Individuals and Institutions in Medieval Scholasticism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Individuals and Institutions in Medieval Scholasticism Individuals and Institutions in Medieval Scholasticism EDITED BY ANTONIA FITZPATRICK AND JOHN SABAPATHY Individuals and Institutions in Medieval Scholasticism New Historical Perspectives is a book series for early career scholars within the UK and the Republic of Ireland. Books in the series are overseen by an expert editorial board to ensure the highest standards of peer-reviewed scholarship. Commissioning and editing is undertaken by the Royal Historical Society, and the series is published under the imprint of the Institute of Historical Research by the University of London Press. The series is supported by the Economic History Society and the Past and Present Society. Series co-editors: Heather Shore (Manchester Metropolitan University) and Jane Winters (School of Advanced Study, University of London) Founding co-editors: Simon Newman (University of Glasgow) and Penny Summerfield (University of Manchester) New Historical Perspectives Editorial Board Charlotte Alston, Northumbria University David Andress, University of Portsmouth Philip Carter, Institute of Historical Research, University of London Ian Forrest, University of Oxford Leigh Gardner, London School of Economics Tim Harper, University of Cambridge Guy Rowlands, University of St Andrews Alec Ryrie, Durham University Richard Toye, University of Exeter Natalie Zacek, University of Manchester Individuals and Institutions in Medieval Scholasticism Edited by Antonia Fitzpatrick and John Sabapathy LONDON ROYAL HISTORICAL SOCIETY INSTITUTE OF HISTORICAL RESEARCH UNIVERSITY OF LONDON PRESS Published in 2020 by UNIVERSITY OF LONDON PRESS SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY INSTITUTE OF HISTORICAL RESEARCH Senate House, Malet Street, London WC1E 7HU © Chapter authors, 2020 The authors have asserted their rights under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 to be identified as the authors of this work. This book is published under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0) license. More information regarding CC licenses is available at https://creativecommons.org/licenses/. Available to download free or to purchase the hard copy edition at https://www.sas.ac.uk/publications/. ISBNs 978-1-912702-26-8 (hardback edition) 978-1-912702-27-5 (paperback edition) 978-1-912702-30-5 (PDF edition) 978-1-912702-28-2 (ePub edition) 978-1-912702-29-9 (.mobi edition) DOI 10.14296/520.9781912702305 Cover image: detail of Andrea da Firenze (Andrea Bonaiuti)’s 1366–8 Allegory of the triumph of the Church for the Dominican Order’s Chapterhouse in S. Maria Novella, Florence. Contents Acknowledgements vii List of abbreviations ix Notes on contributors xi Introduction: individuals and institutions in medieval scholasticism 1 Antonia Fitzpatrick and John Sabapathy I. Individuals and intellectual traditions: construction and criticism 51 1. The fathers of scholasticism: authorities as totems 53 Blaise Dufal 2. The unicity of substantial form in the Correctoria corruptorii fratris Thomae of Richard Knapwell, Robert Orford and John of Paris 71 Antonia Fitzpatrick 3. Italian universities, arts masters and interpreting Pomponazzi’s De immortalitate animae 89 John Marenbon 4. Individual and institution in scholastic historiography: Nicholas Trevet 107 Matthew Kempshall II. Institutions and individuals: organizations and social practices 137 a. Individuals and organizations 137 5. The charismatic leader and the vita religiosa: some observations about an apparent contradiction between individual and institution 139 Gert Melville v Individuals and Institutions in Medieval Scholasticism 6. An institution made of individuals: Peter John Olivi and Angelo Clareno on the Franciscan experience 157 Sylvain Piron 7. Rolando of Cremona and the earliest inquisition depositions of Languedoc 177 Peter Biller b. Individuals and practices 197 8. Robert of Courson’s systematic thinking about early thirteenth-century institutions 199 John Sabapathy 9. ‘Better to let scandal arise than to relinquish the truth’: the cases of conscience of the masters of Paris in the thirteenth century 217 Emily Corran 10. Of parish priests and hermaphrodites: Robert Holcot’s discussion of Omnis utriusque sexus 235 Cornelia Linde 11. The cult of the marriage of Joseph and Mary: the shaping of doctrinal novelty in Jean Gerson’s Josephina (1414–17) 253 Isabel Iribarren Afterword 269 David d’Avray Index 277 vi Acknowledgements Predictably enough there are a number of individuals and institutions we would like to thank. First, all our contributors for their patience with a project which has had a long gestation and for their commitment to it. Second, those contributors to the initial sunny conference in June 2015 at St John’s College Oxford whom it was not possible to include in the volume: Charles Burnett, Magnus Ryan and Juhana Toivanen. Those who chaired and commented on our discussions were also enormously helpful: Mary Carruthers, Jean Dunbabin, Kantik Ghosh, Stephen Mossman, Sandy Murray, Lucy Sackville, Cecilia Trifogli and Ian Wei. Third – if we may – each other. This has been an enormously enjoyable and collaborative project from the start. Antonia Fitzpatrick remembers John Sabapathy proposing the idea but the undertaking has been entirely collaborative from beginning to end. The project’s structure was generated together; its introduction written and revised collaboratively; and its articles proofed alongside one another. There are a number of institutions we would like to thank, not at all distinct from the individuals involved. First, St John’s College, Oxford and University College London, both of which have provided us with physical and intellectual