Downloaded from Brill.Com10/02/2021 02:39:42PM Via Free Access 374 the KNOWLEDGE of GOOD
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Peter Thomas Geach, 1916–2013
PETER GEACH Peter Thomas Geach 1916–2013 PETER GEACH was born on 29 March 1916 at 41, Royal Avenue, Chelsea. He was the son of George Hender Geach, a Cambridge graduate working in the Indian Educational Service (IES), who later taught philosophy at Lahore. George Geach was married to Eleonore Sgnonina, the daughter of a Polish civil engineer who had emigrated to England. The marriage was not a happy one: after a brief period in India Eleonore returned to England to give birth and never returned to her husband. Peter Geach’s first few years were spent in the house of his Polish grandparents in Cardiff, but at the age of four his father had him made the ward of a former nanny of his own, an elderly nonconformist lady named Miss Tarr. When Peter’s mother tried to visit him, Miss Tarr warned him that a dangerous mad woman was coming, so that he cowered away from her when she tried to embrace him. As she departed she threw a brick through a window, and from that point there was no further contact between mother and son. When he was eight years old he became a boarder at Llandaff Cathedral School. Soon afterwards his father was invalided out of the IES and took charge of his education. To the surprise of his Llandaff housemaster, Peter won a scholarship to Clifton College, Bristol. Geach père had learnt moral sciences at Trinity College Cambridge from Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore, and he inducted his son into the delights of philosophy from an early age. -
Ogos De Lo Humano, Experiencia Juridica Y Derecho
OGOS DE LO HUMANO, EXPERIENCIA JURIDICA Y DERECHO SUMAntá, 1. El hecho de la. deliberación, y de la, argumentación. como punto de partida, para una teoría del logos de lo humano.-2. Preomentes en la dialéctica de la Antipüedad Clásica.-3. Renacimiento contemporáneo de este toma : Vieh- .---4. La "experiencia jurídica". Ensayo de mayores y mas rigo- rosas. precisiones sobre este concepto.-S. Aventuras de la noción de "experien- cia".--6. Ensayo de una primera descripción global o de conjunto de la "expe riencia jurídica".-7. Algunos datos de la "experiencia jurídica".-&. El locos de lo razonable o de lo humano y los temas sobre la interpretación dei Derecho y sobre la legislación9. Conclusión. 1. El hecho de la. deliberación, u de la argumentación, come punto ida para una teoría del logos de le., hum El autor del presente trabajo no es kantiano ni neo-kantiano ; pero como cualquier filósofo, por modesto que éste sea, sabe que, aun con- siderando el kantismo como una filosofía del pretérito, dé ella hemos aprendido algunos pensamientos y algunas verdades que hasta sobre- viven incólumes, a pesar de que la obra de Kant haya sido superada. Pues bien, yo querría plantear el problema del lagos de lo humano, partiendo de un factum : del hecho, que ningún filósofo ha fabricado, antes bien se encuentra con él como ante algo dado, de que frente a problemas familiares, domésticos, políticos, jurídicos, económicos, etc., los hombres deliberan, argumentan, ponderan unas razones frente a otras, buscan no la verdad, no la verdad exacta, evidente, o demostra- ble rigurosamente, indiscutible, sino una solución práctica aceptable, la más prudente que quepa encontrar, la que parezca adecuarse mejor a los términos de las. -
Hacker's Complaint
VOL. NO. JULY CONTENTS ARTICLES Intentionalism and the Imaginability of the Inverted Spectrum Eric Marcus Metaphysical Arguments against Ordinary Objects Amie L. Thomasson Kant’s Transcendental Strategy John J. Callanan True Emotions Mikko Salmela Wittgenstein and Strong Mathematical Verificationism Cyrus Panjvani DISCUSSIONS Hacker’s Complaint Scott Soames Are There Non-Existent Intentionalia? Alberto Voltolini CRITICAL STUDY The Sort of Creature You Are Anselm W. Müller BOOK REVIEWS BLACKWELL PUBLISHING FOR THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB AND THE UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. , No. July ISSN – DISCUSSIONS HACKER’S COMPLAINT B S S My goal in writing ‘Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century’ was to identify and explain the most important