opening a large debate on the Abstract order and method of knowledge among his con- temporaries – especially with Francesco Jacopo Zabarella (1553–1589) is considered Piccolomini (1520–1604) and Bernardino Petrella one of the most acute and brilliant logicians (1529–1595). In 1580 Zabarella published his of all time. He made an important contribution Tabulae logicae and also founded the Accademia to the interpretation of Aristotle and developed degli Stabili. In 1584, he came under attack in two original ideas especially in the field of logic directions: from Piccolomini in his Universa and epistemology, opening up the pathway of philosophia de moribus, and from Petrella in his early modern science. Logicarum disputationum libri VII. The same year, Zabarella’s reply to Piccolomini was his De doctrina ordine apologia. In the meantime, on Biography 6 September 1585, he became professor of the second ordinary chair of natural philosophy, and He was born in Padua on 5 September 1533, the the following year he published his De naturalis eldest son of Giulio Zabarella. He was well-versed scientiae constitutione.
    [Show full text]
  • Concrete Possible Worlds (Final)
    CONCRETE POSSIBLE WORLDS Phillip Bricker 1. INTRODUCTION. Open a book or article of contemporary analytic philosophy, and you are likely to find talk of possible worlds therein. This applies not only to analytic metaphysics, but to areas as diverse as philosophy of language, philosophy of science, epistemology, and ethics. Philosophers agree, for the most part, that possible worlds talk is extremely useful for explicating concepts and formulating theories. They disagree, however, over its proper interpretation. In this chapter, I discuss the view, championed by David Lewis, that philosophers’ talk of possible worlds is the literal truth.1 There exists a plurality of worlds. One of these is our world, the actual world, the physical universe that contains us and all our surroundings. The others are merely possible worlds containing merely possible beings, such as flying pigs and talking donkeys. But the other worlds are no less real or concrete for being merely possible. Fantastic? Yes! What could motivate a philosopher to believe such a tale? I start, as is customary, with modality.2 Truths about the world divide into two sorts: categorical and modal. Categorical truths describe how things are, what is actually the case. Modal truths describe how things could or must be, what is possibly or 1 The fullest statement of Lewis’s theory of possible worlds is contained in his magnum opus, Lewis (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds. Lewis’s view is sometimes called “modal realism.” 2 Historically, it was the attempt to provide semantics for modal logic that catapulted possible worlds to the forefront of analytic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • David Lewis's Place in Analytic Philosophy Scott Soames by The
    David Lewis’s Place in Analytic Philosophy Scott Soames By the early 1970s, and continuing through 2001, David Lewis and Saul Kripke had taken over W.V.O. Quine’s leadership in metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of language, and philosophical logic in the English-speaking world. Quine, in turn, had inherited his position in the early 1950s from Rudolf Carnap, who had been the leading logical positivist -- first in Europe, and, after 1935, in America. A renegade positivist himself, Quine eschewed apriority, necessity, and analyticity, while (for a time) adopting a holistic version of verificationism. Like Carnap, he placed philosophical logic and the philosophy of science at the center of philosophy. While not entirely avoiding metaphysics and epistemology, he tried to “naturalize” both. By contrast, Lewis and Kripke embraced the modalities Quine rejected.1 They also had no sympathy for his early verificationism, or his twin flights from intension and intention. As for philosophy of science, it was transforming itself into specialized philosophies of the several sciences, and did not lend itself to unified treatment. Although Lewis had deep interests in scientific issues, and was commendably realist about science in general, science itself was not the center of own distinctive approach to philosophy. Despite similarities in their opposition to Quine, the differences between Lewis and Kripke were large – especially in the semantics and metaphysics of modality. They also had different philosophical styles. Whereas Lewis was a wide-ranging thinker who pieced together a systematic philosophical world view, Kripke gave little thought to system, focusing instead on a few central topics. There is, therefore, no conflict between the two on many of the issues on which Kripke was silent.
    [Show full text]