Takings: What Does Matter?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Takings: What Does Matter? Takings: What Does Matter? A Response to Professor Pefialver James R. Gordley* I agree with Professor Pefialver's criticisms of modern American takings doctrine. The doctrine is incoherent and the cases conflict. The balancing test of Penn Central Transportation Co. v. New York Cityt is not helpful -it is ad hoc and may be meaningless. It is also unhelpful to ask to what extent regulation destroys the economic value of property, and misleading to try to identify a particular property right as essential and therefore sacrosanct. Indeed, Professor Pefialver's main point is correct. It does not make sense to distinguish takings of land from takings of personal property. My disagreement is that I see more hope than Professor Pefialver in one of the five theoretical approaches he discusses: the one he calls the Thomistic-Aristotelian natural law theory. This theory is not only the oldest of the five, but may be the lineal ancestor of the takings provision of the Fifth Amendment. In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, a group of continental jurists known as the "late scholastics," self-consciously tried to synthesize the Aristotelian moral theory of Thomas Aquinas with the law of their times, mostly Roman in origin. Few people today are familiar even with the leaders of this group: Domingo de Soto (1494-1560), Luis de Molina (1535-1600), Leonard Lessius (1554-1623) and Francisco Suarez (1548- 1617). Yet, as I have described elsewhere, these scholars were the first to give private law a theory and a systematic doctrinal structure.2 Before they wrote, the Roman law in force in much of Europe had neither. For Copyright © 2004 by the Regents of the University of California. * Shannon Cecil Turner Professor of Jurisprudence, School of Law, University of California at Berkeley. 1. 438U.S. 104 (1978). 2. JAMES GORDLEY, THE PHILOSOPHICAL ORIGINS OF MODERN CONTRACT DOCTRINE 69-111 (1991); James Gordley, Tort Law in the Aristotelian Tradition, in PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF TORT LAW: A COLLECTION OF ESSAYS 131 (David Owen ed., 1995); James Gordley, The Principle Against Unjustified Enrichment, in GEDACHTNISSCHRIFT FUR ALEXANDER LODERITZ 213 (Klaus Luig, Haimo Schack & Herbert Wiedemann. Eds., 2000). ECOLOGY LA W QUARTERLY [Vol. 31:291 all their subtlety, neither the Romans nor the medieval professors of Roman law were theorists.' In contrast, the late scholastics tried to explain Roman law by philosophical principles. Their work deeply influenced the seventeenth century founders of the northern natural law school of thought, Hugo Grotius (1583-1645) and Samuel Pufendorf (1632-94) who adopted many of the late scholastics' conclusions and disseminated them through northern Europe, paradoxically, at the very time that Aristotelian and Thomistic philosophy was falling out of fashion. One of conclusions of Grotius and Pufendorf and the late scholastics was that the state could not take private property, even for a public purpose, without paying the owner just compensation. Although these writers did not work out all the implications of this principle, we can better understand the principle by examining how it fits into their larger theory of justice. Professor Pefialver is correct that this larger theory of justice Arests on the idea that human actions and institutions should foster >human flourishing.=@4 As Professor Pefialver observes, the Aristotelian approach to law rests on the idea "that human actions and institutions should seek to foster 'human flourishing."' 5 To flourish means to live a life in which one's distinctively human capacities are realized to the greatest extent possible. As Pefialver notes, "[a]ctions or institutions that are utterly inconsistent with human flourishing violate the natural law."6 External things are valuable to the extent they contribute to such a life. Consequently, the state has an obligation to do distributive justice: to see that, so far as feasible, each citizen has the resources that such a life requires. Pefialver observes, citing Finnis and Aquinas, that "Aquinas's theory of property rights endorses an active role for the state in ensuring a just distribution of property, even if that means taking property from those with more and giving it to those with less." 7 Though his description of the premises of the writers of the Aristotelian tradition is correct, Professor Pefialver does not describe the implications of those premises in the same way as writers in the 3. The Roman lawyers were interested in finding concepts and rules to explain the how legal controversies ought to be decided. Medieval lawyers were interested in logically reconciling the Roman texts. Neither were interested in trying to define the concepts they were using, explaining their logical relationship to each other, and showing how one could then logically arrive at consistent doctrine. 