Empathy, Open-Mindedness and Virtue in Argumentation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Empathy, Open-Mindedness and Virtue in Argumentation UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Santa Barbara Empathy, Open-Mindedness and Virtue in Argumentation A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Jonathan Anthony Caravello Committee in charge: Professor Aaron Zimmerman, Chair Professor Kevin Falvey Professor Voula Tsouna June 2018 The dissertation of Jonathan Anthony Caravello is approved. ________________________________________________ Voula Tsouna ________________________________________________ Kevin Falvey ________________________________________________ Aaron Zimmerman Committee Chair June 2018 ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Writing a dissertation took a significant psychological toll on me, but I would be lying if I said that the burden was my own. I would like to thank every person who helped me in developing my thoughts and supporting me throughout this endeavor. Since a young age I have been interested in argument (just ask my Mom), which lead me to pursue what I considered to be the deeper questions about the world. I entered college at ASU with the hope of becoming a theoretical astrophysicist. But there were two factors that turned me off once I began my studies. First, I was not pleased with the culture of the discipline. Too often would professors wave off my questions as irrelevant to learning the techniques being taught. “Once you master these techniques,” they would say, “you will be in a better place and you will better understand why I cannot answer your questions.” Although there is some truth to what they said, I realized later that the reason my questions seemed out of place was because they were philosophical in nature. There were exceptions: Dr. Treacy and Dr. Lebed helped me immensely. Second, my fellow peers suffered from a deep and misguided close-mindedness concerning philosophical concerns. This, for me, was a breaking point. How could I investigate the deepest questions about the world when the space I occupied was full of stubborn interlocutors? Again, there were exceptions: Katie and Lauren, to be specific. Now, don’t get me wrong, there is plenty of stubbornness in philosophy as well. But at the very least, philosophers seemed to be directing their attention toward what really mattered and their practice reflected this. Unlike in my experience in physics, philosophers didn’t stubbornly laugh at my concerns, even if they often stubbornly criticized them. Sometimes that stubborn criticism is exactly what I needed – thanks Thad Botham! – but acceptance and understanding were and continue to be what I need. Thad was not only critical, he was understanding and a huge reason why I was accepted into the PhD program at UCSB. Others that were of immense help at ASU, include professors Cheshire Calhoun, Stephen Reynolds, Brad Armendt, and Angel Pinilos, and my fellow classmate Zach Horne. Thank you also to Travis and Jenni for being model graduate students for me, giving me a taste of what was to come. Thanks to my high school teacher Mr. Schiesser and junior high teacher Ms. Eddy, who shone through the bullshit as beacons of hope. Thank you Aaron Zimmerman for being my mentor and my friend. Thank you Tony Brueckner for showing me how philosophy doesn’t have to be stressful to be impactful. Thank you Kevin Falvey for entertaining some of my wilder ideas. Thank you Voula Tsouna for reminding me that there’s more to life than academic philosophy. Thank you Tony Anderson, Sonny Elizondo, Nathan Salmon, Teresa Robertson, Dan Korman, Michael Rescorla, Chris McMahon, Matthew Hanser, Tom Holden, and any others I’m forgetting for being welcoming and giving me space to grow as a thinker and philosopher. Thank you to my partner, Sarah Aspell, who has been my foundation when the floor beneath me was moving. She has somehow cut through the tangled mess of mind to swing me into a more peaceful side of myself. Thank you to my family and friends who put up with my philosophical tinkering for so long: my mom Dolores, my uncle Pat, my twin brother Pat, my older brother Mike, his kids Mikey and Abby, my older sister Carina and her husband John, their kids John, Cali, Dominick, and Brooklyn. Thank you most of all to my fellow graduate students, who I could not have lived without. Dillon: thank you for opening up and being my partner in philosophy for so