Slippers in Heaven

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Slippers in Heaven Lesley Smith SlippersinHeaven William of Auvergne Preaching to the Brethren Abstract: When he somewhat unexpectedlyfound himself installedasBishop of Paris in 1228,the philosopher-theologian William of Auvergne had to adjust his wayoflife. Auniversity master who had never taken priest’sorders,William found himself having to organize and take the leading role in the pastoral ministry of his diocese. Areformer,William welcomed the arrival of the Mendicant Ordersin Paris, and theirpartinits spiritual life. Indeed, when the University went on strike in 1229,not onlydid William not side with his formercolleagues, he supported the Men- dicants to the extent of giving them their first universitychair.Inaddition, he took his own individual responsibility as bishop seriously,becoming known as asingular preacher.This paper will look at William’ssermons to the Paris Mendicants, and his ideas of what the Mendicant life should be. This essaydoes not directlyconcern Alexander or the Summa. Instead, it focuses on one of Alexander’salmostexactcontemporaries in Paris, William of Auvergne. Wil- liam wasboth asecular teachingmasterinthe cathedral school at Notre Dame and bishop of the city from 1228.His career,and especiallythe 21 years of his episcopate, encompassed the comingofthe mendicant Orders to Paris and their establishment in its university—the foremost centrefor theological research in Europe. William’srela- tionships with the mendicants and the universitydemonstrate his importance for their acceptance into the Paris schools system; and his extant sermons—some of which werepreached to the Paris friars—illustrate the affinity he shared with the brethren, both in preachingstyle and in pastoral and theological emphasis. William was akey playerinthe story of the mendicants in the city;indeed, without William, the Franciscan and Dominican trajectory in the universitywould have been very dif- ferent. William was BishopofParis from 1228 until his death in 1249. Before 1228,dates are somewhat hard to come by,but we know that by 1223 he was ateachingmaster and acanon of Notre Dame.¹ From his name, and some asidesinhis writings, we The standardbiography of William remains Noël Valois, Guillaume d’Auvergne, évêque de Paris (1228–1249): Sa vie et ses ouvrages (Paris:Picard, 1880). Autour de Guillaume d’Auvergne (†1249), ed. Franco Morenzoni and Jean-Yves Tilliette (Turnhout: Brepols,2005), has agood bibliography and recent research.Roland Teske’smanytranslations,with notes, of William’sphilosophical works arealwaysuseful; for abrief overview of William’slife and works see his ‘William of Au- vergne,’ in ACompanion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages,ed. Jorge J.A. Garcia and TimothyB. Noone (Malden,MA: Blackwell, 2002), 680 –7. OpenAccess. ©2020 Lydia Schumacher,published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110685022-019 286 Lesley Smith believethat he was born and grew up in the Auvergne. He is said to have been born around 1180,but the date is reallyonlyreachedbycountingback abiblical 70 years from the date of his death. So like manyimportant medieval people, we know virtu- allynothing of more than half his life, and especiallyabout the formative period of his upbringing.² He became bishop unexpectedly.Onthe death of the previous incumbent,Bar- tholomew,in1227, the canons of Notre Dame (of whom William was one) elected Nicholas the Chanterashis successor.But the electionwas not unanimous, and Wil- liam wasunhappy with the process, which he said had violated the rules laid down in the decrees of LateranIV. Nicholas stood aside,claiming that he had never wished to be bishop,and asecond electionwas held. This gave the posttothe Dean of the Cathedral, Philip. Again, William argued that the process had been uncanonical. At this point,Gregory IX intervened and instituted alocal enquiry,which upheld Wil- liam’sobjections. William was so exercised by the matter that he travelled to Rome to speak to the pope; and here, using Canon 24 of Lateran IV as his authority, Gregory decided to take the election into his own hands, and made William himself bishop. ‘Aman of eminent learning,without astain on his character’,was his judge- ment—one that Gregory was soon to regret and retract,when William did not act as he ordered.³ WasWilliam made bishop by mistake, as it were, or had he gone to Rome with this precise intention?Perhaps he himself did not know.Certainly, he was still onlya deacon whenhewas appointed by Gregory,who had to ordain William priest before he could consecrate him bishop.