An Investigation of Socrates As Characterized in the “Forgotten” Dialogues and Apology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Load more

THE EXAMINED LIFE EXAMINED AN INVESTIGATION OF SOCRATES AS CHARACTERIZED IN THE “FORGOTTEN” DIALOGUES AND APOLOGY A THESIS Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Political Science Colorado College Professor Timothy Fuller, Advisor ________________________ In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Bachelor of Arts By Samantha Albert May 2015 2 Acknowledgements I would like to sincerely thank Professor Timothy Fuller for so generously supporting me through my thesis project. I am grateful for his sage advice, judicious observations and most importantly, for encouraging me to live the examined life. I would also like to thank my family for their unwavering love and encouragement during my four years at CC. 3 Colorado College Honor Code On my honor I have neither given nor received unauthorized aid on this thesis project. Samantha Albert 4 Table of Contents Introduction ............................................................................................................................. 5 Socrates as Stingray, Midwife, and Gadfly ...................................................................... 6 Examination of Hipparchus ................................................................................................. 8 Examination of Minos .......................................................................................................... 15 Examination of Lovers ......................................................................................................... 22 Examination of Cleitophon ................................................................................................. 26 Examination of Alcibiades I ............................................................................................... 28 Examination of Apology ...................................................................................................... 45 Conclusion ............................................................................................................................... 55 5 Introduction Many of us may think that we know Socrates. At one point in our lives we may have been given a glimpse of this man through his portrayal in well-known Platonic dialogues like the Republic, Gorgias, or Apology. While these are all important works that shed light on Socrates as philosopher and teacher, they do not represent the man in his entirety. My goal in this paper is to produce a more “multi- dimensional” characterization of Socrates by examining several “forgotten” Platonic dialogues. The intention of this paper is to produce a more comprehensive characterization of Socrates so as to examine whether Athens was justified in ultimately trying Socrates and putting him to death. I seek to assess how these “forgotten” dialogues shed light upon the conflict between Socrates and Athens and fundamentally how they elucidate the conflict between philosophy and politics. Understanding these conflicts should help contribute to a better understanding of Socrates, his method of enquiry, and his ability to teach others. While Socrates can be characterized in many different ways, some of the best characterization techniques are the use of three analogies, the stingray, the midwife, and the gadfly. In light of his trial in Apology, these analogies are a catalyst for the various ways that Socrates can be best understood throughout all Platonic dialogues. Because these analogies are a good representation of Socrates’s character, they will be used throughout this paper. A brief explanation of each analogy is necessary before I begin my expositions of the various “forgotten” dialogues. 6 Socrates as Stingray, Midwife, and Gadfly The stingray analogy originates from Plato’s dialogue Meno, in which the individual that Socrates is engaged in conversation with recognizes the perplexity that Socrates seems to create in others. The comrade engaged with Socrates exclaims that he is “like the broad torpedo fish [stingray], for it makes anyone who comes close and touches it feel numb, and you seem to have had that kind of effect on me, for both my mind and tongue are numb, and I have no answer to give you” (80b). In other words, Socrates seems to instill a sort of paralysis in others by engaging them in dialogue. Socrates responds by stating that “if the torpedo fish [stingray] is itself numb and so makes others numb, then I resemble it, but not otherwise, for I myself do not have the answer when I perplex others, but I am more perplexed than anyone when I cause perplexity in others” (80c). This analogy helps to characterize Socrates as a man who has the power to paralyze thought, both in others and in himself. This is important because it shows that he is not afraid to ask perplexing questions—to make others truly think and to experience discomfort in dialoguing. Socrates points out, however, that it is not simply numbing paralysis that he may instill in others, but also within himself. This shows that there are no evident answers in the pursuit of wisdom, as Socrates also struggles with the difficult questions that he raises in each dialogue. The midwife analogy comes from Plato’s dialogue Theaetetus. In discussing midwifery with a comrade, Socrates states that in his version of midwifery, “I attend men and not women; and look after their souls when they are in labour, and not after their bodies: and the triumph of my art is in thoroughly examining whether the 7 thought which the mind of the young man brings forth is a false idol or a noble and true birth” (150 b-c). This analogy best explains Socrates as a man who allows others to realize their own thoughts on their quest for wisdom. Socrates does not engage in dialogue to offer answers to others, but to allow others to discover their own answers. Socrates as midwife helps to birth one’s thoughts and recollections. His role as midwife prompts others to recall the things that they may have known before they entered the bodily world. The gadfly analogy originates from Apology. In responding to his accusations during his trial, Socrates states that he was “attached to this city by the god—though it seems a ridiculous thing to say—as upon a great and noble horse which was somewhat sluggish because of its size and needed to be stirred up by a kind of gadfly…. I never cease to rouse each and every one of you, to persuade and reproach you all day long and everywhere I find myself in your company” (30e). Socrates likens himself to a gadfly in the same sense that a gadfly has the ability to jolt a horse. Through Socrates’s method of dialogue, he is able to engage with others and allow them to contemplate questions that they may otherwise have failed to acknowledge. Throughout this process Socrates, as gadfly, has the opportunity to insight a sort of awakening in others, by hopefully allowing them to realize new and thought provoking ideas. Sometimes this works out well, and individuals leave Socrates with a renewed sense of understanding and realization. More often than not however, Socrates increases other’s confusion and puzzlement, by failing to “answer” the questions that they ask. The feeling that Socrates has somehow “failed” them in answering their questions has contributed to a negative perception of 8 Socrates, one that is a theme throughout the following “forgotten” dialogues, and one that contributes to the ultimate trial of Socrates as seen in Apology. Examination of Hipparchus Plato’s Hipparchus begins with the questions, “what is the love of gain?” and “who are the lovers of gain?” (225a) Characteristically some Socratic dialogues begin with the “what is…?” question. This is an important recognition because, as seen in Hipparchus, Socrates makes it clear that he is not simply seeking an example of gain, or justice, etc., but wants to know what the core meaning of gain is—evident in the “what is” question. Ultimately the question is, what is gain in and of itself? Key to this argument is the fundamental difference between what appears to be gain and what real gain actually is. One of the points that Socrates will make is that, while everyone is a lover of gain, moreover there are different types of gain that can be pursued. In response to Socrates’s gain question, the Comrade responds by stating that he believes the lovers of gain to be those who think it meaningful to make gains from things that are worthless (225a). While the Comrade attempts to define gain here, at this point he does not actually answer the “what is the love of gain?” question. Instead, the Comrade makes it seem as if those that like worthwhile things do not love gain. Furthermore, no one is going to pursue something that they know is not worth pursuing. Thus what is required is a genuine knowledge of what something is, not of what it appears to be. While all human beings have a drive to gain something, there is a hierarchy of gain that can be pursued. A lack of knowledge 9 about this hierarchy of gain can sometimes lead to a mistaken view of what should be gained, therefore leading to a misunderstanding of what gain actually is. A common theme throughout the Platonic dialogues is a character’s inability or lack of desire to answer Socrates’s initial question. The Comrade’s lack of appropriate response to the “what is” question leads Socrates to respond by asking whether those who think it is meaningful to make gains from worthless things actually know that the things being pursued are worthless. The Comrade responds by claiming that those pursuing gain do in fact know that they are
Recommended publications
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues

    The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues

    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues

    On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues

    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
  • The Wisdom of Noble Simplicity

    The Wisdom of Noble Simplicity

    The Εὐηθέστεροι Myth: the Wisdom of Noble Simplicity L. M. J. Coulson A Thesis Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Classics and Ancient History School of Philosophical and Historical Inquiry Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences The University of Sydney November 2016 Statement of Originality This is to certify that to the best of my knowledge, the content of this thesis is my own work. This thesis has not been submitted for any degree or other purposes. I certify that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work and that all the assistance received in preparing this thesis and sources have been acknowledged. L. M. J. Coulson November 2016 i Acknowledgements Throughout this undertaking it has been my great good fortune and privilege to have the gracious and generous support of my family, supervisors and colleagues. On November 5, 2012 Professor Eric Csapo and I met for the first time. At that meeting Eric suggested the apparently paradoxical use of εὐήθεια in Ancient Greece as a postgraduate research topic. This thesis is a direct consequence of his suggestion, encouragement and forbearance. Eric’s erudition in the Classics’ disciplines is extraordinary and gives constant cause for admiration. Professor Rick Benitez is officially designated as my auxiliary supervisor. However, he has been far more that that, especially in the last year of this project when the depth of his Platonic scholarship and generous support made an invaluable contribution to the completion of this thesis. I am grateful for the opportunity to have worked closely with these exceptional scholars.
  • SECOND SAILING: Alternative Perspectives on Plato