long. I learned more through talking to you than I have from anything else in my entire life. Our bond is limitless, even when we disagree. Thank you Jason, Tim, Matt, David, Kyle, Daniel, Sherri, Jenna, Julianna, Jeongyu, Alex, Alex, Josh, Phil, Jenessa, Austin, Matt Peterson, Brian, CC, Jason, Jason, Augi, Damien, Blake, Zach, Dan, Keith, Rick, Rob, David Spewak, and any others I’ve missed. I dedicate this dissertation to anyone and everyone who has ever felt isolated from the world, from others, or from themselves . iii VITA OF JONATHAN ANTHONY CARAVELLO Month 2018 Areas of Specialization Epistemology, Ethics (broadly construed) Areas of Competence: Action Theory, Critical Thinking, Moral Psychology Education University of California Santa Barbara 2010-Present • M.A. 2014 • Ph.D. 2018 Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona: B.A. in Philosophy 2010 Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona: B.A. in Physics 2010 Dissertation Empathy, Open-Mindedness and Virtue in Argumentation How should we respond when someone challenges the very norms we assume when evaluating arguments? I contest a widely-accepted dogmatist answer according to which we can justly assert or rely on foundational norms or principles even when we know our interlocutors reject them. I go on to develop a virtue-theoretic approach to argumentation, highlighting the central role played by open-mindedness and related virtues in distinguishing good from bad arguments. The resulting theory elucidates the pragmatic nature of argumentative circularity, offers normative guidance for those looking to improve their discursive behavior, and makes some progress towards resolving ongoing debates over the proper response to peer disagreement. Committee: Aaron Zimmerman (chair), Kevin Falvey, and Voula Tsouna Awards and Honors UCHRI Multi-Campus Graduate Working Group Award 2016 - 2017 UCSB Dissertation (Diversity) Fellowship 2015 - 2016 Aida and Philip Siff Award for Best Essay 2015 - 2016 UCHRI Multi-Campus Graduate Working Group Award 2015 - 2016 SIOP Grant 2015 Steven L. Humphrey Fellowship, University of California Santa Barbara 2010 - 2011 Teaching Experience Instructorships and Adjunct Faculty Positions: (University of California Santa Barbara): Designed syllabi, exams and assignments for both lower and upper division courses, consisting of approximately 50-240 students; conducted 2-3 lectures per week; held office hours; maintained course website; supervised 1-4 teaching assistants. • THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE • CRITICAL THINKING • INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY • WRITING 2: ACADEMIC WRITING (25 students, no teaching assistants) iv Teaching Assistantships: (University of California Santa Barbara) Conducted two discussion sections per week for 50-70 lower and upper division students; held office hours; led review sessions; graded assignments and exams. • Philosophy of Mind (Winter 2014) • Metaphysics (Spring 2011) • Intro to Philosophy(Winter2013) • Theory of Knowledge (Winter 2011) • Philosophy of Religion (Fall 2012) • Introduction to Ethics (Fall 2010) • Philosophy of Mind (Spring 2012) • Philosophy of Mind (Summer 2010) • Theory of Knowledge (Winter 2012) • Critical Thinking (Spring 2010) • Introduction to Ethics (Fall 2011) • Introduction to Ethics (Winter 2010) • Theory of Knowledge (Summer 2011) • Introduction to Philosophy (Fall 2013) Graduate Courses *Indicates Audited Courses University of California Santa Barbara 2010-Present Topics in Philosophy of Mind | Rescorla Historical Philosophers | Zimmerman Hellenistic Philosophy | Tsouna *Seminar in Epistemology | Brueckner Seminar in Epistemology | Zimmerman *Seminar in Philosophy of Language | Salmon Philosophy of Space and Time | Humphrey *Seminar in Epistemology | Brueckner Intermediate Symbolic Logic | Anderson *Topics in Theory of Knowledge | Rescorla Seminar in Epistemology | Brueckner *Seminar in Philosophy of Language | Salmon Contemporary Philosophy | Salmon *Seminar in History of Philosophy | Tsouna Seminar on Hume | Holden *Seminar in Philosophy of Language | Meta-Ethics | Hanser Rescorla Seminar in Philosophy of Mind | Falvey *Seminar in Philosophy of Mind | Falvey Meaning and Reference | Salmon *Seminar in Philosophy of Mind | Rescorla Seminar in Ethics | Hanser *Seminar in Epistemology | Zimmerman Arizona State University 2006-2010 Seminar in Philosophy of Emotion | Cheshire Calhoun v ABSTRACT