4. Eduardo Pefalver, Is Land Special? The Unjustified Preference for Landownership in Regulatory Takings Law, 31 ECOLOGY L.Q. 227,275 (2004). 5. Id. at 276. 6. Id. 7. Pefialver, supra note 5, at 278 (citing JOHN FINNIS, NATURAL LAW AND NATURAL RIGHTS 195 (1980) and THOMAS AoUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGIAE I-I1, 0. 66, a. 7). 20041 TAKINGS: WHATDOES MATTER? Aristotelian tradition.' Pefialver argues that in the Thomistic tradition, natural law would likely govern questions of takings only at the margins. He suggests that a natural law approach would protect an individual's property in so far as necessary to promote human flourishing, but not to the extent that the natural law approach prohibited forcible governmental redistribution to provide for the necessities of other citizens.' With these relatively broad parameters, Pefialver claims that most takings questions following the Thomistic tradition would be answered variously according to a community's choice of positive law."0 As noted earlier, writers in the Aristotelian tradition did think that the state could redistribute resources among its citizens to ensure a greater measure of distributive justice-indeed, the state could do so to promote human flourishing. Nevertheless, these early writers did not believe the state should consider what particular resources, beyond those necessary for survival, a particular citizen needed in order to flourish. Nor did they believe "questions concerning when the government must compensate for takings of property to be primarily a question for positive law.""1 According to the Aristotelian tradition, the state had to answer such questions, with rare exceptions, as a matter of natural law, that is, as a matter of commutative and distributive, justice. Let us take these propositions in turn, and then see how they can help us understand the law of takings as it is today. Although the aim of distributive justice is that each person should be able to acquire the external things that he needs to live the life he should, as Grotius pointed out, the state cannot simply allocate to each person the external things that the state thinks, or the individual thinks, that he needs. That arrangement would work, as Grotius and Lessius noted, in a society like a family or a monastery where there are few people and they are on good terms.12 Writers in the Aristotelian tradition conceived of distributive justice as ensuring that each person has a fair share of wealth. By wealth, they meant roughly what we would call purchasing power. 3 A fair share, 8. Writers in the Aristotelian tradition include among others: Aquinas, the late scholastics, and, to the extent they remained under its influence, natural lawyers such as Grotius and Pufendorf. 9. Id. 10. Id. 11. Id. 12. HUGo GROTIUS, DE lURE BELLI AC PACIS LIBRI TRES (1646), II.ii.2; LEONARDUS LESSIus, DE IUSTITIA ET lURE, CETERISQUE VIRTUTIBUS CARDINALIS LIBRI QUATUOR lib. 2, cap. 5, dub. 3, no. 9. 13. Not quite, because people acquire things that are worth more to them than the amount of purchasing power they represent. A person who loses such a thing, and cannot buy another like it, will have lost more than that amount. Consequently, if someone takes or destroys it, he should pay its value to the owner even if that is more than the amount for which the owner could have sold it. If something identical is not available on the market and someone offers to buy it, the owner can sell it for a price that reflects its value to him. See James Gordley, Contract Law in ECOLOGY LA W QUARTERLY [Vol. 31:291 they acknowledged, will be understood differently in differently constituted societies. In a society ruled by the virtuous-an aristocracy- "fair share" means that wealth should ideally be divided in proportion to individual human virtue. In a democracy, each person should ideally have the same share. 4 Writers in this tradition emphasized that such principles are ideals. A democracy should not confiscate the wealth of rich people, virtuous or otherwise, and divide it up. 5 We can see one reason why it should not if we consider Aristotle's objections -which Aquinas shared- to Plato's proposal to abolish private property. Do so, Aristotle said, and there will be endless quarrels, and people will have no incentive to work or to take care of property. 6 If such evils are to be prevented, an ideal distribution of wealth can only be approximated. Distributive justice, then, aims at securing each citizen a fair share of wealth in the sense of purchasing power. Commutative justice, in contrast, preserves the share that belongs to each-if one person deprives another of resources, commutative justice requires that he make compensation for that deprivation.17 It followed that the state had no more right to deprive a citizen of his resources without compensation than any ordinary citizen. Lessius explained that even if an act is done by a public personage or the governor of the country..
