A Probabilistic Proof of Wallis's Formula for Π

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Probabilistic Proof of Wallis's Formula for Π A PROBABILISTIC PROOF OF WALLIS’S FORMULA FOR ¼ STEVEN J. MILLER There are many beautiful formulas for ¼ (see for example [4]). The purpose of this note is to introduce an alternate derivation of Wallis’s product formula, equation (1), which could be covered in a first course on probability, statistics, or number theory. We quickly review other famous formulas for ¼, recall some needed facts from probability, and then derive Wallis’s formula. We conclude by combining some of the other famous formulas with Wallis’s formula to derive an interesting expression for log(¼=2) (equation (5)). Often in a first-year calculus course students encounter the Gregory-Leibniz for- mula, ¼ 1 1 1 X1 (¡1)n = 1 ¡ + ¡ + ¢ ¢ ¢ = : 4 3 5 7 2n + 1 n=0 The proof uses the fact that the derivative of arctan x is 1=(1 + x2), so ¼=4 = R 1 2 0 dx=(1 + x ). To complete the proof, expand the integrand with the geometric series formula and then justify interchanging the order of integration and summa- tion. Another interesting formula involves Bernoulli numbers and the Riemann zeta function. The Bernoulli numbers Bk are the coefficients in the Taylor series t t X1 B tk = 1 ¡ + k ; et ¡ 1 2 k! k=2 P1 ¡s each Bk is rational. The Riemann zeta function is ³(s) = n=1 n , which converges for real part of s greater than 1. Using complex analysis one finds (see for instance [10, p. 365] or [18, pp. 179–180]) that (¡4)kB ³(2k) = ¡ 2k ¢ ¼2k; 2 ¢ 2k! 1 2 P ¡2 yielding formulas for ¼ to any even power. In particular, ¼ =6 = n n and 4 P ¡4 ¼ =90 = n n . Date: June 24, 2008. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. 60E05 (primary), 60F05, 11Y60 (secondary). Key words and phrases. Wallis’s Formula, t-Distribution, Gamma Function. 1An amusing consequence of these formulas is a proof of the infinitude of primes. Using unique Q ¡s ¡1 factorization, one can show that ³(s) also equals p(1 ¡ p ) , where p runs over all primes. As ¼2 is irrational and ³(2) = ¼2=6, there must be infinitely many primes: if there were only finitely 2 Q ¡2 ¡1 many then ¼ =6 = p(1 ¡ p ) would be rational! See [13] for explicit lower bounds on ¼(x) derivable from upper bounds for the irrationality measure of ³(2), and [14] for more details on the numerous connections between ³(s) and number theory. 1 2 STEVEN J. MILLER One of the most interesting formulas for ¼ is a multiplicative one due to Wallis (1665): ¼ 2 ¢ 2 4 ¢ 4 6 ¢ 6 8 ¢ 8 Y1 2n ¢ 2n = ¢ ¢ ¢ = : (1) 2 1 ¢ 3 3 ¢ 5 5 ¢ 7 7 ¢ 9 (2n ¡ 1)(2n + 1) n=1 Common proofs use the infinite product expansion for sin x (see [18, p. 142]) or induction to prove formulas for integrals of powers of sin x (see [3, p. 115]). We present a mostly elementary proof using standard facts about probability distribu- tions encountered in a first course on probability or statistics (and hence the title).2 The reason we must write “mostly elementary” is that at one point we appeal to the Dominated Convergence Theorem. It is possible to bypass this and argue directly, and we sketch the main ideas for the interested reader. Recall that a continuous function f(x) is a continuous probability distribution if R 1 (1) f(x) ¸ 0 and (2) ¡1 f(x)dx = 1. We immediately see that if g(x) is a non- negative continuous function whose integral is finite then there exists an a > 0 such R 1 that ag(x) is a continuous probability distribution (take a = 1= ¡1 g(x)dx). This simple observation is a key ingredient in our proof, and is an extremely important technique in mathematics; the proof of Wallis’s formula is but one of many applica- tions.3 In fact, this observation greatly simplifies numerous calculations in random matrix theory, which has successfully modeled diverse systems ranging from en- ergy levels of heavy nuclei to the prime numbers; see [5, 14] for introductions to random matrix theory and [11] for applications of this technique to the subject. One of the purposes of this paper is to introduce students to the consequences of this simple observation. Our proof relies on two standard functions from