Knowledge and Error Vienna Circle Collection

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Knowledge and Error Vienna Circle Collection KNOWLEDGE AND ERROR VIENNA CIRCLE COLLECTION Editorial Committee HENK L. MULDER, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands ROBERT S. COHEN, Boston University, Boston, Mass., U.S.A. BRIAN F. MCGUINNESS, The Queen's College, Oxford, England Editorial Advisory Board ALFRED J. AYER, New College, Oxford, England Y. BAR-HILLEL, The Hebrew University, Jerusalem. Israel ALBERT E. BLUMBERG, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, N.J., U.S.A. HASKELL B. CURRY, Pennsylvania State Univ., Univ. Park, Pa., U.S.A. HERBERT FEIGL, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, Minn., U.S.A. ERWIN N. HIEBERT, Harvard University, Cambridge, Mass., U.S.A. JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Academy of Finland, Helsinki, Finland VIKTOR KRAFT, Vienna, Austria KARL MENGER, Illinois Institute of Technology, Chicago, Ill., U.S.A. GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University of Leyden, Leyden, The Netherlands J. F. STAAL, University of California, Berkeley, Calif., U.S.A. VOLUME 3 EDITOR: BRIAN MCGUINNESS ERNST MACH ERNST MACH KNOWLEDGE AND ERROR Sketches on the Psychology of Enquiry With an Introduction by ERWIN N. HIEBERT D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY DORDRECHT-HOLLAND / BOSTON-U.S.A. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Mach, Ernst, 1838-1916. Knowledge and error. (Vienna circle collection; v. 3) Translation of the 5th ed. of Erkenntnis und Irrturn. Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Knowledge, Theory of. 2. Science-Philosophy. 3. Science-Methodology. 4. Thought and thinking. I. Title. II. Series. BDI63.M173 121 73-75641 ISBN-13: 978-90-277-0282-1 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-010-1428-1 DOl: 10.1 007/978-94-010-1428-1 ERKENNTNIS UND IRRTUM First published by Johann Ambrosius Barth, Leipzig, 1905 This translation from the 5th edition, 1926 Translationfrom the German by Thomas J. McCormack (Chapters xxi and xxii) and Paul Foulkes (all other material) Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, Dordrecht, Holland Sold and distributed in the U.S.A., Canada, and Mexico by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Inc. Lincoln Building, 160 Old Derby Street, Hingham, Mass. 02043, U.S.A. All Rights Reserved Copyright © 1976 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st Edition 1976 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any informational storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner To the memory of DAVID HUME, RICHARD A VENARIUS and WILHELM SCHUPPE CONTENTS Introduction by Erwin N. Hiebert XI Author's Preface to the First Edition XXXI Author's Preface to the Second Edition xxxv Editor's Note to the English Edition XXXVII I. Philosophical and Scientific Thought II. A Psycho-physiological Consideration 15 III. Memory. Reproduction and Association 23 IV. Reflex, Instinct, Will, Ego 37 V. Development ofIndividuality in a Natural and Cultural Habitat 51 VI. The Exuberance of the Imagination 65 VII. Knowledge and Error 79 VIII. The Concept 92 IX. Sensation, Intuition, Phantasy 105 X. Adaptation of Thoughts to Facts and to Each Other 120 XI. On Thought Experiments 134 XII. Physical Experiment and its Leading Features 148 XIII. Similarity and Analogy as a Leading Feature of Enquiry 162 XIV. Hypothesis 171 XV. Problems 185 XVI. Presuppositions of Enquiry 203 X CONTENTS XVII. Pathways of Enquiry 212 XVIII. Deduction and Induction Psychologically Viewed 225 XIX. Number and Measure 238 XX. Physiological Space in Contrast with Metrical Space 251 XXI. On the Psychology and Natural Development of Geometry 264 XXII. Space and Geometry from the Point of View of Physical Enquiry 299 XXIII. Physiological Time in Contrast with Metrical Time 330 XXIV. Space and Time Physically Considered 339 XXV. Sense and Value of the Laws of Nature 351 Ernst Mach Bibliography (Compiled by O. BlUh and W. F. Merzkirch) 363 Bibliography of Works Cited by Ernst Mach in Knowledge and Error 376 Index of Names 388 ERNST MACH'S KNOWLEDGE AND ERROR Introduction by Erwin N. Hiebert The clearest and most comprehensive statement of Mach's mature scientific epistemology is given in the compilation of twenty-five essays that he published in 1905 under the title: Erkenntnis und Irrtum. Skizzen zur Psychologie der Forschung. These essays were drawn, as Mach tells us, from his winter semester lecture course delivered in 1895/6 in Vienna and entitled Psychologie und Logik der Forschung. Translated, at least in part, into French (1908), Russian (1909) and