Empathy, Open-Mindedness and Virtue in Argumentation by Jonathan Anthony Caravello Disagreements continue over the most basic epistemic questions. Which logic is correct? What makes an argument good? We need a theory that can both explain the prevalence of such disagreements and evaluate the conduct and characters of those who participate in them. I argue that formal theories cannot supply this need. Circular arguments demonstrate the failure of formal approaches. Circular arguments are often impeccable from a formal perspective, but circular argumentation is almost always criticizable. A skilled arguer does not dismiss other viewpoints out of hand. Instead, to reason with those who reject our most basic assumptions about the logic of argumentation itself or the norms we assume when evaluating arguments for cogency or coherence we must break out of
Recommended publications
  • The Intrinsic Probability of Grand Explanatory Theories
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 37 Issue 4 Article 3 10-1-2020 The Intrinsic Probability of Grand Explanatory Theories Ted Poston Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Poston, Ted (2020) "The Intrinsic Probability of Grand Explanatory Theories," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 37 : Iss. 4 , Article 3. DOI: 10.37977/faithphil.2020.37.4.3 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol37/iss4/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. applyparastyle "fig//caption/p[1]" parastyle "FigCapt" applyparastyle "fig" parastyle "Figure" AQ1–AQ5 THE INTRINSIC PROBABILITY OF GRAND EXPLANATORY THEORIES Ted Poston This paper articulates a way to ground a relatively high prior probability for grand explanatory theories apart from an appeal to simplicity. I explore the possibility of enumerating the space of plausible grand theories of the universe by using the explanatory properties of possible views to limit the number of plausible theories. I motivate this alternative grounding by showing that Swinburne’s appeal to simplicity is problematic along several dimensions. I then argue that there are three plausible grand views—theism, atheism, and axiarchism—which satisfy explanatory requirements for plau- sibility. Other possible views lack the explanatory virtue of these three theo- ries. Consequently, this explanatory grounding provides a way of securing a nontrivial prior probability for theism, atheism, and axiarchism.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidential Relevance and the Grue Paradox
    科 学 哲 学31-1(1998) Evidential Relevance and the Grue Paradox Robert T. Pennock Philosophy Department The University of Texas at Austin Abstract Goodman's Grue Paradox may be intransigent as a version of the problem of induction, but may be resolved within the more lim ited context of confirmation theory in which the task is to explicate the basic notion of evidential relevance. Although the green and grue hypotheses are equivalently confirmed if we follow Goodman's use of the Hempelian instance confirmation relation, there are asym metries than can be exploited if we adopt an "ontic" confirmation theory that uses a causal notion of evidential relevance. I sort out a variety of interpretive confusions about the intended content of the definition of grue and show how the causal approach resolves each in a way that is not paradoxical. 1. Introduction If we are to make progress in confirmation theory, we must distinguish local problems having to do with the nature of evidence from the global problem of induction. Nelson Goodman posed the Grue Paradox as "The New Riddle of In- duction," but his presentation set up the problem within a Hempelian model of confirmation. In what follows I do not address the aspect of the paradox that participates in the old problem of induction but focus upon the aspect that deals with the explication of the confirmation relation, that is, the relation having to do with what counts as evidence of what. In •˜2-•˜5 1 highlight features of the para- 101 dox that are problematic when viewed with this particular question of evidential relevance in mind and in •˜6 I show how we may avoid the problems by moving from a syntactic/semantic to an ontic/causal relevance relation.' 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Argumentum Ad Populum Examples in Media