⁴ In order to teachtheologyinParis, it was necessary to be aclerk in holyorders;being adeacon was sufficient,and William seems to have shown no sign of wantingtogofurther.But of course, beingapriest and being abishop—being in charge—are two very different things. We might even spec- ulate that it was onlywhen he sawthe other possibilities on offer—when he sawthe other possible candidates—that he decided he would have to try to do it himself.⁵ The moreIhave worked on William, the moreIhavecometothink that he was older than the stan- dardbiographies suggest,and Iaminclined to put his birth datecloser to 1170 than 1180;but so far this remains an unsubstantiatedopinion. Valois, Guillaumed’Auvergne,8–16.Gregory’slettertothe chapter at Paris (10 April 1228) reads: ‘Ceterum ne dicta ecclesia pro defectu pastoris dispendium pateretur, nos praenominatum magistrum Wilhelmum, virum eminentis scientiae, vitae ac conversationishonestae,acopinionis praeclarae, zelum Dei et animarum habentem,exofficio nostro, de consilio fratrum nostrorum, in antistitem vobis providimus et ecclesiae supra dictae, quem tandem in presbyterem ordinatum et in episcopum consecratum anobis cum plenitudine gratiae nostrae duximus remittendum,’ in M.B. Hauréau, ‘Quel- ques Lettres de Grégoire IX,’ in Notices et extraits des manuscrits de la bibliothèqueimpériale,vol. 21/2 (Paris:Imprimerie Impériale,1865), 208. See previous note. Foracomparison of the election after William, see Pascal Montaubin, ‘Leschanoines de Notre- Dame de Paris àlamort de l’évêque Guillaume d’Auvergne (1249),’ in Notre-Dame de Paris 1163– SlippersinHeaven 287 What is clear is that William took to being bishop likeaduck to water.Rather like Hildebrand becomingGregory VII, Ithink he had an agenda before he started; and his consecration as bishop gave him the chance to carry it out.After all, by this time he was probablyatleast 48 years old, observing the workings of the Church for decades.Although he does not appear to have had personal ambition—if the op- portunity at Paris had not arisen, Idonot think he would have pursued ecclesiastical preferment elsewhere—he did have strongand serious ideas about what the Church should be; and suddenly, he had the means to bring them about.William was acon- fident man—confident enough,infact,that he can talk about doubt; confident enough to go his ownway.But though full of original and striking ideas, his faith in God wasinits waysimple and very deep. Let us move, then, to the mendicants. Dominic sent the first group of seven friars to Paris in 1217.⁶ Their task—to study, to preach, and to found apriory.Dominic him- self wasinParis for the first General Chapter of the Order in 1220.Asalreadynoted, William was amaster of theologyand canon of Notre Dame by 1223,and so must surelyhavebeen studying in Paris at this time. In all the discussions of Dominic as an organizational genius, it is often forgotten that he was alsoaperson of great charisma,and Ithink it very likelythat William heardhim speak. From Notre Dame, William would have watched as the Dominicans, followed by the Franciscans, worked to establish their houses of study in the city.For both orders, the decade from 1220 to 1230 must have been filled both with enormous exhilaration and enormous trepidation, as they fought for aplace within the Church. In addition, each had to weather the death of amagnetic founder,whose loss might easilyhavespelled the end of the experiment—certainlyfor the Franciscans,and perhaps even for the Dom- inicans, whose numbers had intentionallygrown more slowly, with potential broth- ers often picked out by Dominic himself. It wascrucial to the success of both that they be accepted within individual dioceses—Francis makesitplain, for instance, that his brothers should not attempt to preach except with the agreement of the local authorities. Since bothOrderswerequick to establish themselvesinParis, the attitude of the city’sbishop was amake or break issue. Paris was the city of seri- ous theologyand biblical studies, but it was also the city of serious students and teachers;bothOrderswereaskeen to poach as they weretolearn. It was not obvious thatthe mendicants would be welcomed either into the dio- cese or the university;bothhad much to lose. Aletter of August 1231 from Gregory to William details the bad treatment the friars werereceiving in France.