achievements of analytic philosophy which every student of the subject should be aware of, as well as those of its failures from which we have the most to learn. I attempted to do this by constructing a history that was itself a piece of analytic philosophy in its emphasis on analysis, reconstruction and criticism of arguments. In rebutting Hacker’s critique of it, I explain how my goal shaped my selection of topics, with special reference to the ordinary language period. I correct his misrepresentations of my treatment of the philosophers of this period, I demonstrate his failure to grasp, or understand the significance of, the Kripkean necessary a posteriori, and I reveal the misconceptions in his criticism of my interpretation of the ‘Tractatus’. I I am grateful to the Editors for inviting me to reply to P.M.S. Hacker’s review in this journal of my Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century.1 I begin with his complaint about the materials I chose to discuss: In its selection of materials it is unrepresentative: significant figures are omitted and pivotal works are not discussed .. -
Teorías De La Argumentación Jurídica En El Contexto
I CONGRESO IBEROAMERICANO DE ARGUMENTACIÓN 14, 15 Y 16 DE AGOSTO UNIVERSIDAD EAFIT MEDELLÍN, 2019 LA TEORÍA DE LA ARGUMENTACIÓN JURÍDICA EN EL CONTEXTO IBEROAMERICANO SIMÓN MARTÍNEZ UBÁRNEZ DOCENTE INVESTIGADOR FACULTAD DE DERECHO, CIENCIAS POLÍTICAS Y SOCIALES UNIVERSIDAD POPULAR DEL CESAR. VALLEDUPAR, CESAR, COLOMBIA [email protected] RESUMEN La argumentación jurídica, se proyecta como teoría interdisciplinaria de las formas seguidas para lograr conclusiones válidas al aplicar el derecho al tomar decisiones judiciales. Los antiguos la usaron en escenarios que requerían hablar y escribir convincente y persuasivamente y en el siglo XXI ha alcanzado vigente actualidad. Aunque el centro de interés se coloca en autores europeos y norteamericanos, en Iberoamérica, se han desarrollado posturas originales basadas en el debate crítico como medio para solucionar o esclarecer conflictos. La ponencia aborda propuestas de autores iberoamericanos con suficiente peso como paradigmas dignos de atención intelectual; destacándose Carlos Vaz Ferreira con su novedosa tesis sobre la actualidad de la lógica Aristotélica y propuesta de lógica viva o psico-lógica, vinculada a una ética del entendimiento aplicable al campo del derecho; Luis Recasens Siches, ofrece una propuesta lógica de lo razonable como método de interpretación y aplicación del derecho apartada de la rigidez tradicional; Leandro Vergara, analiza y desestima la teoría de Robert Alexy y desarrolla un método probando que la ponderación es un sistema de privilegio y sacrificio, inapropiado para Latinoamérica y países en desarrollo; Néstor Leandro Guzmán, busca mostrar sintéticamente en qué medida la argumentación jurídica se manifiesta en el empleo de normas o institutos procesales cuando se los somete a las exigencias de la práctica judicial. -
Engaging with Insight of a Higher Order
ENGAGING WITH INSIGHT OF A HIGHER ORDER RECONCILING COMPLEXITY AND SIMPLEXITY THROUGH MEMORABLE METAPHOR ANTHONY JUDGE Introduction Higher orders of perfection? Appreciation of higher orders of insight Complementarity of manifestations of perfection Re-cognition of higher orders of insight through "new thinking" Representation, memorability and metaphor Questionable metaphors of perfectibility meriting challenge Greater insight through holiness? Engaging with higher orders of insight Antithesis and anathema: challenge of the "Satanic"? Potential of mirroring in engaging with greater insight References Introduction This is an exploration of the process of encountering insight of a higher order -- or seemingly so. Understood in its most general terms, this could be an insight which explains everything (a Theory of Everything), a strategy which solves all problems (the Ultimate Panacea), an exemplar understood as embodying a higher order (a Leader, a Genius, a Master, a Guru, a Professor), or a totally transformative aesthetic experience (perhaps a Revelation). Also to be considered are the implications of possible higher orders of artificial intelligence from supercomputers, as well as contact with superintelligent extraterrestrials. The assumption