    Argumentum Ad Populum Examples In Media andClip-on spare. Ashby Metazoic sometimes Brian narcotize filagrees: any he intercommunicatedBalthazar echo improperly. his assonances Spense coylyis all-weather and terminably. and comminating compunctiously while segregated Pen resinify The argument further it did arrive, clearly the fallacy or has it proves false information to increase tuition costs Fallacies of emotion are usually find in grant proposals or need scholarship, income as reports to funders, policy makers, employers, journalists, and raw public. Why do in media rather than his lack of. This fallacy can raise quite dangerous because it entails the reluctance of ceasing an action because of movie the previous investment put option it. See in media should vote republican. This fallacy examples or overlooked, argumentum ad populum examples in media. There was an may select agents and are at your email address any claim that makes a common psychological aspects of. Further Experiments on retail of the end with Displaced Visual Fields. Muslims in media public opinion to force appear. Instead of ad populum. While you are deceptively bad, in media sites, weak or persuade. We often finish one survey of simple core fallacies by considering just contain more. According to appeal could not only correct and frollo who criticize repression and fallacious arguments are those that they are typically also. Why is simply slope bad? 12 Common Logical Fallacies and beige to Debunk Them. Of cancer person commenting on social media rather mention what was alike in concrete post. Therefore, it contain important to analyze logical and emotional fallacies so one hand begin to examine the premises against which these rhetoricians base their assumptions, as as as the logic that brings them deflect certain conclusions.
    [Show full text]
  • Hempel and Confirmation Theory
    Hempel and Confirmation Theory Jan Sprenger* June 15, 2020 Carl Gustav Hempel (1905–1997) was one of the primary exponents of logical empiricism. As a student and member of the Gesellschaft für em- pirische Philosophie in Berlin, alongside Reichenbach and Grelling, he wit- nessed the emergence of logical empiricism as a philosophical program. From the mid-1930s onwards, his contributions shaped its development, too. Hempel studied primarily in Göttingen and Berlin, but in 1929/30, he also spent a semester in Vienna studying with Carnap and partici- pated in the activities of the Vienna Circle. Both societies joined forces for organizing scientific events, and founded the journal Erkenntnis in 1930, where many seminal papers of logical empiricism were published, with Carnap and Reichenbach as editors. While the work of the Berlin philosophers is congenial to the project of the Vienna Circle, there are important differences, too. Neither Hempel nor his mentor Reichenbach identified “scientific philosophy” with the project of cleansing science of meaningless statements (e.g., Carnap 1930). Rather, Hempel extensively used a method that Carnap would apply in later works on probability and confirmation (Carnap 1950, 1952): expli- cation, that is, the replacement of a vague and imprecise pre-theoretical concept (e.g., “confirmation”) by a fruitful and precise concept (e.g., a formal confirmation criterion). Relying on the method of explication, Hempel developed adequacy conditions on a qualitative concept of con- firmation (Hempel 1943, 1945a,b), a probabilistic measure of degree of *Contact information: Center for Logic, Language and Cognition (LLC), Department of Philosophy and Education Sciences, Università degli Studi di Torino, Via Sant’Ottavio 20, 10124 Torino, Italy.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4: INFORMAL FALLACIES I
    Essential Logic Ronald C. Pine Chapter 4: INFORMAL FALLACIES I All effective propaganda must be confined to a few bare necessities and then must be expressed in a few stereotyped formulas. Adolf Hitler Until the habit of thinking is well formed, facing the situation to discover the facts requires an effort. For the mind tends to dislike what is unpleasant and so to sheer off from an adequate notice of that which is especially annoying. John Dewey, How We Think Introduction In everyday speech you may have heard someone refer to a commonly accepted belief as a fallacy. What is usually meant is that the belief is false, although widely accepted. In logic, a fallacy refers to logically weak argument appeal (not a belief or statement) that is widely used and successful. Here is our definition: A logical fallacy is an argument that is usually psychologically persuasive