homes for important periods and which have played instrumental roles in the genesis of this project. We hope that Sir Richard Southern would look favourably on this book. Certainly, his presidential portrait at St John’s seemed to. Neither of us knew Southern but he has had an important influence on our thinking. More materially, St John’s and UCL History Department provided the financial support for the ridiculously fun conference which brought everyone together in the first place. John Sabapathy would also like to thank the Leverhulme Trust for granting a research fellowship on thirteenth-century institutionalization during which this project was completed. This was very much appreciated. Second, the Warburg Institute, where we co-ran a scholasticism reading group for several years, including with some contributors to this volume. The Warburg is one of the best places in the world to work on scholasticism and the book was proofed in its spiritual home on the third floor. Third, the Royal Historical Society and the Institute of Historical Research whose New Historical Perspectives series welcomed our proposal for this book and have supported its production so helpfully. vii Individuals and Institutions in Medieval Scholasticism Finally, this book only apparently lacks a dedication since its efficient cause is an individual who so entirely pervades it that acknowledgment would be as gratuitous as it would be unwanted. In all honesty and gratitude, ceci n’est pas une Festschrift. Antonia Fitzpatrick and John Sabapathy Eton and Bloomsbury, July 2019 viii List of abbreviations BNF Bibliothèque nationale de France Brit. Libr. British Library, London CCCM Corpus Christianorum Continuatio Mediaevalis CCSL Corpus Christianorum Series Latina CSEL Corpus Scriptorum Ecclesiasticorum Latinorum lat. Latin MGH Monumenta Germaniae Historica MGH SRG Monumenta Germaniae Historica. Scriptores rerum Germanicarum in usum scholarum MGH SS Monumenta Germaniae Historica. Scriptores (in Folio) ODNB Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (https:// www.oxforddnb.com) PL Patrologia Latina ix Notes on contributors Peter Biller is emeritus professor at the University of York. His earlier research was on medieval thought about population and ‘race’ in medieval science. Now he is a member of a group editing a large tranche of the earliest inquisition records from southern France – specifically, those that survive only in seventeenth-century copies. Emily Corran is lecturer in medieval history at University College London. Her research focuses on practical ethical thought and casuistry in the later middle ages, with a particular interest in manuals for confessors. Her monograph Lying and Perjury in Medieval Practical Thought: a Study in the History of Casuistry was published in 2018. David d’Avray is emeritus professor of history at University College London. He is a fellow of the British Academy and of the Medieval Academy of America. Blaise Dufal is associated researcher to the University of Sydney and the Ecole des hautes études en sciences sociales (Paris). He is a specialist in medieval scholasticism (late thirteenth century – early fourteenth century), with a focus on the classical and patristic traditions. His research interests include the historiography and epistemology of the humanities and social sciences. He co-edited L’historien et les fantômes. Lectures (autour) de l’œuvre d’Alain Boureau (Paris, 2017) and Une histoire au présent. Les historiens et Michel Foucault (Paris, 2013). Antonia Fitzpatrick is a Bedingfield scholar and Residential Scholar at the Honourable Society of Gray’s Inn. She is studying the bar professional training course at the City Law School and will begin pupillage at Monckton Chambers in October 2020. Before retraining as a barrister, she held a junior research fellowship and a departmental lectureship in medieval history at
Recommended publications
  • The Intellectual Fallout from World War I As the Context of the Roots Post- Modernism
    Olivet Nazarene University Digital Commons @ Olivet Faculty Scholarship – History History 10-24-2014 The nI tellectual Fallout from World War I William Dean Olivet Nazarene University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.olivet.edu/hist_facp Part of the Christianity Commons, Continental Philosophy Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, European History Commons, Intellectual History Commons, Political History Commons, and the Social History Commons Recommended Citation Dean, William, "The nI tellectual Fallout from World War I" (2014). Faculty Scholarship – History. 19. https://digitalcommons.olivet.edu/hist_facp/19 This Presentation is brought to you for free and open access by the History at Digital Commons @ Olivet. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship – History by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Olivet. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 The Intellectual Fallout from World War 1 William W. Dean, Ph.D. October 24, 2014 Introduction Let me begin with some general thoughts about the importance of ideas in human life. All ideas—good, bad, indifferent—are rooted in human experience. Every thought we think comes to us in specific circumstances. The sudden flash of memory that raises the question, “Did I lock the door?” deals with a specific door to a particular house at a particular address. Whatever our age, job, responsibility, or relationship, our ideas are linked to the contexts in which we live. I intend here to explore the intellectual fallout from World War I as the context of the roots post- modernism. One of the surprises I encountered as I began to prepare this talk was the discovery of a long list of titles that linked World War 2 to postmodernism, but none that linked World War 1 in the same way.