    SECOND SAILING: Alternative Perspectives on Plato

    Commentationes Humanarum Litterarum 132 2015 SECOND SAILING: Alternative Perspectives on Plato Edited by Debra Nails and Harold Tarrant in Collaboration with Mika Kajava and Eero Salmenkivi Societas Scientiarum Fennica The Finnish Society of Sciences and Letters Commentationes Humanarun Litterarum is part of the publishing cooperation between the Finnish Society of Sciences and Letters and the Finnish Academy of Science and Letters ISSN 0069-6587 ISBN 978-951-653-409-4 Copyright © 2015 by Societas Scientiarum Fennica Layout by Maija Holappa Printed by Wellprint Oy, Espoo 2015 Contents Preface i Mika Kajava, Pauliina Remes and Eero Salmenkivi Introduction iii Harold Tarrant and Debra Nails Paradigmatic Method and Platonic Epistemology 1 Dimitri El Murr Pseudo-Archytas’ Protreptics? On Wisdom in its Contexts 21 Phillip Sidney Horky Plato and the Variety of Literary Production 41 Mauro Tulli The Meaning of Ἄπολλον‘ ... δαιμονίας ὑπερβολῆς’ in 53 Plato’s Republic 6,509b6–c4: A New Hypothesis A. Gabrièle Wersinger-Taylor Dangerous Sailing: [Plato] Second Alcibiades 147a1–4 59 Harold Tarrant Bad Luck to Take a Woman Aboard 73 Debra Nails Argument and Context: Adaption and Recasting of Positions in 91 Plato’s Dialogues Michael Erler Listening to Socrates in the Theaetetus: Recovering a Lost Narrator 107 Anne-Marie Schultz The Mask of Dialogue: On the Unity of Socrates’ Characterization in 125 Plato’s Dialogues Mario Regali Plato, Socrates, and the genei gennaia sophistikē of Sophist 231b 149 Christopher Rowe Erōs and Dialectic in Plato’s Phaedrus: 169 Questioning the Value of Chronology Francisco J. Gonzalez Changing Course in Plato Studies 187 Gerald A. Press Is the Idea of the Good Beyond Being? 197 Plato’s epekeina tēs ousias Revisited (Republic 6,509b8–10) Rafael Ferber and Gregor Damschen Like Being Nothing: Death and Anaesthesia in Plato Apology 40c 205 Rick Benitez Ideas of Good? 225 Lloyd P.
  • Culture and Society in Plato's Republic

    Culture and Society in Plato's Republic

    Culture and Society in Plato’s Republic M. F. BURNYEAT THE TANNER LECTURES ON HUMAN VALUES Delivered at Harvard University December 10-12, 1997 M. F. BURNYEAT is Senior Research Fellow in Philosophy at All Souls College, Oxford. He was educated at King’s College, Cambridge, and the University College, London. He was for many years the Laurence Professor of Ancient Philosophy at Cambridge University, and has been a visit- ing professor at numerous universities, including Harvard, Cornell, Princeton, and the University of Chicago. He is a fellow of the British Academy, the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, a member of the Institut Interna- tional de Philosophie, and a foreign honorary member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. He is the author of nearly fifty published articles, has been editor or coeditor of such volumes as Doubt and Dogmatism (1980, edited with Malcolm Schofield and Jonathan Barnes) ; The Skeptical Tradition (1983) ; and The Original Sceptics: A Controversy (1997, edited with Michael Frede). He is also the author of The Theaetetus of Plato (1990). In memoriam J. C. W. Reith ( 1889-1971)1 LECTURE I. COUCHES, SONG, AND CIVIC TRADITION THE TOTAL CULTURE: MATERIAL, MORAL, MUSICAL Imagine, if you please, a stormy night in the North Sea. It is around 3:00 A.M. The first lieutenant is on watch on the bridge, his jaw jutting out firmly to defy wind, rain, and sea. Midshipman Burnyeat, being wholly untrained in the arts of navigation and seamanship, has nothing to do but make cup after cup of the navy’s peculiarly strong recipe for cocoa.
  • The Two Supreme Principles of Plato's Cosmos—The One and The