Recommended publications
  • On the Tyrant
    Bartolus of Saxoferrato On the Tyrant Translated from: Diego Quaglioni, ed. 1983. Politica e diritto nel Trecento italiano. Il ‘De tyranno’ di Bartolo da Sassoferrato (1314–1357) con l’edizione critica dei trattati ‘De guelphis et gebellinis,’ ‘De regimine civitatis’ e ‘De tyranno.’ Il pensiero politico, Biblioteca 11. Florence: Leo S. Olschki Editore, 175–213.1 [1] Because2 I have already laboured for a long time over many tracts, deal- ing with the sweetest materials, which render body, heart, and soul entirely mellifluous (saporosam), I am so full of a sweet taste that I have dared not ap- proach the harshnesses, the difficulties, and the tribulations, especially since I see that tyrannical perfidy is extending its strength. Still, having trusted in 3 the protection of that mercy, which makes eloquent the tongues of infants—nay, Sap. 10:21 4 even makes them shine openly for the nations, I do dare take up (with the cf. Ex. 40:33; Ps. 76:19; help of divine aid) the so severe and horrendous subject matter of tyrannical Ps. 143:6 depravity, not so that I derive any joy or solace from it, but so that all are able to rid themselves completely of the tie and noose of that horrendous wickedness, namely, tyrannical servitude; from this austere and immoderate magisterium God delivers (liberet) us; he conserves us in our own holy, good, and perfect tranquility; ⟦and⟧ he makes us be found (colletari) in the sweetness of liberty. 1. Editorial interventions are marked by ⟨angle brackets⟩, while my own are put in ⟦double square brackets⟧.
    [Show full text]
  • Special Collections and University Archives Pages From
    Special Collections and University Archives Pages from the Past: Original leaves from Rare Books and Manuscripts Manuscript Group 178 For Scholarly Use Only Last Modified January 29, 2015 Indiana University of Pennsylvania 302 Stapleton Library Indiana, PA 15705-1096 Voice: (724) 357-3039 Fax: (724) 357-4891 Manuscript Group 178 2 Pages from the Past: Original leaves from Rare Books and Manuscripts; Manuscript Group 178 Indiana University of Pennsylvania, Special Collections and University Archives 4 folios; 4 linear feet Historical Information The “Pages from the Past: Original leaves from Rare Books and Manuscripts” (1964) were proprietorial folios that Alfred W. Stites assembled, individually signed, and marketed to academic libraries in the 1960s. In 1966, Stites was president of Stites Associates in Washington, DC, and he amassed several thousand leaves that were removed from rare books and manuscripts and collected by earlier bibliophiles. The original intent of the creation of these folio collections was to address “the concern of rare book collectors today, that the price of a book only a few centuries old had become too costly.” The folios created an affordable way for academic libraries to purchase many examples of artifacts, rare books, and manuscripts. Please note that although these folios have educational and research potential for those interested in the history of the written word and European printing presses, the IUP Special Collections and University Archives does not condone the unnecessary separation of leaves from any rare book or manuscript. Stites created 122 portfolio sets of leaves removed from rare books and manuscripts that were sold to academic libraries (including the IUP Libraries).
    [Show full text]
  • IMAGES of LEGAL HUMANISM Douglas J
    Document generated on 09/23/2021 1:04 p.m. Surfaces IMAGES OF LEGAL HUMANISM Douglas J. Osler TROISIÈME CONGRÈS INTERNATIONAL SUR LE DISCOURS Article abstract HUMANISTE. LA RÉSISTANCE HUMANISTE AU DOGMATISME Legal humanism is an expression generally used to refer to the study of Roman AUJOURD’HUI ET À LA FIN DU MOYEN ÂGE law by 16th Century philologists. Coming a century an a half after what is THIRD INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON HUMANISTIC generally taken to be the birth of humanism, it is generally understood to be DISCOURSE. HUMANISTIC RESISTANCE TO DOGMATISM TODAY part of humanism mostly in its interest for the historical interpretation of Latin AND AT THE END OF THE MIDDLE AGES texts rather than for participating in the value orientation of humanism. Volume 9, 2001 Strangely enough, legal history has taken the philological work of legal humanism for granted not seeing that legal humanism was itself inscribed in history. First, we should note that when it was being developed in the 16th URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1065066ar Century, this philological work in Roman law was marginal if one compares DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/1065066ar publications in that field to publications of medieval Italian jurisprudence. Secondly, legal history has tended to diminish the presence of interpretation in See table of contents the work of legal humanists who probably more than is generally acknowledged adapted to their times the Latin texts inventing values which have nothing to do with the Roman sources. Legal humanism has never been Publisher(s) used to mean the legal aspects of humanitarianism and probably needn’t to be.