⁷ The brethren 2013: Actes du colloque scientifique tenu au Collège des Bernardins,àParis, du 12 au 15 décembre2012, ed. Cédric Giraud (Turnhout: Brepols,2013), 195–216. William A. Hinnebusch, TheHistoryofthe Dominican Order,2vols (New York: Alba House, 1966–73); M. Michèle Mulchahey, ‘Firstthe Bow is BentinStudy…’:Dominican education before 1350 (Toronto:Pontifical InstituteofMediaeval Studies,1998). Valois, Guillaume d’Auvergne,102– 3and nn. Gregory’stext can be accessedthrough the Brepols Ut per litteras apostolicas (LITPA) database. 288 Lesley Smith werenot permitted to have the sacrament in their chapels; they could not celebrate mass every day; they could not have achurch or bell tower; they could not have a sanctified cemetery within the convent walls; they had to attend parish processions, saytheir first mass thereinthe parish church, and be buried there. Their candles, lamps and ornaments wereall taxed by the secular clergy, who demanded tithes of their kitchen garden produce and levied duty on the construction of their con- vents. The bishop obliged the brothers to come to synod, and made their ministers and guardians take an oath of fidelity,when he had not appointed them himself. Those who refused weredrivenout.
Recommended publications
  • Theories of Truth. Bibliography on Primary Medieval Authors
    Theories of Truth. Bibliography on Primary Medieval Authors https://www.ontology.co/biblio/truth-medieval-authors.htm Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] History of Truth. Selected Bibliography on Medieval Primary Authors The Authors to which I will devote an entire page are marked with an asterisk (*). Hilary of Poitiers Augustine of Hippo (*) Boethius (*) Isidore of Seville John Scottus Eriugena (*) Isaac Israeli Avicenna (*) Anselm of Canterbury (*) Peter Abelard (*) Philip the Chancellor Robert Grosseteste William of Auvergne Albert the Great Bonaventure Thomas Aquinas (*) Henry of Ghent Siger of Brabant John Duns Scotus (*) Hervaeus Natalis Giles of Rome Durandus of St. Pourçain Peter Auriol Walter Burley William of Ockham (*) Robert Holkot John Buridan (*) 1 di 14 22/09/2016 09:25 Theories of Truth. Bibliography on Primary Medieval Authors https://www.ontology.co/biblio/truth-medieval-authors.htm Gregory of Rimini William of Heytesbury Peter of Mantua Paul of Venice Hilary of Poitiers (ca. 300 - 368) Texts 1. Meijering, E.P. 1982. Hilary of Poitiers on the Trinity. De Trinitate 1, 1-19, 2, 3. Leiden: Brill. In close cooperation with J. C. M: van Winden. On truth see I, 1-14. Studies Augustine of Hippo ( 354 - 430) Texts Studies 1. Boyer, Charles. 1921. L'idée De Vérité Dans La Philosophie De Saint Augustin. Paris: Gabriel Beauchesne. 2. Kuntz, Paul G. 1982. "St. Augustine's Quest for Truth: The Adequacy of a Christian Philosophy." Augustinian Studies no. 13:1-21. 3. Vilalobos, José. 1982. Ser Y Verdad En Agustín De Hipona. Sevilla: Publicaciones de la Universidad de Sevilla.
    [Show full text]
  • Page 210 H-France Review Vol. 8 (March 2008), No. 52 Roland J
    H-France Review Volume 8 (2008) Page 210 H-France Review Vol. 8 (March 2008), No. 52 Roland J. Teske, Studies in the Philosophy of William of Auvergne, Bishop of Paris (1228-1249). Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 2006. 274 pp. Table, introduction, notes, bibliography, and indexes. $30.00 U.S. (pb). ISBN 0-87462-674-9. Review by Steven P. Marrone, Tufts University. William of Auvergne, master of theology at the University of Paris and bishop of that city from 1228 until his death in 1249, was one of the most prominent Latin theologians of his day, recognized for his intellectual import throughout much of the rest of the thirteenth century. Yet the modern historiography of scholastic thought has paid him relatively little attention. The only book devoted to the entirety of his thinking, a three-volume study by Amato Masnovo, appeared well over half a century ago.[1] With the new work under review here, gathering together thirteen essays on aspects of William’s philosophy originally published between 1990 and 2003, Roland Teske goes a long way towards redressing the balance. In the name of full disclosure, I should admit that as an author of two books in which William’s speculative achievements play a major role, I cannot be considered an impartial witness to Teske’s effort.[2] All the same, I believe that anyone who reads Teske’s book will come away convinced that William deserves just the sort of probing and sustained examination Teske has given him. For the sake of our accurate appreciation of the historical trajectory of thirteenth-century scholasticism, I hope the book has many readers.