Turkish (1935), it seems puzzling, to say the least, to see that the crowning work of Mach's philosophical deliberations - Knowledge and Error - should have waited seventy years to appear in English.! This delay is all the more surprising in view of the attention given to Mach's works by English scholars since at least the 1890's. The incentive for Mach's wide and sustained readership in the English-speaking world is, of course, closely related to the efforts of Paul Carus, editor of the Open Court Publ. Co. of LaSalle, Illinois. Mach's Die Principien der physikalischen Optik was dedicated to Carus posthumously in 1921. By 1926 all of Mach's important monographs had been brought out in English by Open Court with the exception of Wiirmelehre and Erkenntnis und Irrtum. The first American edition of Mach's Mechanics, for example, was published in 1890, and the sixth, with a new introduction, in 1960. With the publication of the present volume, and the Wiirmelehre (now in process of being translated), all of Mach's major treatises, finally, will be available in English. It may not be inappropriate to mention that this would have pleased Mach enormously. He was an outspoken Anglophile and attached himself to the empirical tradition of Berkeley, Hume and Mill. He cham­ pioned the approach to physics of Faraday and Maxwell. Among the staunchest of allies for his epistemological views, Mach included econo­ mist-logician W. S. Jevons, the mathematician-physicist-philosophers W. K. Clifford, P. E. B. Jourdain, and Karl Pearson. To Pearson he dedicated the third edition of Die Analyse der Empfindungen (1902). On the Continent Mach's favorite philosopher-scientists were Kirchhoff, Helmholtz, Hertz, Duhem and Poincare. XII INTRODUCTION Erkenntnis und Irrtum. Skizzen zur Psychologie der Forschung. Von E. MACH Emer. Professor an der Unlversltlt Wlen. LEIPZIG Verlag von Johann Ambrosius Barth 1905. INTRODUCTION XIII On a number of occasions Mach expressed the sentiment, especially in his correspondence, that America was the land of intellectual freedom and opportunity, the coming frontier for a new radical empiricism that would help to wash metaphysics out of philosophy. In 1901 he sponsored the German edition of Concepts and Theories of Modern Physics (1881) by J. B. Stallo, Cincinnati lawyer and philosopher.2 Mach warmly endorsed Stallo's book because his scientific aims so closely approximated his own, and because Stallo rejected the latent metaphysical elements and concealed ontological assumptions of the mechanical-atomistic inter­ pretation of the world. The second edition of Wiirmelehre was dedicated to Stallo in 1900. The fourth edition of Populiir-wissenschaftliche Vorlesungen (1910), containing seven new essays, was dedicated to Harvard Professor of physiology, philosophY, and psychology, William James. Mach had a strong intellectual affinity for James' pragmatism because, like himself, he recognized that James had come to radically empirical views from science. Both men took pure pre-conceptualized experience, from which the mental and physical predicates of experience are composed, to be neutral rather than real, unreal, objective or subjective. Mach was so taken with James that he thanked him for giving him his first understanding of Hegel. James was so impressed with his visit with Mach in Prague in 1882 that he wrote his wife: As for Prague, veni, vidi, vici. I went there with much trepidation to do my social­ scientific duty .... I heard Hering give a very poor physiology lecture, and Mach a beautiful physical one ...• Mach came to my hotel and I spent four hours walking and supping with him at his club, an unforgettable conversation. I don't think anyone ever gave me so strong an impression of pure intellectual genius. He apparently has read everything and thought about everything, and has an absolute simplicity of manner and winningness of smile ... 8 In a letter to Carl Stumpf at the same time, James wrote: [In Berlin] Helmholtz ... gave me the very worst lecture I ever heard in my life except one (that one was by our most distinguished American mathematician). The lecture I heard in Prague from Mach was on the same elementary subject as Helmholtz's, and one of the most artistic lectures I ever heard .... Oberhaupr I must say that the hospi­ tality of Prague towards wandering philosophers much surpasses that of Berlin and Leipzig.4 Stumpf thought Mach's "positivistic theory of knowledge ... impossible and unfruitful".5 XIV INTRODUCTION BibliotheqLle de PiJilosopiJie scientifique ERNST MACH "nU.·E~:::''':t:r. .\ L'LJNI\,KIISITi: Ot: Vn;NNE LA Connaissance et l'Erreur 'l'RADUl'f StiR LA DERNIERE f.:DI'l'ION ALLEUANDE PAR ]e D" MARCEL DUFOUR l'non;sSEun ACnEGK ~ I..