    [Show full text]
  • 征服と自由:マキァヴェッリの政治思想とルネサンス・フィレンツェ』(風行社、2013年)  参照文献(Bibliography)
    鹿子生浩輝 『征服と自由:マキァヴェッリの政治思想とルネサンス・フィレンツェ』(風行社、2013年) 参照文献(bibliography) *著者の鹿子生氏の了解を得て、『征服と自由』に収録が予定されていながら紙幅の都合で収録さ れなかった参照文献一覧を、本シンポジウムの参考資料として、末尾に収録することとした。 【一次文献】 Alberti, Leon Battista, Della famiglia, diretta da Ferdinando Martini(Milano: Istituto editoriale italiano,n.d.). 池上俊一・徳橋曜訳『家族論』(講談社、2010年)。 Alamanni, Lodovico, Discorso di Lodovico Alamanni sopra il fermare lo stato di Firenze nella devozione de’ Medici,inAlbertini,Firenze dalla repubblica al principato: Storia e coscienza politica, tr.byCesareCristorolini(Torino: GiulioEinaudiEditore,1955),pp.376-384. ― .‘Ill.mo domino domino Alberto Pio, carpensi principi et caesareo oratori, S. D.’, in Albertini, Firenze dalla repubblica al principato,pp.385-390. Anon. Discorso I di anonimo sulla riforma dello stato fiorentino l’anno 1494, in Guidi, Ciò che accadde al tempo della signoria di novembre dicembre in Firenze l’anno 1494(Firenze: Arnaud Editore,1988),pp.201-205. Anon. Discorso II di anonimo sulla riforma dello stato fiorentino l’anno 1494, in Guidi, Ciò che accadde al tempo della signoria di novembre dicembre in Firenze l’anno 1494,pp.206-207. Aquinas, Thomas, De Regimine Principum ad Regem Cypri, in Aquinas: Selected Political Writings, ed.byA.P.D’entrèves,tr.byJ.G.Dawson(Oxford: BasilBlackwell,1959). 柴田平三郎訳『君主 の統治について ― 謹んでキプロス王に捧げる』(慶應義塾大学出版会、2005年)。 ― . Summa Theologiae, in Opera Omnia, vol.II, currante di Roberto Busa(Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt:Frommann-Holzboog,1980),pp.184-924. 高田三郎ほか訳『神学大全』(創文社、1962-2012 年)。 Bacon, Francis, The Advancement of Learning(The Oxford Francis Bacon, IV)(Oxford: Clarendon Press,2000). 服部英次郎・多田英次訳「学問の進歩」『世界の大思想(6)ベーコン』(河出書房新社、 1971年)。 BartolusdeSaxoferrato,De Guelphis,in Humanism and Tyranny: Studies in the Italian Trecento,tr. byEphraimEmerton(Gloucester: PeterSmith,1964),pp.273-284.
