Science and Pseudoscience Imre Lakatos
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Urban Myths Mythical Cryptids
Ziptales Advanced Library Worksheet 2 Urban Myths Mythical Cryptids ‘What is a myth? It is a story that pretends to be real, but is in fact unbelievable. Like many urban myths it has been passed around (usually by word of mouth), acquiring variations and embellishments as it goes. It is a close cousin of the tall tale. There are mythical stories about almost any aspect of life’. What do we get when urban myths meet the animal kingdom? We find a branch of pseudoscience called cryptozoology. Cryptozoology refers to the study of and search for creatures whose existence has not been proven. These creatures (or crytpids as they are known) appear in myths and legends or alleged sightings. Some examples include: sea serpents, phantom cats, unicorns, bunyips, giant anacondas, yowies and thunderbirds. Some have even been given actual names you may have heard of – do Yeti, Owlman, Mothman, Cyclops, Bigfoot and the Loch Ness Monster sound familiar? Task 1: Choose one of the cryptids from the list above (or perhaps one that you may already know of) and write an informative text identifying the following aspects of this mythical creature: ◊ Description ◊ Features ◊ Location ◊ First Sighting ◊ Subsequent Sightings ◊ Interesting Facts (e.g. how is it used in popular culture? Has it been featured in written or visual texts?) Task 2: Cryptozoologists claim there have been cases where species now accepted by the scientific community were initially considered urban myths. Can you locate any examples of creatures whose existence has now been proven but formerly thought to be cryptids? Extension Activities: • Cryptozoology is called a ‘pseudoscience’ because it relies solely on anecdotes and reported sightings rather than actual evidence. -
Reexamining the Problem of Demarcating Science and Pseudoscience by Evan Westre B.A., Vancouver Island University, 2010 a Thesis
Reexamining the Problem of Demarcating Science and Pseudoscience By Evan Westre B.A., Vancouver Island University, 2010 A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS ©Evan Westre, 2014 All Rights Reserved. This thesis may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without the permission of the author. Supervisory Committee Reexamining the Problem of Demarcating Science and Pseudoscience By Evan Westre B.A., Vancouver Island University, 2010 Dr. Audrey Yap: Supervisor (Department of Philosophy) Dr. Jeffrey Foss: Departmental Member (Department of Philosophy) ii Abstract Supervisory Committee Dr. Audrey Yap: Supervisor (Department of Philosophy) Dr. Jeffrey Foss: Departmental Member (Department of Philosophy) The demarcation problem aims to articulate the boundary between science and pseudoscience. Solutions to the problem have been notably raised by the logical positivists (verificationism), Karl Popper (falsificationism), and Imre Lakatos (methodology of research programmes). Due, largely, to the conclusions drawn by Larry Laudan, in a pivotal 1981 paper which dismissed the problem of demarcation as a “pseudo-problem”, the issue was brushed aside for years. Recently, however, there has been a revival of attempts to reexamine the demarcation problem and synthesize new solutions. My aim is to survey two of the contemporary attempts and to assess these approaches over and against the broader historical trajectory of the demarcation problem. These are the efforts of Nicholas Maxwell (aim-oriented empiricism), and Paul Hoyningen-Huene (systematicity). I suggest that the main virtue of the new attempts is that they promote a self-reflexive character within the sciences. -
A Quick How-To User-Guide to Debunking Pseudoscientific Claims
A quick how-to user-guide to debunking pseudoscientific claims Maxim Sukharev Arizona State University Have you ever wondered why we have never heard of psychics and palm readers winning millions of dollars in state or local lotteries or becoming Wall Street wolfs? Neither have I. Yet we are constantly bombarded by tabloid news on how vaccines cause autism (hint: they don’t), or some unknown firm building a mega-drive that defies the laws of physics (nope, that drive doesn’t work either). And the list continues on and on and on. Sometimes it looks quite legit as, say, various “natural” vitamin supplements that supposedly increase something that cannot be increased, or enhance something else that is most likely impossible to enhance by simply swallowing a few pills. Or constantly evolving diets that “sure work” giving a false relieve to those who really need to stop eating too much and actually pay frequent visits to a local gym. It is however understandable that most of us fall for such products and “news” just because we cannot be experts in everything, and we tend to trust various mass-media sources without even a glimpse of skepticism. So how can we distinguish between baloney statements and real exciting scientific discoveries and breakthroughs? In what follows I will try to do my best to provide a simple how-to user’s guide to debunking pseudoscientific claims. Just one more quick note before we begin: always remember that debunking a myth can actually backfire and reinforce it if done incorrectly. In 2005 the group of researchers [1] performed a set of experiments examining various true/false consumer health/food claims and their time-delayed effects on adults. -