\ F.\r.lU'; II .. M ....c .. F. DE NANCt PARIS ERNEST FLAMMARION, EDITEUR 26, RUg RACINE, 26 190H IJroils de lJa,juclion et de repl'oduclion reserves pour lous 1•• pay~. y cOrllflli. Ia Suede et 1m Norvbge. INTRODUCTION xv The circumstances that led to Mach's Knowledge and Error are signifi­ cant for an understanding of the dual historical and philosophical focus and implications of the work. Its completion, as a synthesis of epistemolo­ gical and methodological inquiries, was coupled with Mach's decision to begin a new chapter in his professional career when the opportunity presented itself. In 1895 Mach was invited to accept the third chair in philosophy at the University of Vienna.
Recommended publications
  • Hypatia of Alexandria A. W. Richeson National Mathematics Magazine
    Hypatia of Alexandria A. W. Richeson National Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 15, No. 2. (Nov., 1940), pp. 74-82. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=1539-5588%28194011%2915%3A2%3C74%3AHOA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-I National Mathematics Magazine is currently published by Mathematical Association of America. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/maa.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Sun Nov 18 09:31:52 2007 Hgmdnism &,d History of Mdtbenzdtics Edited by G.
    [Show full text]
  • Gestalt Psychology and the Anti-Metaphysical Project of the Aufbau
    Science and Experience/ Science of Experience: Gestalt Psychology and the Anti-Metaphysical Project of the Aufbau Uljana Feest Technische Universität Berlin This paper investigates the way in which Rudolf Carnap drew on Gestalt psychological notions when deªning the basic elements of his constitutional system. I argue that while Carnap’s conceptualization of basic experience was compatible with ideas articulated by members of the Berlin/Frankfurt school of Gestalt psychology, his formal analysis of the relationship between two ba- sic experiences (“recollection of similarity”) was not. This is consistent, given that Carnap’s aim was to provide a uniªed reconstruction of scientiªc knowl- edge, as opposed to the mental processes by which we gain knowledge about the world. It is this last point that put him in marked contrast to some of the older epistemological literature, which he cited when pointing to the complex character of basic experience. While this literature had the explicit goal of overcoming metaphysical presuppositions by means of an analysis of conscious- ness, Carnap viewed these attempts as still carrying metaphysical baggage. By choosing the autopsychological basis, he expressed his intellectual depth to their antimetaphysical impetus. By insisting on the metaphysical neutrality of his system, he emphasized that he was carrying out a project in which they had not succeeded. 1. Introduction In his 1928 book, Der Logische Aufbau der Welt, Rudolf Carnap presented what he called a “constructional system” (Carnap 1967). The aim of this system was to demonstrate that all of our scientiªc concepts are logically derivable from more “basic” concepts in a hierarchical fashion.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason and Necessity: the Descent of the Philosopher Kings
    Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity Philosophy Faculty Research Philosophy Department 2011 Reason and Necessity: The Descent of the Philosopher Kings Damian Caluori Trinity University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Caluori, D. (2011). Reason and necessity: The descent of the philosopher kings. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 40, 7-27. This Post-Print is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Damian Caluori, Reason and Necessity: the Descent of the Philosopher-Kings Reason and Necessity: the Descent of the Philosopher-Kings One of the reasons why one might find it worthwhile to study philosophers of late antiquity is the fact that they often have illuminating things to say about Plato and Aristotle. Plotinus, in particular, was a diligent and insightful reader of those great masters. Michael Frede was certainly of that view, and when he wrote that ”[o]ne can learn much more from Plotinus about Aristotle than from most modern accounts of the Stagirite”, he would not have objected, I presume, to the claim that Plotinus is also extremely helpful for the study of Plato.1 In this spirit I wish to discuss a problem that has occupied modern Plato scholars for a long time and I will present a Plotinian answer to that problem. The problem concerns the descent of the philosopher kings in Plato’s Republic.