    [Show full text]
  • Why God Became Man; on Grace; on Faith
    00-front 09/02/2011 4:23 PM Page i Introduction | i william of auvergne Selected Spiritual Writings: Why God Became Man; On Grace; On Faith This volume contains translations of three of William of Auvergne’s shorter more spiritual works: Cur Deus homo (Why God Became Man), De gratia (On Grace), and De fide (On Faith). Each work touches upon the understanding of the relation between nature and grace, the moral and theological virtues, and of the need for our redemption by Christ and its character. The introduction situates the treatises within William’s many works and within the thought of the early thirteenth century. In the first treatise William sets forth the reasons for the incarnation of the Word. In it he is deeply influenced by Anselm of Canterbury’s emphasis on the need for satisfaction to be made to God for human sin, a satisfaction that could only adequately be made by someone both divine and human. While Anselm claimed to provide necessary reason of the incarnation, William admits that God could have redeemed the world in another way. In the second William argues for the need of grace in order for human beings to return to God and aims to refute the position of the Pelagian heretics as he understood it. In the third treatise, William defines faith and establishes belief in God as the foundation of faith – something, he argues, that cannot be grasped by the human intellect alone. roland j. teske, sj, has an MA in classical languages and ecclesiastical degrees in philosophy and theology from Saint Louis University, as well as a PhD in philosophy from the University of Toronto.
    [Show full text]
  • What the Middle Ages Knew IV
    Late Medieval Philosophy Piero Scaruffi Copyright 2018 http://www.scaruffi.com/know 1 What the Middle Ages knew • Before the Scholastics – The Bible is infallible, therefore there is no need for scientific investigation or for the laws of logic – Conflict between science and religion due to the Christian dogma that the Bible is the truth – 1.Dangerous to claim otherwise – 2.Pointless to search for additional truths – Tertullian (3rd c AD): curiosity no longer necessary because we know the meaning of the world and what is going to happen next ("Liber de Praescriptione Haereticorum") 2 What the Middle Ages knew • Before the Scholastics – Decline of scientific knowledge • Lactantius (4th c AD) ridicules the notion that the Earth could be a sphere ("Divinae Institutiones III De Falsa Sapientia Philosophorum") • Cosmas Indicopleustes' "Topographia Cristiana" (6th c AD): the Earth is a disc 3 What the Middle Ages knew • Before the Scholastics – Plato's creation by the demiurge in the Timaeus very similar to the biblical "Genesis" – Christian thinkers are raised by neoplatonists • Origen was a pupil of Ammonius Sacca (Plotinus' teacher) • Augustine studied Plotinus 4 What the Middle Ages knew • Preservation of classical knowledge – Boethius (6th c AD) translates part of Aristotle's "Organon" and his "Arithmetica" preserves knowledge of Greek mathematics – Cassiodorus (6th c AD) popularizes scientific studies among monks and formalizes education ("De Institutione Divinarum" and "De artibus ac disciplinis liberalium litterarum") with the division of disciplines into arts (grammar, rhetoric, dialectic) – and disiplines (arithmeitc,geometry, music, astronomy) – Isidore of Sevilla (7th c AD) preserves Graeco- Roman knowledge in "De Natura Rerum" and "Origines" 5 What the Middle Ages knew • Preservation of classical knowledge – Bede (8th c AD) compiles an encyclopedia, "De Natura Rerum" – St Peter's at Canterbury under Benedict Biscop (7th c AD) becomes a center of learning – Episcopal school of York: arithmetic, geometry, natural history, astronomy.