probability, the Gamma func- tion and the Student t-distribution. The Gamma function ¡(x) is defined by Z 1 ¡(x) = e¡ttx¡1dt: 0 Note that this integral is well defined if the real part of x is positive. Integrating by parts yields ¡(x + 1) = x¡(x). This implies that if n is a nonnegative integer then ¡(n + 1) = n!; thus the Gamma function generalizes the factorial function (see [17] for more on the Gamma function, including another proof of Wallis’s formula involving the Gammap function). We need the following: Claim: ¡(1=2) = ¼. 2For a statistical proof involving an experiment and data, see the chapter on Buffon’s needle in [1] (page 133): if you have infinitely many parallel lines d units apart, then the probability that a “randomly” dropped rod of length ` · d crosses one of the lines is 2`=¼d. Thus you can calculate ¼ by throwing many rods on the grid and counting the number of intersections. 3A nice application of Wallis’s formula is in determining the universal constant in Stirling’s for- mula for n!; see [15] for some history and applications. A PROBABILISTIC PROOF OF WALLIS’S FORMULA FOR ¼ 3 p Proof. Inp the integral for ¡(1=2), change variables by setting u = t (so dt = 2udu = 2 tdu). This yields Z 1 Z 1 2 2 ¡(1=2) = 2 e¡u du = e¡u du: 0 ¡1 p This integral is well-known to equal ¼ (see page 542 of [2]). The standard proof is to square the integral and convert to polar coordinates: Z 1 Z 1 Z 1 Z 2¼ 2 2 2 ¡(1=2)2 = e¡u du e¡v dv = e¡r rdrdθ = ¼: ¡1 ¡1 0 0 ¤ In fact, our proof above shows Z 1 1 2 p e¡t =2dt = 1: (2) ¡1 2¼ This density is called the standard normal (or Gaussian). This is one of the most important probability distributions, and we shall see it again when we look at the Student t-distribution. If g is a continuous probability density, then we say that the random variable Y has distribution g if for any interval [a; b] the probabil- R b ity that Y takes on a value in [a; b] is a g(y)dy. The celebrated Central Limit Theorem (see [6, p. 515] for a proof) states that for many continuous densities g, if X1;:::;Xn are independent randomp variables, each with density g, then as n ! 1 the distribution of (Yn ¡ ¹)=(σ= n) converges to the standard normal (where Yn = (X1 + ¢ ¢ ¢ + Xn)=n is the sample average, ¹ is the mean of g, and σ is its standard deviation4). The second function we need is the Student5 t-distribution (with º degrees of freedom): ¡ ¢ µ ¶ º+1 µ ¶ º+1 º+1 2 ¡ 2 2 ¡ 2 ¡ 2 t t fº(t) = p ¡ º ¢ ¢ 1 + = cº 1 + ; ¼º ¡ 2 º º here º is a positive integer and t is any real number. Claim: The Student t-distribution is a continuous probability density. Proof. As fº(t) is clearly continuous and nonnegative, to show fº(t) is a proba- bility density it suffices to show that it integrates to 1. We must therefore show that Z µ ¶ º+1 p ¡ ¢ 1 2 ¡ 2 º t ¼º ¡ 2 1 + dt = ¡ º+1 ¢ : ¡1 º ¡ 2 4 R The mean ¹ of a distribution is its average value: ¹ = xg(x)dxR. The standard deviation σ measures how spread out a distribution is about its average value: σ2 = (x ¡ ¹)2g(x)dx. 5Student was the pen name of William Gosset. 4 STEVEN J. MILLER As the integrand isp symmetric, we mayp integrate from 0 to infinity and double the result. Letting t = º tan θ (so dt = º sec2 θdθ) we find Z µ ¶ º+1 Z Z 1 2 ¡ 2 ¼=2 2 ¼=2 t p sec θdθ p º¡1 1 + dt = 2 º º+1 = 2 º cos θdθ: ¡1 º 0 sec θ 0 The proof follows immediately from two properties of the Beta function (see [2, p. 560]): B(p; q) = ¡(p)¡(q)=¡(p + q) Z ¼=2 B(m + 1; n + 1) = 2 cos2m+1(θ) sin2n+1(θ)dθ; (3) 0 an elementary proof without appealing to properties of the Beta function is given in Appendix A. ¤ The Student t-distribution arises in statistical analyses where the sample size º is small and each observation is normally distributed with the same mean and the same (unknown) variance (see [8, 12]). The reason the Student t-distribution is used only for small samples sizes is that as º ! 1, fº(t) converges to the standard normal; proving this will yield Wallis’s formula. While we can prove this by invoking the Central Limit Theorem, we may also see this directly by recalling that ³ x ´N ex = lim 1 + : N!1 N We therefore have µ 2 ¶¡º=2 ³ ´ t 2 ¡1=2 2 lim 1 + = et = e¡t =2: º!1 º As fº(t) is a probability distribution for all positive integers º, it integrates to 1 for all such º, which is equivalent to p ¡ ¢ Z µ ¶ º+1 º 1 2 ¡ 2 1 ¼º ¡ 2 t = ¡ º+1 ¢ = 1 + dt: cº ¡ 2 ¡1 º Taking the limit as º ! 1 yields Z µ ¶¡ º+1 1 1 t2 2 lim = lim 1 + dt º!1 cº º!1 ¡1 º º+1 Z 1 µ 2 ¶¡ Z 1 t 2 2 p = lim 1 + dt = e¡t =2dt = 2¼: ¡1 º!1 º ¡1 Some work is necessary of course to justify interchanging the integral and the limit; this justification is why our argument is only “mostly elementary”.