    The Two Supreme Principles of Plato's Cosmos—The One and The

    S S symmetry Article The Two Supreme Principles of Plato’s Cosmos—the One and the Indefinite Dyad—the Division of a Straight Line into Extreme and Mean Ratio, and Pingala’s Matr¯ ameru¯ Maria Antonietta Salamone Department of Philosophy and Society, Faculty of Philosophy, Complutense University of Madrid, 28040 Madrid, Spain; salamonema@filos.ucm.es Received: 6 December 2018; Accepted: 8 January 2019; Published: 16 January 2019 Abstract: The objective of this paper is to propose a mathematical interpretation of the continuous geometric proportion (Timaeus, 32a) with which Plato accomplishes the goal to unify, harmonically and symmetrically, the Two Opposite Elements of Timaeus Cosmos—Fire and Earth—through the Mean Ratio. As we know, from the algebraic point of view, it is possible to compose a continuous geometric proportion just starting from two different quantities a (Fire) and b (Earth); their sum would be the third term, so that we would obtain the continuous geometric proportion par excellence, which carries out the agreement of opposites most perfectly: (a + b)/a = a/b. This equal proportion, applied to linear geometry, corresponds to what Euclid called the Division into Extreme and Mean Ratio (DEMR) or The Golden Proportion. In fact, according to my mathematical interpretation, in the Timaeus 32b and in the Epinomis 991 a–b, Plato uses Pingala’s Matr¯ ameru¯ or The First Analogy of the Double to mould the body of the Cosmos as a whole, to the pint of identifying the two supreme principles of the Cosmos—the One (1) and the Indefinite Dyad (F and1/F)—with the DEMR.
  • What Is Socratic About the Pseudo-Platonica?

    What Is Socratic About the Pseudo-Platonica?

    chapter 7 What Is Socratic about the Pseudo-Platonica? Mark Joyal The Socrates of the pseudo-Platonic dialogues is, we find, on the whole Socratic rather than Platonic, both in characterization and in content of thought…. [These dialogues] tend to perpetuate the ear- lier and simpler portrait; and the pseudo-Platonic field gives little or no ground for superseding the old tradition, or for enhancing the personality and expanding the doctrine of Socrates to the scale of Plato’s own achievement. Tarrant 1938, 172–3 ∵ So Dorothy Tarrant’s conclusion to her examination of the works that form the subject of this chapter. It is a confident and seductively simple conclusion, but her confidence is at least partly justified. As we shall see, the Socrates of the pseudo-Platonica shows no interest in or adherence to those doctrines which are generally considered most distinctively Platonic, in particular the Forms and Recollection (anamnesis). But against what standard did Tarrant judge the pseudo-Platonic Socrates to be “Socratic”? She does not say explicitly, but we can assume she is thinking of the character who emerges mainly from Plato’s Apology and his early, aporetic dialogues.1 Most scholars today would be much more reluctant to disengage the Socrates thus constructed from the source of evidence on which that construction is based. Yet whatever else may be said of Tarrant’s study and conclusion, she deserves credit for taking a 1 Tarrant opens her paper (1938, 167) by observing that “discussion on the Platonic Socrates in relation to the historic Socrates has to some extent subsided in recent years,” and refers to G.C.
  • PLATO (The Philosopher): USER's GUIDE