    [Show full text]
  • Theories of Cognition in the Later Middle Ages
    Theories of cognition in the later Middle Ages ROBERT PASNAU St. Joseph's University q;.::.~ CAMBRIDGE - ::: UNIVERSITY PRESS PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge CB2 1RP, United Kingdom CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, United Kingdom 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA 10 Samford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia © Robert Pasnau 1997 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1997 Typeset in Palatino Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Pasnau, Robert. Theories of cognition in the later Middle Ages / Robert Pasnau. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-521-58368-3 1. Knowledge, Theory of - History. 2. Cognition - History. 3. Philosophy, Medieval. 4. Thomas, Aquinas, Saint, 1225?-1274. 5. Olivi, Pierre Jean, 1248 or 9-1298. 6. William, of Ockham, ca. 1285-ca. 1349. 1. Title. B161.P37 1997 128'.2'0902 - dC20 96-36249 C1P A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library Transferred to digital printing 2003 Contents Preface page vii List of abbreviations x Introduction 1 1 The philosophical-historical context 4 2 Thomas Aquinas and the theory of species 11 3 Challenges to the theory 18 PART r: FUNDAMENTALS 1 Immateriality and intentionality 31 1 Cognition
    [Show full text]
  • Idolaters, Philosophers and an Elusive
    John Marenbon Idolaters, Philosophersand an ElusiveJew The Problem of Paganism in the Summa Halensis Abstract: This chapter examines the Summa’streatment of the philosophers, by which it means, in the main, the ancient pagan philosophers, although some later Jewishand Islamic figures are alsoincluded. It shows how the authorsbalanced the obvious virtue and wisdom of the philosophers against their moralshortcomings, inevitable since they lacked God’sgrace, and the severe limitation to theirunder- standing entailedbytheirlimited understanding of the Trinityand theirlack of ex- plicit knowledge of the Incarnation. With regard to salvation, the authors seem not to have had ageneral theory about the fate of the philosophers, but they suggest that some might have been savedbyspecial inspiration. The chapter also considers a more anthropological approach to the pagans in the Old Testament found in Summa Book 2, and it argues that thereisnoevidence of direct knowledge of Mai- monides’s Guide of the Perplexed in the Summa Halensis. The large group of people often described as ‘pagans’—all thosewho werenot Chris- tians, Jews or Muslims—posed aproblem for Christian thinkers in the Middle Ages. These pagans included the philosophers, poets and heroes from antiquity whose wis- dom and virtuesmanymedievalwriters so admired. How could pagans, giventheir ignorance of Christian truth, be the sources of scientific knowledge that the ancient philosophers were taken to be? Could pagans be trulyvirtuous, and, if not,why did so manyfamous figures of antiquity
    [Show full text]
  • William of Auvergne and Popular Demonology
    Quidditas Volume 28 Article 6 2007 William of Auvergne and Popular Demonology Thomas de Mayo J. Sargeant Reynolds Community College Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/rmmra Part of the Comparative Literature Commons, History Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Renaissance Studies Commons Recommended Citation de Mayo, Thomas (2007) "William of Auvergne and Popular Demonology," Quidditas: Vol. 28 , Article 6. Available at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/rmmra/vol28/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at BYU ScholarsArchive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Quidditas by an authorized editor of BYU ScholarsArchive. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Quidditas 28 (2007) 61 William of Auvergne and Popular Demonology Thomas de Mayo J. Sargeant Reynolds Community College Theologian and bishop of Paris during St. Louis’ early reign, William of Auvergne (d. 1249) aimed in his life and writings to combat the myriad threats he perceived as facing Christianity. The early thirteenth century saw many potential competitors to official doctrines concerning the natural and supernatural worlds—Arabic philosophy imported into the universities, heretical attacks on the institutional church, and persistent folk beliefs and practices. William attributed these challenges to an underlying demonic conspiracy directed against humankind. This paper examines William’s treatment of popular beliefs on the Wild Hunt, a mysterious congregation of spirits, and related beliefs about female spirits and night terrors. William applies to these legends his learned conceptions about the natural and supernatural worlds. He argues that although God might cause or encourage the morally salutary visions of the male riders of the Wild Hunt, visions of female spirits such as Lady Abundia represent a demonic ploy to secure the idolatrous worship of human women.