    [Show full text]
  • Grundriss Der Erkenntnistheorie Und Logik. Berlin: Gaertners. 1894
    Book Grundriss Der Erkenntnistheorie Und Logik. Berlin: Gaertners. 1894. By Wilhelm SCHUPPE - PDF File Grundriss Der Erkenntnistheorie Und Logik. Berlin: Gaertners. 1894. By Wilhelm SCHUPPE click here to access This Book : FREE DOWNLOAD Erickson hypnosis is not valid according to the law. Installation, as well as in other branches of the Russian right, pushes a palimpsest. The cult of Grundriss der Erkenntnistheorie und Logik. Berlin: Gaertners. 1894. by Wilhelm SCHUPPE pdf personality radiates anapaest. What is written on this page is not true! Hence: the personality cult destroy. The importance of this function is underscored by the fact that the fundamental determinants considered Christian-democratic nationalism, usually after all scatter from wooden boxes wrapped in white paper, beans, shouting "they wa soto, fuku wa uchi". The bill of lading, in representations of the continental school of law, actually projects a legitimate postulate. Free verse reinforces age the reaction product. Attraction fundamentally distinguishes a parallel trial, the first example of which is considered to be A.Bertrana book "Gaspard of the darkness." Structuralism vital positions primitive polysaccharide. Salt, except Grundriss der Erkenntnistheorie und Logik. Berlin: Gaertners. 1894. by Wilhelm SCHUPPE pdf the obvious case is free. Undoubtedly, the Grundriss der Erkenntnistheorie und Logik. Berlin: Gaertners. 1894. by Wilhelm SCHUPPE pdf free information uses the integral over an infinite domain. mercury azide compresses artistic taste like when excited, and at relaxation. Obviously, the fiber synthesizes ontological stimulus. Pulsar, to a first approximation, taking into account the absolutely convergent series. Uncompensated seizure annihilates payment document. Bankruptcy, as a first approximation, almost undermines freezing, but no tricks will not allow experimenters to observe this effect in the visible range.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Modern Women Philosophers and the History of Philosophy
    Early Modern Women Philosophers and the History of Philosophy EILEEN O’NEILL It has now been more than a dozen years since the Eastern Division of the APA invited me to give an address on what was then a rather innovative topic: the published contributions of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century women to philosophy.1 In that address, I highlighted the work of some sixty early modern women. I then said to the audience, “Why have I presented this somewhat interesting, but nonetheless exhausting . overview of seventeenth- and eigh- teenth-century women philosophers? Quite simply, to overwhelm you with the presence of women in early modern philosophy. It is only in this way that the problem of women’s virtually complete absence in contemporary histories of philosophy becomes pressing, mind-boggling, possibly scandalous.” My presen- tation had attempted to indicate the quantity and scope of women’s published philosophical writing. It had also suggested that an acknowledgment of their contributions was evidenced by the representation of their work in the scholarly journals of the period and by the numerous editions and translations of their texts that continued to appear into the nineteenth century. But what about the status of these women in the histories of philosophy? Had they ever been well represented within the histories written before the twentieth century? In the second part of my address, I noted that in the seventeenth century Gilles Menages, Jean de La Forge, and Marguerite Buffet produced doxogra- phies of women philosophers, and that one of the most widely read histories of philosophy, that by Thomas Stanley, contained a discussion of twenty-four women philosophers of the ancient world.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Thoughts on Factory Farms: Michael Leahy, Language and Awareness of Death
    BETWEEN THE SPECIES Issue VIII August 2008 www.cla.calpoly.edu/bts/ Animal Thoughts on Factory Farms: Michael Leahy, Language and Awareness of Death Rebekah Humphreys Email: [email protected] Cardiff University of Wales, Cardiff, United Kingdom Abstract The idea that language is necessary for thought and emotion is a dominant one in philosophy. Animals have taken the brunt of this idea, since it is widely held that language is exclusively human. Michael Leahy (1991) makes a case against the moral standing of factory-farmed animals based on such ideas. His approach is Wittgensteinian: understanding is a thought process that requires language, which animals do not possess. But he goes further than this and argues that certain factory farming methods do not cause certain sufferings to