Recommended publications
  • J. Wallis the Arithmetic of Infinitesimals Series: Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences
    J. Wallis The Arithmetic of Infinitesimals Series: Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences John Wallis was appointed Savilian Professor of Geometry at Oxford University in 1649. He was then a relative newcomer to mathematics, and largely self-taught, but in his first few years at Oxford he produced his two most significant works: De sectionibus conicis and Arithmetica infinitorum. In both books, Wallis drew on ideas originally developed in France, Italy, and the Netherlands: analytic geometry and the method of indivisibles. He handled them in his own way, and the resulting method of quadrature, based on the summation of indivisible or infinitesimal quantities, was a crucial step towards the development of a fully fledged integral calculus some ten years later. To the modern reader, the Arithmetica Infinitorum reveals much that is of historical and mathematical interest, not least the mid seventeenth-century tension between classical geometry on the one hand, and arithmetic and algebra on the other. Newton was to take up Wallis’s work and transform it into mathematics that has become part of the mainstream, but in Wallis’s text we see what we think of as modern mathematics still 2004, XXXIV, 192 p. struggling to emerge. It is this sense of watching new and significant ideas force their way slowly and sometimes painfully into existence that makes the Arithmetica Infinitorum such a relevant text even now for students and historians of mathematics alike. Printed book Dr J.A. Stedall is a Junior Research Fellow at Queen's University. She has written a number Hardcover of papers exploring the history of algebra, particularly the algebra of the sixteenth and 159,99 € | £139.99 | $199.99 ▶ seventeenth centuries.
    [Show full text]
  • Who Invented the Calculus? - and Other 17Th Century Topics Transcript
    Who invented the calculus? - and other 17th century topics Transcript Date: Wednesday, 16 November 2005 - 12:00AM Location: Barnard's Inn Hall WHO INVENTED THE CALCULUS? Professor Robin Wilson Introduction We’ve now covered two-thirds of our journey ‘From Caliphs to Cambridge’, and in this lecture I want to try to survey the mathematical achievements of the seventeenth century – a monumental task. I’ve divided my talk into four parts – first, the movement towards the practical sciences, as exemplified by the founding of Gresham College and the Royal Society. Next, we’ll gravitate towards astronomy, from Copernicus to Newton. Thirdly, we visit France and the gradual movement from geometry to algebra (with a brief excursion into some new approaches to pi) – and finally, the development of the calculus. So first, let’s make an excursion to Gresham College. Practical science The Gresham professorships arose from the will of Sir Thomas Gresham, which provided for £50 per year for each of seven professors to read lectures in Divinity, Astronomy, Music, Geometry, Law, Physic and Rhetoric. As the Ballad of Gresham College later described it: If to be rich and to be learn’d Be every Nation’s cheifest glory, How much are English men concern’d, Gresham to celebrate thy story Who built th’Exchange t’enrich the Citty And a Colledge founded for the witty. From its beginning, Gresham College encouraged the practical sciences, rather than the Aristotelian studies still pursued at the ancient universities: Thy Colledg, Gresham, shall hereafter Be the whole world’s Universitie, Oxford and Cambridge are our laughter; Their learning is but Pedantry.