    [Show full text]
  • The Black Platonism of David Lindsay
    Volume 19 Number 2 Article 3 Spring 3-15-1993 Encounter Darkness: The Black Platonism of David Lindsay Adelheid Kegler Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.swosu.edu/mythlore Part of the Children's and Young Adult Literature Commons Recommended Citation Kegler, Adelheid (1993) "Encounter Darkness: The Black Platonism of David Lindsay," Mythlore: A Journal of J.R.R. Tolkien, C.S. Lewis, Charles Williams, and Mythopoeic Literature: Vol. 19 : No. 2 , Article 3. Available at: https://dc.swosu.edu/mythlore/vol19/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Mythopoeic Society at SWOSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Mythlore: A Journal of J.R.R. Tolkien, C.S. Lewis, Charles Williams, and Mythopoeic Literature by an authorized editor of SWOSU Digital Commons. An ADA compliant document is available upon request. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To join the Mythopoeic Society go to: http://www.mythsoc.org/join.htm Mythcon 51: A VIRTUAL “HALFLING” MYTHCON July 31 - August 1, 2021 (Saturday and Sunday) http://www.mythsoc.org/mythcon/mythcon-51.htm Mythcon 52: The Mythic, the Fantastic, and the Alien Albuquerque, New Mexico; July 29 - August 1, 2022 http://www.mythsoc.org/mythcon/mythcon-52.htm Abstract Characterizes Lindsay as a “belated symbolist” whose characters are “personifications of ontological values.” Uses Neoplatonic “references to transcendence” but his imagery and technique do not suggest a positive view of transcendence. Additional Keywords Lindsay, David—Neoplatonism; Lindsay, David—Philosophy; Lindsay, David. A Voyage to Arcturus; Neoplatonism in David Lindsay This article is available in Mythlore: A Journal of J.R.R.
    [Show full text]
  • Denying a Dualism: Goodman's Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 28, 2004, 226-238. Denying a Dualism: Goodman’s Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction Catherine Z. Elgin The analytic synthetic/distinction forms the backbone of much modern Western philosophy. It underwrites a conception of the relation of representations to reality which affords an understanding of cognition. Its repudiation thus requires a fundamental reconception and perhaps a radical revision of philosophy. Many philosophers believe that the repudiation of the analytic/synthetic distinction and kindred dualisms constitutes a major loss, possibly even an irrecoverable loss, for philosophy. Nelson Goodman thinks otherwise. He believes that it liberates philosophy from unwarranted restrictions, creating opportunities for the development of powerful new approaches to and reconceptions of seemingly intractable problems. In this article I want to sketch some of the consequences of Goodman’s reconception. My focus is not on Goodman’s reasons for denying the dualism, but on some of the ways its absence affects his position. I do not contend that the Goodman obsessed over the issue. I have no reason to think that the repudiation of the distinction was a central factor in his intellectual life. But by considering the function that the analytic/synthetic distinction has performed in traditional philosophy, and appreciating what is lost and gained in repudiating it, we gain insight into Goodman’s contributions. I begin then by reviewing the distinction and the conception of philosophy it supports. The analytic/synthetic distinction is a distinction between truths that depend entirely on meaning and truths that depend on both meaning and fact. In the early modern period, it was cast as a distinction between relations of ideas and matters of fact.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Logic 2018 Course Description (Tentative) January 15, 2018