but logically weak. By this definition we mean that fallacious arguments work in getting many people to accept conclusions, that they make bad arguments appear good even though a little commonsense reflection will reveal that people ought not to accept the conclusions of these arguments as strongly supported. Although logicians distinguish between formal and informal fallacies, our focus in this chapter and the next one will be on traditional informal fallacies.1 For our purposes, we can think of these fallacies as "informal" because they are most often found in the everyday exchanges of ideas, such as newspaper editorials, letters to the editor, political speeches, advertisements, conversational disagreements between people in social networking sites and Internet discussion boards, and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • An Analysis of Informal Reasoning Fallacy and Critical Thinking Dispositions Amoung Malaysian Undergraduates
    An Analysis of Informal Reasoning Fallacy and Critical Thinking Dispositions among Malaysian Undergraduates Shamala Ramasamy Asia e University Malaysia [email protected] 28th October 2011 Abstract In this information age, the amount of complex information available due to technological advancement would require undergraduates to be extremely competent in processing information systematically. Critical thinking ability of undergraduates has been the focal point among educators, employers and the public at large. One of the dimensions of critical thinking is informal fallacy. Informal fallacy is able to distract us in thinking critically because they tend to appear as reasonable and their unreliability is not apparent on the surface. Empirical research affirms that critical thinking involves cognitive skills and dispositions. Critical thinking dispositions and informal reasoning fallacy are integral in facilitating students to have high ability in thinking critically. The aim of this paper is to measure the level of critical thinking ability among Malaysian undergraduates through the use of informal logic and critical thinking dispositions. A cross sectional survey was conducted on 189 samples of undergraduates from three different disciplines, testing them on newly developed Informal Reasoning Fallacy Instrument (IRFI) and California Critical Thinking Dispositions (CCTDI). A high reliability was achieved from both tests, with Cronbach alpha .802 for IRFI and .843 for CCTDI. Both tests projected good results among Malaysian undergraduates. Keywords Critical thinking disposition, informal logic, fallacy Introduction Critical thinking is neither the state-of-the-art scientific thinking nor it is a fad. It can be traced back to the early philosophies of Plato and Aristotle. In fact, philosophy itself revolves around critical thinking.
    [Show full text]
  • 334 CHAPTER 7 INFORMAL FALLACIES a Deductive Fallacy Is
    CHAPTER 7 INFORMAL FALLACIES A deductive fallacy is committed whenever it is suggested that the truth of the conclusion of an argument necessarily follows from the truth of the premises given, when in fact that conclusion does not necessarily follow from those premises. An inductive fallacy is committed whenever it is suggested that the truth of the conclusion of an argument is made more probable by its relationship with the premises of the argument, when in fact it is not. We will cover two kinds of fallacies: formal fallacies and informal fallacies. An argument commits a formal fallacy if it has an invalid argument form. An argument commits an informal fallacy when it has a valid argument form but derives from unacceptable premises. A. Fallacies with Invalid Argument Forms Consider the following arguments: (1) All Europeans are racist because most Europeans believe that Africans are inferior to Europeans and all people who believe that Africans are inferior to Europeans are racist. (2) Since no dogs are cats and no cats are rats, it follows that no dogs are rats. (3) If today is Thursday, then I'm a monkey's uncle. But, today is not Thursday. Therefore, I'm not a monkey's uncle. (4) Some rich people are not elitist because some elitists are not rich. 334 These arguments have the following argument forms: (1) Some X are Y All Y are Z All X are Z. (2) No X are Y No Y are Z No X are Z (3) If P then Q not-P not-Q (4) Some E are not R Some R are not E Each of these argument forms is deductively invalid, and any actual argument with such a form would be fallacious.