    [Show full text]
  • Wallis's Product, Brouncker's Continued Fraction, and Leibniz's Series Author(S): Jacques Dutka Source: Archive for History of Exact Sciences, Vol
    Wallis's Product, Brouncker's Continued Fraction, and Leibniz's Series Author(s): Jacques Dutka Source: Archive for History of Exact Sciences, Vol. 26, No. 2 (1982), pp. 115-126 Published by: Springer Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/41133644 Accessed: 23-10-2017 15:57 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/41133644?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Archive for History of Exact Sciences This content downloaded from 140.233.2.214 on Mon, 23 Oct 2017 15:57:11 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms Wallis' s Product, Brouncker's Continued Fraction^ and Leibniz s Series Jacques Dutka Communicated by M. Kline Abstract A historical sketch is given of Wallis's infinite product for 4/a, and of the at- tempts which have been made, over more than three centuries, to find the method by which Brouncker obtained his equivalent continued fraction. A derivation of Brouncker's formula is given.
    [Show full text]
  • Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences
    Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences Editorial Board J.Z. Buchwald J. Lützen G.J. Toomer Advisory Board P.J. Davis T. Hawkins A.E. Shapiro D. Whiteside Springer Science+Business Media, LLC Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Seiences K. Andersen Brook Taylor's Work on Linear Perspective H.l.M. Bos Redefining Geometrical Exactness: Descartes' Transformation of the Early Modern Concept of Construction 1. Cannon/S. Dostrovsky The Evolution of Dynamics: Vibration Theory from 1687 to 1742 B. ChandIerlW. Magnus The History of Combinatorial Group Theory A.I. Dale AHistory of Inverse Probability: From Thomas Bayes to Karl Pearson, Second Edition A.I. Dale Most Honourable Remembrance: The Life and Work of Thomas Bayes A.I. Dale Pierre-Simon Laplace, Philosophical Essay on Probabilities, Translated from the fifth French edition of 1825, with Notes by the Translator P. Damerow/G. FreudenthallP. McLaugWin/l. Renn Exploring the Limits of Preclassical Mechanics: A Study of Conceptual Development in Early Modem Science: Free Fall and Compounded Motion in the Work of Descartes, Galileo, and Beeckman, Second Edition P.l. Federico Descartes on Polyhedra: A Study of the De Solworum Elementis B.R. Goldstein The Astronomy of Levi ben Gerson (1288-1344) H.H. Goldstine A History of Numerical Analysis from the 16th Through the 19th Century H.H. Goldstine A History of the Calculus of Variations from the 17th Through the 19th Century G. Graßhoff The History of Ptolemy's Star Catalogue A.W. Grootendorst Jan de Witt's Eiementa Curvarum Linearum, über Primus Continued after Index The Arithmetic of Infinitesimals John Wallis 1656 Translated from Latin to English with an Introduction by Jacqueline A.