    [Show full text]
  • The Economic Thought of Abu Hamid Al-Ghazali and St. Thomas Aquinas: Some Comparative Parallels and Links S
    The Economic Thought of Abu Hamid Al-Ghazali and St. Thomas Aquinas: Some Comparative Parallels and Links S. M. Ghazanfar My primary purpose in this article is to identify and present some par- allelsand similaritiesbetweenthe major economic ideasof two me- dieval Scholastics: Abu Hamid Al-Ghazali (1058–1111), “acclaimed asthe greates t...certainly one of the greatest” (Watt 1963, vii) and “by general consent, the most important thinker of medieval Islam” (Bagley 1964, xv); and St. ThomasAquinas(1225–1274), the most prominent of the European-Latin Schoolmen, “the Doctor Angelicus, the PrincepsScholasticorum”(Pribram 1983, 4), “perhapsthe greatest Catholic philosopher of all time” (Newman, Gayer, and Spencer 1954, 16). Heretofore, some scholars of medieval history have explored sim- ilaritiesand linksbetween Al-Ghazali and St. Thomaswith reference to other dimensions of their discourses, but none has focused on their economic views. While this essay mainly discusses similarities in the economic ideas of the two Scholastics, more serious analysis might fur- ther corroborate the observationsof historiansastolinksbetween the two in other areasof knowledge. Further, it might be noted that while Thomistic economic thought is well recognized in the literature, very Correspondence may be addressed to S. M. Ghazanfar, Department of Economics, University of Idaho, Moscow, ID 83844-3240. This is a revised version of a paper presented at the 1993 History of Economics Society International Conference. I gratefully acknowledge comments offered by Professor Todd Lowry, the paper’s discussant, as well as by faculty colleagues. Also acknowledged are suggestions offered by two anonymous referees; this essay has signifi- cantly benefited from those suggestions. The author also deeply appreciates Paul Dudenhefer’s editorial assistance.
    [Show full text]
  • Maimonides and Aquinas on Divine Attributes the Importance of Avicenna
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 8-2019 Maimonides and Aquinas on Divine Attributes the Importance of Avicenna Richard C. Taylor Follow this and additional works at: https://epublications.marquette.edu/phil_fac Part of the Philosophy Commons 12 Maimonides and Aquinas on Divine Attributes The Importance of Avicenna richard c. taylor It is well known that Shlomo Pines’s translation of Maimonides’ Guide of the Perplexed and Pines’s learned, stimulating introduction to the text have long influenced not only students of the rabbi’s work but also scholars of the Jew- ish, Christian, and Islamic Abrahamic traditions of medieval philosophical and religious thought. In scholarship on the Latin tradition, the use of the Guide by thinkers such as Alexander of Hales, William of Auvergne, Ro- land of Cremona, Giles of Rome, Albertus Magnus, Meister Eckhart, and other Christian Aristotelians of the thirteenth century has been duly noted. Nonetheless, major studies have focused mainly on the importance of Mai- monides for the teachings of Thomas Aquinas, the best- known Latin theo- logian and philosophical thinker of that period.1 With few exceptions,2 the research has also centered on the direct relation between Maimonides and Aquinas without consideration of their wider context, even though recent studies of Aquinas have repeatedly shown the invaluable importance of key 1. Some examples are the following: Dienstag 1975; Haberman 1979; Kluxen 1986; Copyright © 2019. University of Chicago Press. All rights reserved. of Chicago Press. © 2019. University Copyright Dobbs- Weinstein 1995; Hasselhoff 2001, 2002, 2004; Rubio 2006. 2.