here is that the sense of higher order implies an extraordinary sense of perfection -- relative to one's current ordinary experience. How then to engage with the experience of perfection? How to "handle" it in practice? The challenge is of course charmingly illustrated by the encounter with an unusually attractive person -- an encounter which may mysteriously conflate all the above (as when falling in love). The exploration is of current relevance to the extent that there is a degree of hope, if not anticipation, with respect to the emergence of an Ultimate Plan, perhaps articulated by an extraordinarily charismatic individual, perhaps in the light of some ultimate Theory of Everything. -
Network Map of Knowledge And
Humphry Davy George Grosz Patrick Galvin August Wilhelm von Hofmann Mervyn Gotsman Peter Blake Willa Cather Norman Vincent Peale Hans Holbein the Elder David Bomberg Hans Lewy Mark Ryden Juan Gris Ian Stevenson Charles Coleman (English painter) Mauritz de Haas David Drake Donald E. Westlake John Morton Blum Yehuda Amichai Stephen Smale Bernd and Hilla Becher Vitsentzos Kornaros Maxfield Parrish L. Sprague de Camp Derek Jarman Baron Carl von Rokitansky John LaFarge Richard Francis Burton Jamie Hewlett George Sterling Sergei Winogradsky Federico Halbherr Jean-Léon Gérôme William M. Bass Roy Lichtenstein Jacob Isaakszoon van Ruisdael Tony Cliff Julia Margaret Cameron Arnold Sommerfeld Adrian Willaert Olga Arsenievna Oleinik LeMoine Fitzgerald Christian Krohg Wilfred Thesiger Jean-Joseph Benjamin-Constant Eva Hesse `Abd Allah ibn `Abbas Him Mark Lai Clark Ashton Smith Clint Eastwood Therkel Mathiassen Bettie Page Frank DuMond Peter Whittle Salvador Espriu Gaetano Fichera William Cubley Jean Tinguely Amado Nervo Sarat Chandra Chattopadhyay Ferdinand Hodler Françoise Sagan Dave Meltzer Anton Julius Carlson Bela Cikoš Sesija John Cleese Kan Nyunt Charlotte Lamb Benjamin Silliman Howard Hendricks Jim Russell (cartoonist) Kate Chopin Gary Becker Harvey Kurtzman Michel Tapié John C. Maxwell Stan Pitt Henry Lawson Gustave Boulanger Wayne Shorter Irshad Kamil Joseph Greenberg Dungeons & Dragons Serbian epic poetry Adrian Ludwig Richter Eliseu Visconti Albert Maignan Syed Nazeer Husain Hakushu Kitahara Lim Cheng Hoe David Brin Bernard Ogilvie Dodge Star Wars Karel Capek Hudson River School Alfred Hitchcock Vladimir Colin Robert Kroetsch Shah Abdul Latif Bhittai Stephen Sondheim Robert Ludlum Frank Frazetta Walter Tevis Sax Rohmer Rafael Sabatini Ralph Nader Manon Gropius Aristide Maillol Ed Roth Jonathan Dordick Abdur Razzaq (Professor) John W. -
'The Supreme Principle of Morality'? in the Preface to His Best
The Supreme Principle of Morality Allen W. Wood 1. What is ‘The Supreme Principle of Morality’? In the Preface to his best known work on moral philosophy, Kant states his purpose very clearly and succinctly: “The present groundwork is, however, nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality, which already constitutes an enterprise whole in its aim and to be separated from every other moral investigation” (Groundwork 4:392). This paper will deal with the outcome of the first part of this task, namely, Kant’s attempt to formulate the supreme principle of morality, which is the intended outcome of the search. It will consider this formulation in light of Kant’s conception of the historical antecedents of his attempt. Our first task, however, must be to say a little about the meaning of the term ‘supreme principle of morality’. For it is not nearly as evident to many as it was to Kant that there is such a thing at all. And it is extremely common for people, whatever position they may take on this issue, to misunderstand what a ‘supreme principle of morality’ is, what it is for, and what role it is supposed to play in moral theorizing and moral reasoning. Kant never directly presents any argument that there must be such a principle, but he does articulate several considerations that would seem to justify supposing that there is. Kant holds that moral questions are to be decided by reason. Reason, according to Kant, always seeks unity under principles, and ultimately, systematic unity under the fewest possible number of principles (Pure Reason A298-302/B355-359, A645- 650/B673-678). -
Hegel and Aristotle