    [Show full text]
  • John Wallis and Transcendence: Measuring the Circle
    John Wallis and Transcendence: measuring the circle January 25, 2010 MATH 160 (seminar-course) Tuesdays 2-4 p.m. Sci Center Room 530 Barry Mazur and Mark Reeder What does it mean to know a length, an area, a volume? We do it by relating lengths to other lengths, areas to areas, volumes to volumes. Archimedes had his \mechanical" method and modern mathematics has the Calculus. John Wallis grappled with an approach that lies somewhere in between Archimedes and the Calculus. We will read John Wallis's treatise The arithmetic of infinitesimals to learn what this is1. Archimedes2 related the area of a circle to that of a certain triangle built on its circumference. He related the area of parabolic segments to the area of appropriate triangles, and the volumes of spheres to that of cones and cylinders. Lurking behind many of these wonderful theorems is π (which providentially cancels out in all of the ratios that occur in these theorems). How can we study this (as it turns out, transcendental) number π? Wallis shows how the circle forces us to expand the idea of Number to include such things as π, and he gives new ways of representing such numbers. (His own Proposition 191 was quite a shocker to him|and remains a startling thing to us: it is great fun trying to get into his way of thinking, and watch it emerge.) It is also constructive, and Wallis describes (sometimes tortuously) his path to the result. In Wallis's exposition one can glimpse, as well, an implied rebuke to the ancients, who{in contrast to him| were fond of hiding their ideas; this is made explicit by Wallis in one of several interesting comments he makes.
    [Show full text]
  • John Wallis (1616–1703), Oxford's Savilian Professor
    John Wallis (1616–1703), Oxford’s Savilian Professor of Geometry from 1649 to 1703, was the most influential English mathematician before the rise of Isaac Newton. His most important works were his Arithmetic of Infinitesimals and his treatise on Conic Sections, both published in the 1650s. It was through studying the former that Newton came to discover his version of the binomial theorem. Wallis’s last great mathematical work A Treatise of Algebra was published in his seventieth year. John Wallis Wallis’ time-line “In the year 1649 I removed to 1616 Born in Ashford, Kent Oxford, being then Publick 1632–40 Studied at Emmanuel College, Professor of Geometry, of the Cambridge Foundation of Sr. Henry Savile. 1640 Ordained a priest in the And Mathematicks which Church of England had before been a pleasing 1642 Started deciphering secret codes diversion, was now to be for Oliver Cromwell’s intelligence my serious Study.” service during the English Civil Wars John Wallis 1647 Inspired by William Oughtred’s Clavis Mathematicae (Key to Mathematics) which considerably extended his mathematical knowledge 1648 Initiated mathematical correspondence with continental scholars (Hevelius, van Schooten, etc.) 1649 Appointed Savilian Professor of Geometry at Oxford 31 October: Inaugural lecture 1655–56 Arithmetica Infinitorum (The Arithmetic of Infinitesimals) and De Sectionibus Conicis (On Conic Sections) 1658 Elected Oxford University Archivist 1663 11 July: Lecture on Euclid’s parallel postulate 1655–79 Disputes with Thomas Hobbes 1685 Treatise of Algebra 1693–99 Opera Mathematica 1701 Appointed England’s first official decipherer (alongside his grandson William Blencowe) 1703 Died in Oxford John Wallis (1616–1703) Savilian Professor During the English Civil Wars John Wallis was appointed Savilian Professor of Geometry in 1649.
    [Show full text]
  • The Birth of Calculus: Towards a More Leibnizian View
    The Birth of Calculus: Towards a More Leibnizian View Nicholas Kollerstrom [email protected] We re-evaluate the great Leibniz-Newton calculus debate, exactly three hundred years after it culminated, in 1712. We reflect upon the concept of invention, and to what extent there were indeed two independent inventors of this new mathematical method. We are to a considerable extent agreeing with the mathematics historians Tom Whiteside in the 20th century and Augustus de Morgan in the 19th. By way of introduction we recall two apposite quotations: “After two and a half centuries the Newton-Leibniz disputes continue to inflame the passions. Only the very learned (or the very foolish) dare to enter this great killing- ground of the history of ideas” from Stephen Shapin1 and “When de l’Hôpital, in 1696, published at Paris a treatise so systematic, and so much resembling one of modern times, that it might be used even now, he could find nothing English to quote, except a slight treatise of Craig on quadratures, published in 1693” from Augustus de Morgan 2. Introduction The birth of calculus was experienced as a gradual transition from geometrical to algebraic modes of reasoning, sealing the victory of algebra over geometry around the dawn of the 18 th century. ‘Quadrature’ or the integral calculus had developed first: Kepler had computed how much wine was laid down in his wine-cellar by determining the volume of a wine-barrel, in 1615, 1 which marks a kind of beginning for that calculus. The newly-developing realm of infinitesimal problems was pursued simultaneously in France, Italy and England.