    [Show full text]
  • Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-49323-9 — Polish
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-49323-9 — Polish Republican Discourse in the Sixteenth Century Dorota Pietrzyk-Reeves , Translated by Teresa Bałuk-Ulewiczowa Index More Information Index absolutum dominium, 75, 111, 203, 230, see also as guide to res publica, 7, 8, 16, 47, 49, 53, 56, 57, power 65, 154 Anonim Senator, 100, 230 influence of on republican discourse of Aristotle, 7, 60, 61, 87, 239 Poland–Lithuania, 20, 23, 25, 45, 46, 56, 60, as guide to mixed constitution, 176, 177, 221 61, 67, 121, 122, 144, 152, 157 as guide to political authority, 186 on law, 61, 78, 80, 97 as guide to politics, 2, 4, 6 on liberty, 98 as guide to virtue, 142, 150, 153, 157, 158, 211 citizenship, 12, 15, 16, 58, 59, 66, 107, 151, 152, 153, influence on republican ideas, 7, 16, 45, 46, 56 154, 155, 157, 158, 159, 166, 168, 171, 173 reception in Poland–Lithuania, 59–62, 70, 77, as amor patriae, 158, 159 88, 121, 130, 132, 135, 136–8, 144, 146, 151, 154, civitas libera, 3, 7, 12, 44, 51, 53, 69, 71, 73, 107, 125, 155, 171, 196, 197, 214, 215, 224, 233 128, 131, 156, 159, 164, 166, 183, 192, 210, 218, Augustine, St, 6, 22, 45 225, 240 authority, 23, 25, 40, 72, 77, 105, 175, 184, 186, 188, classical republican tradition, 51, 56, 66, 70, 104, 191, 201, 215, 216, 217, see also power 122, 127, 158, 174, 178 in law, 126, 187 and political order, 131 sources of, 16, 25, 27, 34, 36, 72 and republicanism, 6 defined, 5 Baranowski, Wojciech, 102 in Aristotle, 132, 134 Bartolus, de Saxoferrato, 45, 52 common good, 3, 5–7, 22, 23, 53–4, 67, 105, 106, Biernat of Lublin,
    [Show full text]
  • Fuentes Para El Estudio De La Ciudad Medieval (Siglos XIII-XV): Tratados De Gobierno
    Fuentes para el estudio de la ciudad medieval (siglos XIII-XV): tratados de gobierno. Definición de un género literario Sources for the study of medieval city (13th to 15th centuries): trea- tises of government. Definition of a literary genre Josué VILLA PRIETO Università degli Studi di Roma “Tor Vergata” [email protected] Recibido: 25/03/2014 Aceptado: 10/06/2014 RESUMEN El objeto de este artículo es analizar las particularidades literarias de los tratados bajomedievales desti- nados a la formación de los regidores urbanos en la Baja Edad Media. Este tipo de tratados se desarrollan como género literario se durante los siglos XIII-XV; en su configuración intervienen tres elementos: las ordenanzas reales sobre el funcionamiento de las instituciones locales, los textos pedagógicos sobre materia política y moral de la Antigüedad Clásica y Tardía, y la tratadística coetánea europea, espe- cialmente la elaborada en el humanismo italiano. La segunda parte del artículo se centra en exponer la influencia de los tratados italianos sobre los hispanos, con autores como Egidio Romano (De regimine principum), Leonardo Bruni (De nobiliate) o Bartolo de Sasoferrato (De insigniis et armis), entre otros. Por otra parte, los tratados peninsulares que permiten un mejor estudio de la caracterización ideal de la nobleza urbana con responsabilidades políticas son las obras de Ramón Llull, don Juan Manuel, Fran- cesc Eiximenis, Juan de Alarcón, Alonso de Cartagena, Rodrigo Sánchez de Arévalo y Diego de Valera. Palabras clave: Tratados de gobierno, ciudad medieval, regidores urbanos, educación y moralidad me- dieval, Rodrigo Sánchez de Arévalo, Diego de Valera. ABSTRACT This article aims to expose the literary characteristics of the treatises used to provide professional trai- ning to urban councillors in the Late Middle Ages.
    [Show full text]
  • When Is the Use of Foreign Law Possible? a Hard Case: the Rp Otection of Privacy in Europe and the United States James Gordley
    Louisiana Law Review Volume 67 | Number 4 Symposium: Law Making in a Global World Summer 2007 When Is the Use of Foreign Law Possible? A Hard Case: The rP otection of Privacy in Europe and the United States James Gordley Repository Citation James Gordley, When Is the Use of Foreign Law Possible? A Hard Case: The Protection of Privacy in Europe and the United States, 67 La. L. Rev. (2007) Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.lsu.edu/lalrev/vol67/iss4/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews and Journals at LSU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Louisiana Law Review by an authorized editor of LSU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. When Is the Use of Foreign Law Possible? A Hard Case: The Protection of Privacy in Europe and the United States James Gordley* I. INTRODUCTION No one thinks it odd that a Minnesota court should be guided by a decision in Wisconsin. The reason, some might say, is that Minnesota and Wisconsin are both applying the same system of legal rules: the common law. The meaning of a rule is shaped by its place in the larger system of rules and by the traditions that formed that system. If that is so, one might expect little guidance by looking to the rules of a foreign legal system. Instead, however, one might think a Minnesota court should consult a Wisconsin decision simply because both courts are facing the same problem. History and tradition might explain why the problem happens to be the same, but so long as it is, Minnesota judges should care about what those in Wisconsin do for the same reason that engineers at Boeing should care about what engineers at Airbus do.