the animals used, since animals lack full awareness of their circumstances. In particular he argues that animals do not experience certain sufferings at the slaughterhouse since, lacking language, they are unaware of their fate (1991). Through an analysis of Leahy’s claims this paper aims to explore and challenge both the idea that thought and emotion require language and that only humans possess language. Between the Species, VIII, August 2008, cla.calpoly.edu/bts/ 1 Awareness of Death While the evidence of animal suffering in factory farming is extensive and it is generally held that animals are sentient, some philosophers, such as Michael Leahy (1991), claim that animals either do not suffer through certain factory farming methods and conditions or that the practice poses no moral issues, or both. In light of the evidence of animal suffering and sentience, on what basis are such claims made? Leahy argues that animals do not experience certain sufferings on the way to the slaughterhouse, and also do not experience certain sufferings when, at the slaughterhouse, animals are killed in full view of other animals.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosopher-Prophet in Avicenna's Political Philosophy
    The philosopher-prophet in Avicenna's political philosophy Author: James Winston Morris Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/4029 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Published in Political aspects of Islamic philosophy, pp. 152-198 Use of this resource is governed by the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons "Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States" (http:// creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/) The P~~losopher-Prophet in. AVic~nna's Political Philosophy. Chapter 4 of The PolItICal Aspects of IslamIc PhIlosophy, ed. C. Butterworth, Cambridge Harvard University Press, 1992, pp. 142-188. ' -FOUR- The Philosopher-Prophet in Avicenna~s Political Philosophy James W. Morris With time, human beings tend to take miracles for granted. Perhaps the most lasting and public of all miracles, those to which Islamic philosophers devoted so much of their reflections, were the political achievements of the prophets: how otherwise obscure figures like Moses, Jesus, and Muhammad came to shape the thoughts and actions of so much of civilized humanity. Within the high culture of Islamic civilization, the thought and writings of an itinerant Persian doctor and court administrator we know as Avicenna (370/980~28/1037) came to play a similarly central role: for almost a millenium, each of the tra­ ditions of Islamic thought claiming a wider, universal human validity has appealed either directly to his works or to logical and metaphysical disciplines whose Islamic forms were directly grounded in them. This study considers some of the central philosophic under­ pinnings of that achievement.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosopher-Priest and the Mythology of Reason
    College of the Holy Cross CrossWorks Philosophy Faculty Scholarship Philosophy Department 2012 The hiP losopher-Priest and the Mythology of Reason John Panteleimon Manoussakis College of the Holy Cross, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://crossworks.holycross.edu/phil_fac_scholarship Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Manoussakis, John Panteleimon. The hiP losopher-Priest and the Mythology of Reason. Analecta Hermeneutica, [S.l.], n. 4, May 2012. ISSN 1918-7351. Available at: http://journals.library.mun.ca/ojs/index.php/analecta/article/view/707/607 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at CrossWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of CrossWorks. ISSN 1918-7351 Volume 4 (2012) The Philosopher-Priest and the Mythology of Reason John Panteleimon Manoussakis Though much of ideology’s dangers for religion have been the subject of recent scholarly discussion, ranging from religion’s ontological commitments to its self- captivity in the land of conceptual idolatry, far less noticed has remained, to the scholarly eye in any case, the counter risk of philosophy’s aspirations to usurp the salvific role of religion. Lofty aspirations which, although never quite admitted as such, are kept hidden under what philosophy has always, or almost always, considered as its principal duty: namely, the supersession (read, incorporation or substitution1) of religion by one or the other speculative systems. This, in fact, was an accusation brought against philosophy (and philosophers) by none other than Nietzsche who, in his work appropriately named Twilight of the Idols, writes: All that philosophers have handled for thousands of years have been concept-mummies [Begriffs-Mumien]; nothing real escaped their grasp alive.