    [Show full text]
  • Reza Negarestani – Glass Bead – 2017 1 Three Nightmares of The
    Reza Negarestani – Glass Bead – 2017 1 Three Nightmares of the Inductive Mind Of all the disquieting riddles and paradoxes found in the arsenal of epistemological scepticism— understood as a systematic and piecemeal scrutiny into the methods and paradigms of the formation and justification of knowledge-claims—one problem has particularly proved, time and again, to be a never- ending source of cognitive vexation. With few notable exceptions, philosophers and philosophically- minded scientists and statisticians (e.g., Hume, Goodman, Putnam, Stegmüller, Boltzmann and De Finetti among others) have invariably either downplayed and deflected the seriousness of this problem and its variations, or have simply given up worrying about it in the hope that it may miraculously disappear. The said problem is nothing but David Hume’s strong version of the problem of induction which, unbeknownst to Hume himself, was destined to become the superacid of methodological scepticism capable, in the blink of an eye, of eating away the foundation of any epistemic project built on naïve forms of empiricism and rationalism. It is often the case that philosophers who pose sceptical problems recoil in fear once they realize the far- reaching implications of such problems, and Hume, with his problem of induction, is no exception. They rush into defusing their inadvertent exercise in scepticism. But systematic scepticism is something akin to an explosive chemical chain reaction. Once it is set off, with every passing minute it becomes more difficult to extinguish the flames. Pour on more water, and the fire spreads to areas you never imagined flammable. A genuine philosopher—regardless of her alliances—seeks to examine how far the fire spreads.
    [Show full text]
  • Better Thinking and Reasoning Chapter 11 Test Answer
    Name ________________________________ Better Thinking and Reasoning Chapter 11 Test Page 1 Answer each question. 1. Define formal fallacy. an error in the form of reasoning (caught by using a truth table) 2. Define informal fallacy. an error in the relationship of the premises (caught by examining context) 3. When is a valid argument unsound? when it has a false premise 4. What should you always do after you have completed your essay? rewrite it and check it for logical fallacies Classify the informal fallacy in each deductive argument as accident, begging the question, composition, division, or equivocation. 5. Anyone who thrusts a knife into another person should be arrested on the grounds of attempted murder. Since surgeons regularly put knives into their victims, they should be arrested for attempted murder. accident 6. Every atom in this chair is invisible. Therefore, the chair is invisible. composition 7. Please be quiet. You are making far too much noise. begging the question 8. A watermelon is a fruit. Therefore, a small watermelon is a small fruit. equivocation 9. The average American family has 2.4 children. The Smiths are an average American family. Therefore the Smiths have 2.4 children. division Classify each deductive argument as displaying a false dichotomy or having one of these three formal fallacies: affirming the consequent, denying the antecedent, or improper negation. 10. If your pet is a whale or a dolphin, then your pet is a mammal. Judy is not a mammal. Therefore, Judy is not a whale or not a dolphin. improper negation 11. If Probst won the election, then we would have a Democrat for mayor.