    [Show full text]
  • A Concise History of Mathematics the Beginnings 3
    A CONCISE HISTORY OF A CONCISE HISTORY MATHEMATICS STRUIK OF MATHEMATICS DIRK J. STRUIK Professor Mathematics, BELL of Massachussetts Institute of Technology i Professor Struik has achieved the seemingly impossible task of compress- ing the history of mathematics into less than three hundred pages. By stressing the unfolding of a few main ideas and by minimizing references to other develop- ments, the author has been able to fol- low Egyptian, Babylonian, Chinese, Indian, Greek, Arabian, and Western mathematics from the earliest records to the beginning of the present century. He has based his account of nineteenth cen- tury advances on persons and schools rather than on subjects as the treatment by subjects has already been used in existing books. Important mathema- ticians whose work is analysed in detail are Euclid, Archimedes, Diophantos, Hammurabi, Bernoulli, Fermat, Euler, Newton, Leibniz, Laplace, Lagrange, Gauss, Jacobi, Riemann, Cremona, Betti, and others. Among the 47 illustra- tions arc portraits of many of these great figures. Each chapter is followed by a select bibliography. CHARLES WILSON A CONCISE HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS by DIRK. J. STRUIK Professor of Mathematics at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology LONDON G. BELL AND SONS LTD '954 Copyright by Dover Publications, Inc., U.S.A. FOR RUTH Printed in Great Britain by Butler & Tanner Ltd., Frame and London CONTENTS Introduction xi The Beginnings 1 The Ancient Orient 13 Greece 39 The Orient after the Decline of Greek Society 83 The Beginnings in Western Europe 98 The
    [Show full text]
  • Throughout the 18Th Century Oxford Was Central in the Development of Newtonian Philosophy. Edmond Halley, the Most Famous Englis
    Throughout the 18th century Oxford was central in the development of Newtonian philosophy. Edmond Halley, the most famous English astronomer of his day, was Oxford’s Savilian Professor of Geometry. Thomas Hornsby, Sedleian Professor of Natural Philosophy, founded the Radcliffe Observatory. Oxford Mathematics from Halley to Hornsby Time-line 1656 Edmond Halley born in London 1673 Halley enters The Queen’s College, Oxford 1676–78 Halley’s expedition to map the skies of the southern hemisphere 1678 Oxford University grants Halley his MA degree by Royal Mandamus 1687 Publication of Isaac Newton’s Principia Mathematica 1704 Halley appointed Savilian Professor of Geometry 1705 Halley publishes his cometary researches 1710 Halley’s edition of Apollonius’s Conics 1717 James Stirling’s book on Isaac Newton’s classification of cubics 1720 Halley appointed Astronomer Royal 1721 James Bradley appointed Savilian Professor of Astronomy 1742 Halley dies in Greenwich and Nathaniel Bliss is appointed as his successor to the Savilian Chair 1763 Thomas Hornsby is appointed Savilian Professor of Astronomy 1764 Bliss dies and Joseph Betts is appointed as his successor 1766 Betts dies and John Smith is appointed as his successor 1782 Thomas Hornsby is appointed Sedleian Professor of Natural Philosophy 1797 Smith dies and Abraham Robertson is appointed as his successor The Radcliffe Observatory, built in the 1770s at the instigation of 1810 Hornsby dies and Robertson succeeds him as Savilian Professor Thomas Hornsby, was the first academic establishment in Europe of Astronomy to combine teaching and original research in astronomy. George Cooke succeeds Hornsby as Sedleian Professor of Natural Philosophy Oxford Mathematics from Halley to Hornsby Edmond Halley in Oxford In 1704 Edmond Halley succeeded John Wallis as Savilian Professor of Geometry and remained in post until his death in 1742.