    [Show full text]
  • Great Christian Jurists in German History
    Great Christian Jurists in German History Edited by Mathias Schmoeckel and John Witte Jr. Great Christian Jurists in German History Edited by Mathias Schmoeckel and John Witte Jr. Mohr Siebeck Mathias Schmoeckel is professor of civil law and legal history and Director of the Institute of German and Rhenish Legal History. John Witte Jr. is Robert W. Woodruff University Professor of Law, McDonald Distin‑ guished Professor of Religion, and Director of the Center for the Study of Law and Reli‑ gion at Emory University in Atlanta. ISBN 978‑3‑16‑158346‑9 / eISBN 978‑978‑3‑16‑158347‑6 DOI 10.1628 / 978‑3‑16‑158347‑6 The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliogra‑ phie; detailed bibliographic data are available at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2020 Mohr Siebeck Tübingen, Germany. www.mohrsiebeck.com This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This applies particularly to reproductions, translations and storage and processing in electronic systems. The book was typeset using Stempel Garamond typeface and printed on non‑aging paper by Laupp und Göbel in Gomaringen, and bound by Nädele in Nehren. Printed in Germany. Table of Contents Preface and Acknowledgements ................................... IX Chapter 1 Ken Pennington: Johannes Teutonicus (ca. 1170 / 75 – 1245) .............. 1 Chapter 2 Tilman Repgen: Eike von Repgow (ca. 1180 – 1235) and the Christian Character of his Sachsenspiegel .................................... 13 Chapter 3 Sven Lichtmann and Hannes Möhle: Albertus Magnus (ca. 1200 – 1280) Natural Law as Law of Reason and its Significance for the Political Order ..........................
    [Show full text]
  • Washington, DC 22–24 March 2012 Leonardo Da Vinci, Ginevra De’ Benci, Ca
    The Renaissance Society of America Annual Meeting Program and Abstract Book Washington, DC 22–24 March 2012 Leonardo da Vinci, Ginevra de’ Benci, ca. 1474/78. Alisa Mellon Bruce Fund. Image courtesy of the National Gallery of Art, Washington. Contents The indexes in this book refer to five-digit panel numbers, not page numbers. Panels on Thursday have panel numbers that begin with the number 1; panels on Friday begin with the number 2; and pan- els on Saturday begin with the number 3. The black tabs on each page of the full program are an additional navigational aid: they pro- vide the date and time of the panels. RSA Executive Board.......................................................................5 Acknowledgments.............................................................................6 Book Exhibition and Registration ...................................................10 Business Meetings...........................................................................11 Plenaries, Awards, and Special Events.............................................12 Program Summary Thursday.................................................................................16 Friday.....................................................................................25 Saturday..................................................................................32 Full program with abstracts Thursday 8:30–10:00.......................................................................41 10:15–11:45.....................................................................74
    [Show full text]
  • A Feud on Italian City- States? Again on Lorenzetti's
    Pag. 1 A FEUD ON ITALIAN CITY- STATES? AGAIN ON LORENZETTI’S BUONGOVERNO Data: 31 Maggio 2021 - Di Mario Ascheri Rubrica: Letture It would be useful a new examination on the topic of the Italian City-States. For a long time historians shared a general interest on the Italian city-states and their final failure within the rise of the “Signorie”, that is governments led by single rulers (cf. the traditional book by Daniel Waley,The Italian City- Republics, 4th edition with Trevor Dean, London, 2010, a good example among many others). During the last decades, this appreciation became doubtful. Paradoxically, one reason was the republican interpretation of the medieval and modern history led by the so-called school of Cambridge (Pocock-Skinner, followed by Viroli). They bound with a redline the political thought of the Greek antiquity, of the medieval Italian Communes and the 'modern' English-American republicanism[1]. The result has been growing, heterogenous, and more or less explicit reactions. Some scholars accuse the traditional historiography of super- evaluation of the writings of the communal thirteenth century rhetoric masters, giving too much attention and importance to the theological- juridical Marsilius’ and Bartolus’ thoughts, or to Florentines theorists such as Coluccio Salutati and Leonardo Bruni. They imply the following idea: Italian Communes were not so different from the free cities of other states, specially ilpensierostorico.com A Feud on Italian City-States? Again on Lorenzetti’s Buongoverno https://ilpensierostorico.com/a-feud-on-italian-city-states-again-on-lorenzettis-buongoverno/ Pag. 2 the German or Flemish ones. My assumption is, on the contrary, that the Italian city-states were exceptional institutions in European history which left permanent – positive and negative – effects (at least) in the Italian history.