HEGEL AND ARISTOTLE ALFREDO FERRARIN Boston University published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, vic 3166, Australia Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org © Alfredo Ferrarin 2001 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2001 Printed in the United States of America Typeface Baskerville 10.25/13 pt. System QuarkXPress™ 4.04 [AG] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Ferrarin, Alfredo, 1960– Hegel and Aristotle / Alfredo Ferrarin. p. cm.–(Modern European philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 0-521-78314-3 1. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770–1831. 2. Aristotle – Influence. I. Title. II. Series. B2948 .F425 2000 193–dc21 00-029779 ISBN 0 521 78314 3 hardback CONTENTS Acknowledgments page xiii List of Abbreviations xv Introduction 1 § 1. Preliminary Notes 1 § 2. On the Object and Method of This Book 7 § 3. Can Energeia Be Understood as Subjectivity? 15 part i the history of philosophy and its place within the system 1. The Idea of a History of Philosophy 31 § 1. The Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Editions and Sources 31 § 2. -
Following the Argument Where It Leads
Following The Argument Where It Leads Thomas Kelly Princeton University [email protected] Abstract: Throughout the history of western philosophy, the Socratic injunction to ‘follow the argument where it leads’ has exerted a powerful attraction. But what is it, exactly, to follow the argument where it leads? I explore this intellectual ideal and offer a modest proposal as to how we should understand it. On my proposal, following the argument where it leaves involves a kind of modalized reasonableness. I then consider the relationship between the ideal and common sense or 'Moorean' responses to revisionary philosophical theorizing. 1. Introduction Bertrand Russell devoted the thirteenth chapter of his History of Western Philosophy to the thought of St. Thomas Aquinas. He concluded his discussion with a rather unflattering assessment: There is little of the true philosophic spirit in Aquinas. He does not, like the Platonic Socrates, set out to follow wherever the argument may lead. He is not engaged in an inquiry, the result of which it is impossible to know in advance. Before he begins to philosophize, he already knows the truth; it is declared in the Catholic faith. If he can find apparently rational arguments for some parts of the faith, so much the better: If he cannot, he need only fall back on revelation. The finding of arguments for a conclusion given in advance is not philosophy, but special pleading. I cannot, therefore, feel that he deserves to be put on a level with the best philosophers either of Greece or of modern times (1945: 463). The extent to which this is a fair assessment of Aquinas is controversial.1 My purpose in what follows, however, is not to defend Aquinas; nor is it to substantiate the charges that Russell brings against him. -
Lotze and the Early Cambridge Analytic Philosophy
LOTZE AND THE EARLY CAMBRIDGE ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY ―This summer I‘ve read about a half of Lotze‘s Metaphysik. He is the most delectable, certainly, of all German writers—a pure genius.‖ William James, September 8, 1879.1 Summary Many historians of analytic philosophy consider the early philosophy of Moore, Russell and Wittgenstein as much more neo-Hegelian as once believed. At the same time, the authors who closely investigate Green, Bradley and Bosanquet find out that these have little in common with Hegel. The thesis advanced in this chapter is that what the British (ill-named) neo-Hegelians brought to the early analytic philosophers were, above all, some ideas of Lotze, not of Hegel. This is true regarding: (i) Lotze’s logical approach to practically all philosoph- ical problems; (ii) his treating of the concepts relation, structure (constructions) and order; (iii) the discussion of the concepts of states of affairs, multiple theory of judgment, general logical form; (iv) some common themes like panpsychism and contemplating the world sub specie aeternitatis. 