    PLATO (The Philosopher): USER's GUIDE

    PLATO (the philosopher): USER’S GUIDE (version of December 6, 2016, emended April 6, 2020) “Unless either the philosophers become kings in the cities or those who are nowadays called kings and rulers get to philosophizing truly and adequately, and this falls together upon the same person, political power and philosophy, while the many natures of those who are driven toward the one apart from the other are forcibly set aside, there will be no cessation of evils, my dear Glaucon, for cities, nor, methinks, for the human race.” Plato, République, V, 473c11-d61 “I realised that it is not only the material world that is different from the aspect in which we see it; that all reality is perhaps equally dissimilar from what we think ourselves to be directly perceiving and that we compose by means of ideas which don’t show up but are active, in the same way the trees, the sun and the sky would not be such as we see them if they were appre- hended by beings having eyes differently constituted from ours, or else en- dowed for this task with organs other than eyes which would provide equiva- lents of trees and sky and sun, though not visual.” M. Proust, The Guermantes Way, translation C. K. Scott Moncrieff revised by me (Note: a table of contents based on bookmarks is available for display on the left part of the screen in Adobe Reader) Foreword: this paper is a translation by me into English of a paper I originally wrote in French, my native tongue, under the title “Platon: mode d’emploi” (version of December 6, 2016).
  • Reading Order and Authenticity: the Place of Theages and Cleitophon in Platonic Pedagogy Autor(Es): Altman, William H

    Reading Order and Authenticity: the Place of Theages and Cleitophon in Platonic Pedagogy Autor(Es): Altman, William H

    Reading order and authenticity: the place of Theages and Cleitophon in platonic pedagogy Autor(es): Altman, William H. F. Publicado por: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra URL persistente: URI:http://hdl.handle.net/10316.2/42181 DOI: DOI:https://doi.org/10.14195/2183-4105_11_2 Accessed : 26-Sep-2021 06:46:15 A navegação consulta e descarregamento dos títulos inseridos nas Bibliotecas Digitais UC Digitalis, UC Pombalina e UC Impactum, pressupõem a aceitação plena e sem reservas dos Termos e Condições de Uso destas Bibliotecas Digitais, disponíveis em https://digitalis.uc.pt/pt-pt/termos. Conforme exposto nos referidos Termos e Condições de Uso, o descarregamento de títulos de acesso restrito requer uma licença válida de autorização devendo o utilizador aceder ao(s) documento(s) a partir de um endereço de IP da instituição detentora da supramencionada licença. Ao utilizador é apenas permitido o descarregamento para uso pessoal, pelo que o emprego do(s) título(s) descarregado(s) para outro fim, designadamente comercial, carece de autorização do respetivo autor ou editor da obra. Na medida em que todas as obras da UC Digitalis se encontram protegidas pelo Código do Direito de Autor e Direitos Conexos e demais legislação aplicável, toda a cópia, parcial ou total, deste documento, nos casos em que é legalmente admitida, deverá conter ou fazer-se acompanhar por este aviso. impactum.uc.pt digitalis.uc.pt JOURNAL DE Z 2011 ISSN 2079-7567 eISSN 2183-4105 PLATO 11 Established 1989 http://platosociety.org/ INTERNATIONAL PLATO SOCIETY PLATO INTERNATIONAL PL ATO Société Platonicienne JOURNALInternationale Associazione Internazionale dei Platonisti Sociedad Internacional de Platonistas Internationale Platon-Gesellschaft ALTMAN, William H.F., “Reading Order and Authenticity : The Place of Theages and Cleitophon in Platonic Pedagogy” READING ORDER AND AUTHENTICITY: THE PLACE OF THEAGES AND CLEITOPHON IN PLATONIC PEDAGOGY William H.F.
  • The Republic