    Philosophical Logic 2018 Course description (tentative) January 15, 2018 Valentin Goranko Introduction This 7.5 hp course is mainly intended for students in philosophy and is generally accessible to a broad audience with basic background on formal classical logic and general appreciation of philosophical aspects of logic. Practical information The course will be given in English. It will comprise 18 two-hour long sessions combining lectures and exercises, grouped in 2 sessions per week over 9 teaching weeks. The weekly pairs of 2-hour time slots (incl. short breaks) allocated for these sessions, will be on Mondays during 10.00-12.00 and 13.00-15.00, except for the first lecture. The course will begin on Wednesday, April 4, 2018 (Week 14) at 10.00 am in D220, S¨odra huset, hus D. Lecturer's info: Name: Valentin Goranko Email: [email protected] Homepage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko Course webpage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko/Courses2018/PhilLogic-2018.html Prerequisites The course will be accessible to a broad audience with introductory background on classical formal logic. Some basic knowledge of modal logics would be an advantage but not a prerequisite. Brief description Philosophical logic studies a variety of non-classical logical systems intended to formalise and reason about various philosophical concepts and ideas. They include a broad family of modal logics, as well as many- valued, intuitionistic, relevant, conditional, non-monotonic, para-consistent, etc. logics. Modal logics extend classical logic with additional intensional logical operators, reflecting different modes of truth, including alethic, epistemic, doxastic, temporal, deontic, agentive, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Introitus: the Entrance Chant of the Mass in the Roman Rite
    Introitus: The Entrance Chant of the mass in the Roman Rite The Introit (introitus in Latin) is the proper chant which begins the Roman rite Mass. There is a unique introit with its own proper text for each Sunday and feast day of the Roman liturgy. The introit is essentially an antiphon or refrain sung by a choir, with psalm verses sung by one or more cantors or by the entire choir. Like all Gregorian chant, the introit is in Latin, sung in unison, and with texts from the Bible, predominantly from the Psalter. The introits are found in the chant book with all the Mass propers, the Graduale Romanum, which was published in 1974 for the liturgy as reformed by the Second Vatican Council. (Nearly all the introit chants are in the same place as before the reform.) Some other chant genres (e.g. the gradual) are formulaic, but the introits are not. Rather, each introit antiphon is a very unique composition with its own character. Tradition has claimed that Pope St. Gregory the Great (d.604) ordered and arranged all the chant propers, and Gregorian chant takes its very name from the great pope. But it seems likely that the proper antiphons including the introit were selected and set a bit later in the seventh century under one of Gregory’s successors. They were sung for papal liturgies by the pope’s choir, which consisted of deacons and choirboys. The melodies then spread from Rome northward throughout Europe by musical missionaries who knew all the melodies for the entire church year by heart.
    [Show full text]
  • Alexander of Hales'stheology in His Authentic Texts (Commentary On
    chapter 13 Alexander of Hales’s Theology in His Authentic Texts (Commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Various Disputed Questions) Hubert Philipp Weber As the first teacher at the University of Paris to become a Franciscan friar, Alexander of Hales has an honoured place in the history of the order. The greater part of his theological work was already completed while he was a secular master. It is therefore more correct to call him an important theolo- gian who influenced Franciscan theology. However, it is not easy to distinguish what makes him a ‘Franciscan theologian’. I will begin by offering some his- torical remarks on his life and his authentic writings, most of which were discovered in the twentieth century. Then I will continue by giving an impres- sion of his thought with a few examples from his writings. The final sec- tion contains a very short outline of the Summa Universae Theologiae (also known as the Summa fratris Alexandri or Summa Halensis) connected with his name. 1 Historical Remarks: Alexander’s Life and Work We do not know very much about Alexander’s early life.1 His surname indicates his origin, Hales in Shropshire, England, where he was born around 1185. He stayed in contact with England all his life. In the first years of the thirteenth century he arrived at the University of Paris, where he studied and taught artes liberales. From about 1220 he lectured at the theological faculty. During the conflict between the university and the bishop of Paris in 1229/31 he went into exile.