    [Show full text]
  • IMAGES of LEGAL HUMANISM Douglas J
    Document generated on 09/27/2021 2:54 p.m. Surfaces IMAGES OF LEGAL HUMANISM Douglas J. Osler TROISIÈME CONGRÈS INTERNATIONAL SUR LE DISCOURS Article abstract HUMANISTE. LA RÉSISTANCE HUMANISTE AU DOGMATISME Legal humanism is an expression generally used to refer to the study of Roman AUJOURD’HUI ET À LA FIN DU MOYEN ÂGE law by 16th Century philologists. Coming a century an a half after what is THIRD INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON HUMANISTIC generally taken to be the birth of humanism, it is generally understood to be DISCOURSE. HUMANISTIC RESISTANCE TO DOGMATISM TODAY part of humanism mostly in its interest for the historical interpretation of Latin AND AT THE END OF THE MIDDLE AGES texts rather than for participating in the value orientation of humanism. Volume 9, 2001 Strangely enough, legal history has taken the philological work of legal humanism for granted not seeing that legal humanism was itself inscribed in history. First, we should note that when it was being developed in the 16th URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1065066ar Century, this philological work in Roman law was marginal if one compares DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/1065066ar publications in that field to publications of medieval Italian jurisprudence. Secondly, legal history has tended to diminish the presence of interpretation in See table of contents the work of legal humanists who probably more than is generally acknowledged adapted to their times the Latin texts inventing values which have nothing to do with the Roman sources. Legal humanism has never been Publisher(s) used to mean the legal aspects of humanitarianism and probably needn’t to be.
    [Show full text]
  • Studien Zur Europäischen Rechtsgeschichte
    Studien zur europäischen Rechtsgeschichte Veröffentlichungen des Max-Planck-Instituts für europäische Rechtsgeschichte Frankfurt am Main Band 319 Vittorio Klostermann Frankfurt am Main 2019 Guido Rossi Representation and Ostensible Authority in Medieval Learned Law Vittorio Klostermann Frankfurt am Main 2019 Bibliographische Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliographie; detaillierte bibliographische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.dnb.de abruar. © Vittorio Klostermann GmbH Frankfurt am Main 2019 Alle Rechte vorbehalten, insbesondere die des Nachdrucks und der Übersetzung. Ohne Genehmigung des Verlages ist es nicht gestattet, dieses Werk oder Teile in einem photomechanischen oder sonstigen Reproduktionsverfahren oder unter Verwendung elektronischer Systeme zu verarbeiten, zu vervielfältigen und zu verbreiten. Druck und Bindung: docupoint GmbH, Barleben Typographie: Elmar Lixenfeld, Frankfurt am Main Gedruckt auf Eos Werkdruck. Alterungsbeständig und PEFC-zerti fiziert TM PEFC/04-31-0880 Printed in Germany ISSN 1610-6040 ISBN 978-3-465-04390-4 to Peter Oestmann Contents Foreword ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... XI Main abbreviations ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... XII 1 Introduction ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... 1 1.1 On the non-linearity of (legal) thought ... ... ... ... ... ... ..
    [Show full text]