    [Show full text]
  • CAUSAL SKEPTICISM and the DESTRUCTION of ANTIQUITY By
    CAUSAL SKEPTICISM AND THE DESTRUCTION OF ANTIQUITY by JASON M. JORDAN A DISSERTATION Presented to the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate School of the University of Oregon in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2011 DISSERTATION APPROVAL PAGE Student: Jason M. Jordan Title: Causal Skepticism and the Destruction of Antiquity This dissertation has been accepted and approved in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Doctor of Philosophy degree in the Department of Philosophy by: Dr. Naomi Zack Chairperson Dr. Cheney Ryan Member Dr. Colin Koopman Member Dr. Malcolm Wilson Outside Member and Kimberly Andrews Espy Vice President for Research & Innovation/Dean of the Graduate School Original approval signatures are on file with the University of Oregon Graduate School. Degree awarded December 2011 ii © 2011 Jason M. Jordan iii DISSERTATION ABSTRACT Jason M. Jordan Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy December 2011 Title: Causal Skepticism and the Destruction of Antiquity This dissertation examines the development of skeptical views concerning causation from the medieval to the early modern period. While causal skepticism is often overlooked by intellectual historians, I argue that, in spite of its typical motivation as a religious response to shibboleths of ancient philosophy that stood askance from the dogmas of Abrahamic theology, causal skepticism was the greatest intellectual development of post-antiquity and ultimately culminated into modern Science. The first chapter examines Hume's famous analysis of causation and serves as a foil for the prior history of causal skepticism addressed in the subsequent chapters. The second chapter addresses the dispute over causation in medieval Islamic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fate of the Flying Man Medieval Reception of Avicenna’S Thought Experiment
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi The Fate of the Flying Man Medieval Reception of Avicenna’s Thought Experiment Juhana Toivanen 1. INTRODUCTION Thought experiments are nowadays an important part of philosophical discourse. They are used to illuminate theoretical arguments and to reveal philosophically significant features of an argument or a problem in a way that aspires to precision. Although the phrase ‘thought experiment’ itself is quite recent, the use of imagined counterfactual cases which are designed to have a role in philosophical argument can be traced back to Antiquity, and the technique was widely employed in the Middle Ages.1 One of the most well-known medieval thought experiments is the so-called ‘flying man’ of Avicenna. The flying man is an imaginary person whose senses do not provide any input but who nevertheless admits his own existence, or the existence of his soul. Avicenna’s idea was that this thought experiment helps us to understand that the soul is not identical to the body but an immaterial entity. Modern scholarship has discussed the Latin reception of this thought experiment to some extent,2 but there are a couple of issues that have not 1 For the role of thought experiments in the history of Western philosophy, see Katerina Ierodiakonou and Sophie Roux (eds), Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts, History of Science and Medicine Library 19 (Leiden: Brill, 2011), 1–142. 2 Dag Nikolaus Hasse, Avicenna’s De anima in the Latin West: The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the Soul, 1160–1300 (London: The Warburg Institute, 2000), 80–92 and 236; Deborah J.
    [Show full text]
  • Providence and Causality in the Summa Halensis
    CoreyL.Barnes Providenceand Causality in the Summa Halensis Abstract: William of Auvergne’streatment of providenceinhis De universo (1230s) selectively employed Avicenna, Aristotle, and the category of efficient causality to mark adistinctionbetween divine foreknowledge and providence.William’sfocus on efficiency and affirmation that natural agents work in the mode of servants fol- lows Neoplatonicimpulses to instrumentalize nature and thereby risks eviscerating anymeaningful secondary causality.Considerations of providence at Paris in the 1230s and 1240s engagewith or react to William, with the Summa Halensis providing an interesting example. The Summa Halensis counters this risk by framing provi- dence within the largerscope of divine knowledge and will, using reinterpreted ver- sions of Aristotelianformal and final causality.The Summists avoid the danger of re- ducingprovidence to predictive knowledge or to atemporal awareness of temporal events by stressing the causality of the divine intellect and will. Further,the Sum- mists counter the danger of magnifyingthe causal efficacy of providenceuntil God remains the sole agent of every effect by framing the causality of the divine intellect and will in terms of formal and final causality.Bythis approach, the Summa Halensis harmonizes providential causality with the integrity of secondary causality. The Summa Halensis begins its consideration of providence with aclear recognition that the observable world is full of confusion and disorder and with aclear affirma- tion that everythingnot
    [Show full text]