    [Show full text]
  • Against Logical Form
    Against logical form Zolta´n Gendler Szabo´ Conceptions of logical form are stranded between extremes. On one side are those who think the logical form of a sentence has little to do with logic; on the other, those who think it has little to do with the sentence. Most of us would prefer a conception that strikes a balance: logical form that is an objective feature of a sentence and captures its logical character. I will argue that we cannot get what we want. What are these extreme conceptions? In linguistics, logical form is typically con- ceived of as a level of representation where ambiguities have been resolved. According to one highly developed view—Chomsky’s minimalism—logical form is one of the outputs of the derivation of a sentence. The derivation begins with a set of lexical items and after initial mergers it splits into two: on one branch phonological operations are applied without semantic effect; on the other are semantic operations without phono- logical realization. At the end of the first branch is phonological form, the input to the articulatory–perceptual system; and at the end of the second is logical form, the input to the conceptual–intentional system.1 Thus conceived, logical form encompasses all and only information required for interpretation. But semantic and logical information do not fully overlap. The connectives “and” and “but” are surely not synonyms, but the difference in meaning probably does not concern logic. On the other hand, it is of utmost logical importance whether “finitely many” or “equinumerous” are logical constants even though it is hard to see how this information could be essential for their interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Absurd Author(S): Thomas Nagel Reviewed Work(S): Source: the Journal of Philosophy, Vol
    Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Absurd Author(s): Thomas Nagel Reviewed work(s): Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 68, No. 20, Sixty-Eighth Annual Meeting of the American Philosophical Association Eastern Division (Oct. 21, 1971), pp. 716-727 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2024942 . Accessed: 19/08/2012 01:08 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org 7i6 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY The formerstands as valid only if we can findcriteria for assigning a differentlogical formto 'allegedly' than to 'compulsively'.In this case, the criteriaexist: 'compulsively'is a predicate, 'allegedly' a sentenceadverb. But in countless other cases, counterexamplesare not so easily dismissed.Such an example, bearing on the inference in question, is Otto closed the door partway ThereforeOtto closed the door It seems clear to me that betterdata are needed beforeprogress can be made in this area; we need much more refinedlinguistic classificationsof adverbial constructionsthan are presentlyavail- able, ifour evidenceconcerning validity is to be good enough to per- mit a richerlogical theory.In the meantime,Montague's account stands: thereis no reason to thinka morerefined theory, if it can be produced, should not be obtainable within the frameworkhe has given us.
    [Show full text]
  • Christian - Chagga Afterlife Beliefs: Pertinent Tensions
    Est Ag 56 (2021) 273-326 Christian - Chagga Afterlife Beliefs: Pertinent Tensions KOSMAS ASENGA Jordan University College, Morogoro, Tanzania Resumen: En la tarea de cumplir el mandato del Señor de anunciar el Evan- gelio a todo el mundo, el cristianismo se ha encontrado con otras culturas que poseen una concepción diferente de la creencia en la otra vida. El cristianismo tiene su propia antropología y escatología, con su compren- sión propia de la realidad del más allá caracterizada por lo que le ocurre al individuo inmediatamente después de la muerte y lo que se refiere a la consumación comunitaria en la Parusía de Cristo. El autor de este ar- tículo examina a los cristianos Chagga de Rombo que han recibido la fe cristiana, basada esta en el evento de Cristo, mientras que el pueblo Chagga se caracteriza por su creencia dominada por los antepasados y los muertos vivientes. El presente artículo abordará la cuestión de cómo conciliar estas dos creencias que parecen estar bien arraigadas en la vida espiritual del pueblo Chagga. Palabras clave: Escatología, fe, Chagga, antropología, muerte, más allá, cul- tura, religión, África. Abstract: In fulfilling the commandment of the Lord to share the Gospel to the entire world, Christianity has encountered other cultures with different comprehension regarding the afterlife belief. Christianity has its own an- thropology and eschatology. It has different understanding of the afterlife reality characterized with it: that which occurs to the individual immedi- ately after death and what is concerned with the communitarian consum- mation in the Parousia of Christ. The author of this paper is examining the Chagga Christians of Rombo who have received Christian faith with its own belief on the afterlife dominated by Christ event while the Chagga people have their belief dominated by the ancestors and the living-dead.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth-Bearers and Truth Value*
    Truth-Bearers and Truth Value* I. Introduction The purpose of this document is to explain the following concepts and the relationships between them: statements, propositions, and truth value. In what follows each of these will be discussed in turn. II. Language and Truth-Bearers A. Statements 1. Introduction For present purposes, we will define the term “statement” as follows. Statement: A meaningful declarative sentence.1 It is useful to make sure that the definition of “statement” is clearly understood. 2. Sentences in General To begin with, a statement is a kind of sentence. Obviously, not every string of words is a sentence. Consider: “John store.” Here we have two nouns with a period after them—there is no verb. Grammatically, this is not a sentence—it is just a collection of words with a dot after them. Consider: “If I went to the store.” This isn’t a sentence either. “I went to the store.” is a sentence. However, using the word “if” transforms this string of words into a mere clause that requires another clause to complete it. For example, the following is a sentence: “If I went to the store, I would buy milk.” This issue is not merely one of conforming to arbitrary rules. Remember, a grammatically correct sentence expresses a complete thought.2 The construction “If I went to the store.” does not do this. One wants to By Dr. Robert Tierney. This document is being used by Dr. Tierney for teaching purposes and is not intended for use or publication in any other manner. 1 More precisely, a statement is a meaningful declarative sentence-type.