    Leo Strauss Plato’s Republic (1957) Seminar in Political Philosophy: Plato’s Republic A course given in the spring quarter, 1957 Department of Political Science, The University of Chicago Edited and with an introduction by Peter Ahrensdorf Peter Ahrensdorf is James Sprunt Professor of Political Science and affiliated professor of classics at Davidson College. He is the author of The Death of Socrates and the Life of Philosophy: An Interpretation of Plato’s Phaedo (State University of New York Press, 1995) and other works on ancient philosophy and drama. © 1975 Joseph Cropsey © 2014 The Estate of Leo Strauss. All Rights Reserved. TABLE OF CONTENTS Editor’s Introduction i-v The Leo Strauss Transcript Project vi-vii Editorial Headnote viii Session 1: Introduction, Book I 1-18 Session 2: Book I 19-34 Session 3: Book I 35-51 Session 4: Review, Book II 52-68 Session 5: Books II, III 69-82 Session 6: Books III, IV 83-100 Session 7: Book IV 101-113 Session 8: Books IV, V 114-128 Session 9: Books V, VI, VII 129-140 Session 10: Book VII 141-155 Session 11: Book VII 156-173 Session 12: Book VIII 174-190 Session 13: Books VIII, IX 191-204 Session 14: Books IX, X 205-218 Session 15: Book X; summary points 219-221 Plato’s Republic, spring 1957 i Introduction to Leo Strauss’s 1957 Spring Seminar on Plato’s Republic Peter J. Ahrensdorf Plato’s Republic had already played a leading role in Leo Strauss’s intellectual life long before he taught his seminar on that dialogue during the spring quarter of 1957.
  • Pythagorean Plato

    Pythagorean Plato

    The Pythagorean Plato The Pythagorean Plato Prelude to the Song Itself Ernest G. McClain Nicolas-Hays, Inc. York Beach, Maine First published in 1978 by Nicolas-Hays, Inc. Box 612 York Beach, Maine 03910 First paperback edition 1984 Copyright © Ernest G. McClain ISBN 0-89254-010-9 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 77-13355 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopy, recording, or any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. Distributed by Samuel Weiser, Inc. Box 612 York Beach, Maine 03910 Printed in the United States by Mitchell-Shear, Ann Arbor, Michigan to Ernst Levy musician, philosopher, friend The consideration of which numbers are concordant and which not, and why in each case . don't we know that all of this is a prelude to the song itself, . .. the song itself that dialectic performs? (Republic 531c-532a) Contents Acknowledgements vii Charts and Tables ix 1. Introduction 1 2. The Marriage Allegory (Republic) 17 3. The Tyrant's Allegory (Republic) 33 4. The Myth of Er (Republic) 41 5. The Creation of the World-Soul (Timaeus) 57 6. Ancient Athens (Critias) 71 7. Atlantis (Critias) 77 8. Magnesia (Laws) 97 9. Plato's Musical Trigonometry 117 10. Conclusions 127 Appendices I. Historical Commentary 135 II. Conversion Tables 165 III. Tone Numbers in the Marriage Allegory 167 IV. Introduction to the Monochord 169 Footnotes 177 Index 189 Acknowledgements My book develops certain musical insights of Ernst Levy and Siegmund Levarie into Pythagoreanism in general and Plato in particular, and owes its existence to their encouragement and assistance over a period of many years.
  • Copyright by Samuel Palmer Bellows 2015

    Copyright by Samuel Palmer Bellows 2015

    Copyright by Samuel Palmer Bellows 2015 The Thesis Committee for Samuel Palmer Bellows Certifies that this is the approved version of the following thesis: On Plato’s Hipparchus APPROVED BY SUPERVISING COMMITTEE: Supervisor: Lorraine Pangle Devin Stauffer On Plato’s Hipparchus by Samuel Palmer Bellows, B.A. Thesis Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts The University of Texas at Austin December 2015 Abstract On Plato’s Hipparchus Samuel Palmer Bellows, M.A. The University of Texas at Austin, 2015 Supervisor: Lorraine Pangle The Hipparchus, Plato’s short dialogue on the love of gain, generally receives little attention from contemporary scholars. This essay, however, argues that Socrates’ brazenly amoral defense of seeking gain provides deep insights into some of the fundamental themes of Platonic political philosophy, helping to clarify the character of the human good, as well as its relation to philosophy and morality. iv Table of Contents Introduction ............................................................................................... 1 Chapter I: 225a1-226e7 ............................................................................. 8 Chapter II: 226e8-228a10 ....................................................................... 25 Chapter III: 228b1-229d7 ........................................................................ 30 Chapter IV: 229d8-232c9 .......................................................................