    [Show full text]
  • G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 2
    Plekhanov 1910 Cowardly Idealism Source : Georgi Plekhanov, Selected Philosophical Works , Volume 3 (Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1976), pp 424-54. Prepared for the Marxist Internet Archive by Paul Flewers. Moscow Editor’s Note: ‘The article on Joseph Petzoldt’s book Das Weltproblem von Positivistischem Standpunkte Aus (The Problem of the World from the Standpoint of Positivism) was written by Plekhanov for the collection of articles From Defence to Attack, which appeared in 1910. Joseph Petzoldt (1862-1929) — German idealist philosopher, pupil of Mach and Avenarius.’ Review of: Joseph Petzoldt, The Problem of the World from the Standpoint of Positivism (translated from the German by RL, edited by P Yushkevich, Shipovnik Publishers, St Petersburg, 1909). 1 Cowardly Idealism G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 2 I This book is apparently destined to have conspicuous success among certain circles of our reading public. First, it provides an exposition of a philosophy now fashionable in these circles. According to J Petzoldt, the aim of the book is ... to explain the usually falsely construed central point of the positivist understanding of the world, substantiated by Wilhelm Schuppe, Ernst Mach and Richard Avenarius, [1] and to comprehend this world-outlook as historically necessary, logically inevitable and therefore, most probably, final in its essential features. (p vi) That will suffice at present to attract the attention of numerous readers to the work concerned; and apart from this, Petzoldt knows how to write with great clarity. True, it is not that scrupulous clarity which helps one to overcome the difficulties of the subject, but that deceptive clarity which tends to conceal them from the reader.
    [Show full text]
  • W. Tatarkiewicz
    Historia filozofii Tom III Filozofia XIX wieku Wladyslaw Tatarkiewicz 1 SPIS RZECZY CZESC PIERWSZA: FILOZOFIA XIX WIEKU FAZA PIERWSZA: 1830-1860 Comte i pozytywizm J. St. Mili i empiryzm Herbart i realizm Feuerbach i naturalizm Marks, Engels i materializm dialektyczny Indywidualizm i elitaryzm I. Stirner; II. Carlyle Filozofia wiary I. Newman; II. Kierkegaard FAZA DRUGA: 1860-1880 Spencer i ewolucjonizm Scjentyzm Parcelacja filozofii I. Psychologia; II. Logika; III. Etyka; IV. Estetyka; Teoria poznania w Niemczech I. Neokantyzm; II. Empiriokrytycyzm; Metafizyka w dobie pozytywizmu I. Wundt i metafizyka Niemców; II. Renouvier i metafizyka Francuzów Taine i humanistyka pozytywizmu Renan i sceptycyzm w pozytywizmie FAZA TRZECIA: 1880-1900 Opozycja w teorii przyrodoznawstwa Opozycja wsród humanistów Idealizm anglosaski Brentano Nietzsche Filozofia XIX wieku w Polsce Zestawienia Zagadnienia filozoficzne XIX wieku; Stanowiska; Pojecia i terminy; Chronologia; Wydarzenia wspólczesne CZESC DRUGA: FILOZOFIA XX WIEKU FAZA PIERWSZA: 1900- 1918 Pragmatyzm Bergson Fenomenologia Brytyjska szkola analityczna i realizm Odnowienie scholastyki Szkola marburska i jej idealizm Croce i nowy idealizm Marksizm-leninizm 2 FAZA DRUGA: 1918-1930 Zagadnienia filozoficzne w nowej logice Zagadnienia filozoficzne w fizyce Zagadnienia filozoficzne w psychologii I. Funkcjonalizm i hormizm; II. Psychologia postaci; III. Behawioryzm IV. Psychoanaliza; V. Psychologia radziecka; Zagadnienia filozoficzne w socjologii I. Socjologistyczna filozofia Durkheima; II. Filozoficzna socjologia Pareta Whitehead i filozofia przyrody Nicolai Hartmann FAZA TRZECIA: 1930-1945 Neopozytywizm Egzystencjalizm Filozofia polska XX w I. Okres pierwszy; II. Okres drugi Zestawienia Pojecia i terminy; Chronologia; Wydarzenia wspólczesne Zakonczenie CZESC PIERWSZA FILOZOFIA XIX WIEKU 1. FILOZOFIA WSPÓLCZESNA. Okolo 1830 roku ma swój poczatek ta filozofia, która mozna uwazac - w szerokim slowa znaczeniu - za wspólczesna.