    [Show full text]
  • The Anthropology of Christianity
    The Anthropology of Christianity: Beyond Missions and Conversion Review of: Austin-Broos, Diane Jamaica Genesis: Religion and the Politics of Moral Orders Chicago:U Chicago Press (1997) Meyer, Brigit Translating the Devil: Religion and Modernity among the Ewe in Ghana Trenton, NJ/Asmara:Africa World Press, Inc. (1999) Robbins, Joel Becoming Sinners: Christianity + Moral Torment in a Papua New Guinea Society Berkeley:U California Press (2004) Frederick, Marla Between Sundays: Black Women and Everyday Struggles of Faith Berkeley:U California Press (2003) There are many within the Christian academy, and arguably more outside it, who consider “Christian Anthropology” to be oxymoronic. Even beyond sophisticated (if misguided) theological positions declaring disciplines such as cultural anthropology to be indelibly secular and incompatible with a Christian view of the world (cf: Milbank 1991), the historic conflict between missionaries and anthropologists in the field, and the more recent yet glaringly public clash between Christian anti-evolutionists and the secular anthropologists who serve as their foil (e.g., the late Stephen Jay Gould, or Louis Leakey) has left a peculiar and particular mark on the place of anthropology vis a vis the Christian world.(Bonsen, Marks, and Miedema 1990; also Douglas 2001; Priest 2001) This history of antagonism has become written into the academic life of Christians and Christian institutions, manifest to this day. While there are no liberal arts colleges among the top 50 of U.S. News and World Report without an anthropology major (excluding technical institutes and Wabash College), there are only five schools in the CCCU (out of 105) who offer the major.
    [Show full text]
  • The Passions of the Will and the Passion of Christ in Franciscantheologyfromthe Summa Halensis to Duns Scotus
    Andrew V. Rosato The Passions of the Will and the Passion of Christ in FranciscanTheologyfromthe Summa Halensis to Duns Scotus Abstract: This chapter examines how the Summa Halensis’ analysis of Christ’ssorrow was adopted and modified by later Franciscan theologians.Accordingtothe teach- ing of Jerome, which Peter Lombardmade available to medieval theologians,Christ’s sorrow arose from an involuntary reaction to his physical suffering. In order to ex- pand upon Jerome’saccount,the Summa Halensis develops an elaborate map of Christ’ssoul by drawing on psychological principles found in Augustine and John Damascene. 13th century theologians debated whether Christ could experience sor- row over his ownsuffering not justasanatural and instinctual reaction, but also as the result of freelywillingthat he not suffer.Anobstacle to asserting this would be anyimplication that Christ did not will by his human willwhat God willed him to will. Richard of Middleton, Matthew of Aquasparta, and Duns Scotus do af- firm that Christ in some wayfreelynilled his own suffering, and experiencedsorrow over it because of that.Indifferent ways they employ the account of Christ’ssoul out- lined in the Summa Halensis to avoid anyimplication that Christ fell into sin by freely nilling his ownsuffering. The GospelofMatthew reports that Jesus experienced sorrow in the Garden of Geth- semane (26:37–38): ‘he began to be sorrowful [coepit contristari]and troubled. Then he said to them, “My soul is sorrowful [tristis]tothe point of death.”’ Jerome offered an influential interpretation of this passagewhen he statedthatChrist experienced the propassion of sorrow rather than afull-fledgedform of thatpassion. One differ- ence between apropassion and afull-fledgedpassion is that apropassion does not overwhelm one’sability to use reason.
    [Show full text]