1. LOTZE, NOT HEGEL, LIES AT THE BOTTOM OF CAMBRIDGE ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY Conventional wisdom has it that the early philosophy of Moore and Russell was under the strong sway of the British ―neo-Hegelians‖. In the same time, however, those historians who investigate the British ―neo-Hegelians‖ of 1880–1920 in detail, turn attention to the fact that the latter are not necessarily connected with Hegel: William Sweet made this point in regard to 1 Perry (1935), ii, p. 16. Bosanquet,2 Geoffrey Thomas in regard to Green,3 and Peter Nicholson in regard to Bradley.4 Finally, Nicholas Griffin has shown that Russell from 1895–8, then an alleged neo-Hegelian, ―was very strongly influenced by Kant and hardly at all by Hegel‖.5 These facts are hardly surprising, if we keep in mind that the representatives of the school of T. -
RLD PEACE Arougfclaw
tfudt f-^ublidked ! This volume records the addresses RLD and discussions of world leaders pre sented in the First World Conference PEACE on World Peace Through Law to de termine what lawyers could do to ArougfcLAW substitute the rule of law for the rule of force in international relations. The volume also records the agree The Athens World Conference ments reached and the program adopted to strengthen and expand international law and international le gal institutions as a means of main taining world peace. 874 pages beautifully bound in blue fabrikoid and stamped in gold The book every lawyer will Price $15.00 want to own WEST PUBLISHING CO. 50 West Kellogg Blvd. St Paul, Minnesota 55102 Please send copies of World Peace Through Law at $15.00 each. • Bill me P Payment enclosed Name ___________________________________________ — Address —— City State . .Zip Code. AMERICAN SOCIETY OF INTERNATIONAL LAW ANNOUNCEMENT OF NEW PUBLICATIONS LEGAL ADVISERS AND FOREIGN AFFAIRS A summary report of a conference, sponsored by the Society on the role of legal advisers in the conduct of foreign affairs, and background papers on the organization and procedures in eleven different governments for bringing legal advice to bear in the decision-making process in foreign affairs. Edited by H. C. L. Merillat. Published for the Society by Oceana Publications, Inc. 162 pp. $4.00. Now available. FOREIGN ENTERPRISE IN INDIA: LAW AND POLICIES An analysis of the legal aspects of foreign private investment in India, considered in the context of official policies and economic, political, and social trends. Includes chapters on licensing and regulation of industry, company law, exchange controls, price controls, protection of industrial property, and taxation. -
As Above, So Below. Astrology and the Inquisition in Seventeenth-Century New Spain
Department of History and Civilization As Above, So Below. Astrology and the Inquisition in Seventeenth-Century New Spain Ana Avalos Thesis submitted for assessment with a view to obtaining the degree of Doctor of History and Civilization of the European University Institute Florence, February 2007 EUROPEAN UNIVERSITY INSTITUTE Department of History and Civilization As Above, So Below. Astrology and the Inquisition in Seventeenth-Century New Spain Ana Avalos Thesis submitted for assessment with a view to obtaining the degree of Doctor of History and Civilization of the European University Institute Examining Board: Prof. Peter Becker, Johannes-Kepler-Universität Linz Institut für Neuere Geschichte und Zeitgeschichte (Supervisor) Prof. Víctor Navarro Brotons, Istituto de Historia de la Ciencia y Documentación “López Piñero” (External Supervisor) Prof. Antonella Romano, European University Institute Prof. Perla Chinchilla Pawling, Universidad Iberoamericana © 2007, Ana Avalos No part of this thesis may be copied, reproduced or transmitted without prior permission of the author A Bernardo y Lupita. ‘That which is above is like that which is below and that which is below is like that which is above, to achieve the wonders of the one thing…’ Hermes Trismegistus Contents Acknowledgements 4 Abbreviations 5 Introduction 6 1. The place of astrology in the history of the Scientific Revolution 7 2. The place of astrology in the history of the Inquisition 13 3. Astrology and the Inquisition in seventeenth-century New Spain 17 Chapter 1. Early Modern Astrology: a Question of Discipline? 24 1.1. The astrological tradition 27 1.2. Astrological practice 32 1.3. Astrology and medicine in the New World 41 1.4.