    [Show full text]
  • SF-01 (1-27) 9/5/00 9:40 AM Page Viii SF-01 (1-27) 9/5/00 9:40 AM Page 1
    SF-01 (1-27) 9/5/00 9:40 AM Page viii SF-01 (1-27) 9/5/00 9:40 AM Page 1 800 years of mathematical traditions John Fauvel If the Elizabethan antiquary William Camden is to be believed, the teaching of mathematics at Oxford, along with the foundation of the University itself, dates from the time of Alfred the Great in the ninth century: In the year of our Lord 886, the second year of the arrival of St. Grimbald in England, the University of Oxford was begun … John, monk of the church of St. David, giving lectures in logic, music and arithmetic; and John, the monk, colleague of St. Grimbald, a man of great parts and a universal scholar, teaching geometry and astronomy before the most glorious and invincible King Alfred. By such a reckoning, we could now be celebrating over 1100 years of mathematical traditions at Oxford. Alas, the founding of the University by King Alfred is but one of the stories of Oxford’s mythical past for which there is now considered to be insufficient historical evidence. The University of Oxford can, however, safely trace its existence back over at least 800 years, which confirms its respectable antiquity while recognizing it as younger than the universities of Bologna and Paris. The University seems to have come into being gradually during the twelfth century, as groups of scholars gathered to learn and study together at ‘that catarrhal point of the English Midlands where the rivers Thames and Cherwell soggily conjoin’, in the evocative words of Jan Morris.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mathematical Minister: John Wallis (1616-1703) at the Intersection of Science, Mathematics, and Religion
    The Mathematical Minister: John Wallis (1616-1703) at the Intersection of Science, Mathematics, and Religion by Adam Richter A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology University of Toronto © Copyright by Adam Richter 2018 The Mathematical Minister: John Wallis (1616-1703) at the Intersection of Science, Mathematics, and Religion Adam Richter Doctor of Philosophy Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology University of Toronto 2018 Abstract John Wallis, Savilian Professor of Geometry at Oxford, is primarily known for his contributions to seventeenth-century mathematics. However, as a founder member of the Royal Society and an Anglican minister, Wallis also had a productive career in both natural philosophy and theology. This thesis considers Wallis as a “clerical practitioner” of science—a member of the clergy who studied natural philosophy as well as divinity—and seeks to articulate his unique perspective on the relationship between God and nature. This account of Wallis serves as a case study in the history of science and religion, establishing several novel connections between secular and sacred studies in seventeenth-century England. In particular, Wallis blends elements of experimental philosophy, Calvinist theology, and Scholastic philosophy in creative ways to make connections between the natural and the divine. This thesis has three main goals. First, it traces Wallis’s unique and idiosyncratic role in the history of science and religion. Second, it complicates two common narratives about Wallis: first, that he is historically significant mostly because his mathematics served as a precursor to Isaac Newton’s development of calculus, and second, that his successful career is the result of his ambition and political savvy rather than his original contributions to mathematics, natural philosophy, theology, and other fields.
    [Show full text]
  • Microbios II
    History Biographies II (Before Calculus) ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Mohammed ibn Musa al-Khowarizmi (Arab, ca 825) Described Hindu number system with base ten positional notation and a zero. This spread to Europe through translations of his work. Wrote treatise on algebra called Hisab al-jabr w'al-muqa-balah (Science of taking apart and joining back). Adelard translated his astronomy tables for Europe. Gherardo of Cremona translated his algebra work into Latin (ca 1150). His work included casting out nines, estimating square and cube roots, fractions, and the rule of three (business math). ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Bhaskara (India, 1114 - ca 1185 AD) Lived in Ujjain, India (central India, home of Brahmagupta, 5 centuries before). Wrote Siddhanta Siromani (Diadem of an Astronomical System) in 1150. Proved the Pythagorean theorem by a dissection method (central square with side b–a). Also had the "altitude-on-the-hypotenuse" proof of the Pythagorean theorem. Used the method of inversion/false position. Had identities for square roots and quadratic surds, and worked on Pell's equation. Gave 3927/1250 as π; also 22/7 and square root of 10 as approximates to π. Also gave 754/240 which was known to Ptolemy. Lilavati (The Beautiful) deals with arithmetic and Vijaganita (Seed arithmetic) with algebra. ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Brahmagupta (India, ca 628 AD) Lived in Ujjain (central India) in 628. Wrote on "the revised system of Brahma", a work on astronomy. Worked on Pell's equation. Found integral solutions to ax + by = c given a, b, c integers. Had Heron's formula for area of a triangle in terms of three sides and also had a generalization.
    [Show full text]