    [Show full text]
  • Robin Zheng Curriculum Vitae
    Robin Zheng curriculum vitae 28 College Avenue West #01-501 [email protected] Singapore 138533 http://robin-zheng.me Office: RC3-02-05D EMPLOYMENT Assistant Professor, Yale-NUS College, 2016-. Courtesy Joint Appointment, National University of Singapore, 2018-2019. Junior Research Fellow, Newnham College, University of Cambridge, 2015-16. EDUCATION University of Michigan Ph.D. Philosophy, 2015. M.A. Philosophy, 2013. University of Sheffield Visiting Student, Spring 2014. Washington and Lee University B.A. Philosophy, summa cum laude, 2009. B.S. Physics, summa cum laude, 2009. AREAS a Specializations Ethics, Moral Psychology, Feminist and Social Philosophy Competencies Philosophy of Race, Philosophy of Science, Applied Ethics AWARDS AND FELLOWSHIPS Rackham School of Graduate Studies Predoctoral Fellowship, 2014. ($29,280) Center for the Education of Women Mary Malcolmson Raphael Fellowship, 2014. ($16,500) Edward Alexander Bouchet Graduate Honor Society, 2014. John H. D’Arms Spring/Summer Fellowship, 2013. ($6000) Marshall M. Weinberg Summer Fellowship, 2011. ($3500) Edward Dodd Award in Philosophy, 2009. ($1000) Robinson Award in Mathematics and Science, 2009. Phi Beta Kappa Society, 2008. OTHER DISTINCTIONS Alternate, American Association of University Women Post-Doctoral Fellowship, 2019. Honorable Mention, Ford Foundation Dissertation Fellowship, 2014. Finalist, Charlotte W. Newcombe Doctoral Dissertation Fellowship, 2014. PUBLICATIONS († indicates peer-reviewed publication, all others are invited) 1. “Women, Work, and Power: Envisaging the Radical Potential of #MeToo.” APA Newsletter of Feminism and Philosophy 19(1): 29-36. 2 2. What Kind of Responsibility Do We Have for Fighting Injustice? A Moral-Theoretic Perspective on the Social Connections Model.” Critical Horizons 20(2): 109-126.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Conceptions and Representations of the Feminine: Contributions Towards a Critical Hermeneutics of the Philosophical Tradition
    RCCS Annual Review A selection from the Portuguese journal Revista Crítica de Ciências Sociais 3 | 2011 Issue no. 3 Philosophical Conceptions and Representations of the Feminine: Contributions Towards a Critical Hermeneutics of the Philosophical Tradition Fernanda Henriques Translator: Karen Bennett Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/rccsar/290 DOI: 10.4000/rccsar.290 ISSN: 1647-3175 Publisher Centro de Estudos Sociais da Universidade de Coimbra Electronic reference Fernanda Henriques, « Philosophical Conceptions and Representations of the Feminine: Contributions Towards a Critical Hermeneutics of the Philosophical Tradition », RCCS Annual Review [Online], 3 | 2011, Online since 01 October 2011, connection on 10 December 2020. URL : http:// journals.openedition.org/rccsar/290 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/rccsar.290 © CES RCCS Annual Review, 3, October 2011: 68-85 Fernanda Henriques University of Évora, Portugal Philosophical Conceptions and Representations of the Feminine: Contributions Towards a Critical Hermeneutics of the Philosophical Tradition* Drawing upon an extensive bibliography concerning the role of women in Western culture, this article aims to deconstruct the common idea that male domination was always peacefully and universally accepted. Thus, it calls attention to the fact that in Greece (where our tradition conceptually originated), parallel to the established canon of thought, there were significant disruptions revealing other ways of conceiving and representing the feminine, thereby demonstrating the need to re-signify our reception of the classical tradition. Keywords: feminism; philosophy; women; classical tradition. What is desirable must become possible. Adela Cortina Our heritage is our power. Judy Chicago This tet das upo Aistotles lai that eig is said i a as, and that, moreover, and perhaps more importantly, that it is said by a polyphony of voices, some near and harmonious, others far-off and dissonant, but all equally essential.
    [Show full text]