    [Show full text]
  • PHIL 110A Introduction to Philosophy: Knowledge and Reality Syllabus
    PHIL 110A Introduction to Philosophy: Knowledge and Reality Fall 2015 Syllabus Instructor: Prof. Doreen Fraser E-mail (for quick questions): [email protected] Office Hours (for substantive questions): Tuesdays 1-2p.m. and Thursdays 11:30a.m.-12:30p.m. Office: HH 330 Teaching assistant: Phillipe Beriault E-mail (for quick questions): [email protected] Office Hours (for substantive questions): See the Calendar on LEARN Office: HH 337 Course Meeting Time and Location: Mondays, Tuesdays and Thursdays 10:30-11:20p.m. in AL 124 Course Description This course provides an introduction to some central questions about knowledge and reality. What is knowledge? What are our best sources of knowledge? What are the distinguishing features of our best sources of knowledge? What sorts of things exist? How do we know? What is the relationship between our minds and our brains? We will study answers to these questions offered by a selection of philosophers past and present, including Descartes, Berkeley, Hume, Russell, P.S. Churchland, Thagard, and Searle. Methods for analyzing and assessing arguments will be an important focus of the course. Readings All of the texts for the course are available free of charge online from either the LEARN course web site or the library e-reserves web site. Required readings for each class are listed on the attached course schedule. All of the readings listed on the course schedule are required. Students are expected to read each assigned text prior to the class for which it is assigned. The assigned texts should be brought to class. You will probably find that it is necessary to re- read the texts at least once after they are discussed in class.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Grue' Problem Really Show? Re-Reading of Frank Jackson, 'Grue', Journal of Philosophy 5 (1975), Pp.113-131
    Okasha, S. (2007). What does Goodman's 'Grue' Problem Really Show? re-reading of Frank Jackson, 'Grue', Journal of Philosophy 5 (1975), pp.113-131. Philosophical Papers, 36(3), 483-502. https://doi.org/10.1080/05568640709485211 Peer reviewed version Link to published version (if available): 10.1080/05568640709485211 Link to publication record in Explore Bristol Research PDF-document This is an author's accepted manuscript of an article published in Philosophical Papers, Volume 36, Issue 3, 2007, copyright Taylor & Francis, available online at: http://www.tandfonline.com/10.1080/05568640709485211 University of Bristol - Explore Bristol Research General rights This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite only the published version using the reference above. Full terms of use are available: http://www.bristol.ac.uk/red/research-policy/pure/user-guides/ebr-terms/ Philosophical Papers Vol. 36, N o. 3 (N ovem ber 2007): 483-502 W hat Does Goodm an’s ‘Grue’ Problem Really Show? Samir Okasha Re-reading of Frank Jackson, ‘Grue’, Journal of Philosophy 5 (1975), pp.113-131.∗ Introduction N elson Goodm an devised his fam ous ‘grue’ exam ple in order to show that the sim ple ‘straight rule’ of induction leads to inconsistency unless restricted to the so-called ‘projectible’ predicates. In his searching critique of Goodm an’s discussion, Frank Jackson (1975) argued that on careful exam ination, Goodm an’s alleged paradox dissolves—the naïve straight rule does not lead to inconsistency, and does not need to be restricted to predicates of any particular type. Jackson’s article seem s to have been overlooked by m uch of the subsequent literature on ‘grue’; indicative of this is that virtually all philosophers today believe that Goodm an did show what, according to Jackson, he did not show.1 The structure of this paper is as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Confirmation and Induction
    Confirmation and Induction Jan Sprenger∗ Abstract Scientific knowledge is based on induction, that is, ampliative inferences from experience. This chapter reviews attacks on and defenses of induction, as well as attempts to spell out rules of inductive inference. Particular attention is paid to the degree of confirmation of a hypothesis, its role in inductive inference and the Bayesian explications of that concept. Finally, the chapter compares Bayesian and frequentist approaches to statistical inference. Keywords: confirmation, degree of confirmation, induction, probability, inductive logic, Bayesianism, statistical inference. ∗Contact information: Tilburg Center for Logic, Ethics and Philosophy of Science (TiLPS), Tilburg University, P.O. Box 90153, 5000 LE Tilburg, The Netherlands. Email: [email protected]. Webpage: www.laeuferpaar.de 1 1 The Problems of Induction Induction is a method of inference that aims at gaining empirical knowledge. It has two main characteristics: First, it is based on experience. (The term “experience” is used interchangeably with “observations” and “evidence”.) Second, induction is ampliative, that is, the conclusions of an inductive inference are not necessary, but contingent. The first feature makes sure that induction targets empirical knowledge, the second feature distinguishes induction from other modes of inference, such as deduction, where the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion. Induction can have many forms. The most simple one is enumerative induction: inferring a general principle or making a prediction based on the observation of par- ticular instances. For example, if we have observed 100 black ravens and no non-black ravens, we may predict that also raven #101 will be black.
    [Show full text]