An Analysis of the Demarcation Problem in Philosophy of Science and Its Application to Homeopathy
AN ANALYSIS OF THE DEMARCATION PROBLEM IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND ITS APPLICATION TO HOMEOPATHY Alper Bilgehan YARDIMCI ABSTRACT This paper presents a preliminary analysis of homeopathy from the perspective of the demarcation problem in the philosophy of science. In this context, Popper, Kuhn and Feyerabend’s solution to the problem will be given respectively and their criteria will be applied to homeopathy, aiming to shed some light on the controversy over its scientific status. It then examines homeopathy under the lens of demarcation criteria to conclude that homeopathy is regarded as science by Feyerabend and is considered as pseudoscience by Popper and Kuhn. By offering adequate tools for the analysis of the foundations, structure and implications of homeopathy, demarcation issue can help to clarify this medical controversy. The main argument of this article is that a final decision on homeopathy, whose scientific status changes depending on the criteria of the philosophers mentioned, cannot be given. Keywords: Demarcation Problem, Scientific Status of Homeopathy, Falsifiability, Puzzle-solving, Anarchist Method, Pseudoscience BİLİM FELSEFESİNDE SINIR ÇİZME SORUNUNUN ANALİZİ VE HOMEOPATİYE UYGULANMASI ÖZ Bu makale, bilim felsefesinin önemli konularından biri olan sınır çizme sorunu açısından homeopatinin bir ön analizini sunmaktadır. Bu bağlamda, Popper, Kuhn ve Feyerabend'in sınır çizme sorununa yönelik çözümleri sırasıyla verilecek ve onların ölçütleri, homeopatinin bilimsel durumu üzerindeki tartışmalara ışık tutacak şekilde uygulanacaktır. Homeopatinin Feyerabend tarafından bilim, Popper ve Kuhn açısından ise sözde bilim olduğu sonucuna varmak amacıyla, homeopati sınır çizme ölçütleri çerçevesinde incelenmektedir. Sınır çizme tartışması homeopatinin temellerini, yapısını ve sonuçlarını analiz etmek için yeterli araçları sunarak bu tıbbi tartışmayı netleştirmeye yardımcı olabilir. -
Four Examples of Pseudoscience
Four Examples of Pseudoscience Marcos Villavicencio Tenerife, Canarias, Spain E-mail address: [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0001-6700-4872 January 2020 Abstract A relevant issue in the philosophy of science is the demarcation problem: how to distinguish science from nonscience, and, more specifically, science from pseudoscience. Sometimes, the demarcation problem is debated from a very general perspective, proposing demarcation criteria to separate science from pseudoscience, but without discussing any specific field in detail. This article aims to focus the demarcation problem on particular disciplines or theories. After considering a set of demarcation criteria, four pseudosciences are examined: psychoanalysis, speculative evolutionary psychology, universal grammar, and string theory. It is concluded that these theoretical frameworks do not meet the requirements to be considered genuinely scientific. Keywords Demarcation Problem · Pseudoscience · Psychoanalysis · Evolutionary psychology · Universal grammar · String theory 1 Introduction The demarcation problem is the issue of how to differentiate science from nonscience in general and pseudoscience in particular. Even though expressions such as “demarcation problem” or “pseudoscience” were still not used, some consider that an early interest for demarcation existed as far back as the time of ancient Greece, when Aristotle separated episteme (scientific knowledge) from mere doxa (opinion), holding that apodictic certainty is the basis of science (Laudan 1983, p. 112). Nowadays, the issue of demarcation continues being discussed. Certainly, demarcating science from pseudoscience is not a topic of exclusive philosophical interest. Scientists and members of skeptical organizations such as the Committee for Scientific Inquiry also deal with this crucial theme. The issue of how to recognize pseudoscience not only affects academia. -
Tools for Skeptical Thinking
Tools for Skeptical Thinking Evaluating Science and Pseudoscience in Speech- Language Pathology (pages 2-13) Logic, Theory, and Evidence Against the Use of Nonspeech Oral Motor Exercises (NSOME) to Change Speech Sound Productions in Children (pages 14-28) February 13, 2017 Presented by: Gregory L. Lof, PhD, CCC-SLP, FASHA Chair/Professor Department of Communication Sciences and Disorders MGH Institute of Heath Professions, Boston, MA Page 1 Quackery • A type of pseudoscience; any practice or remedy that has no compelling scientific basis for them to work. Includes questionable ideas and questionable products and services, regardless of the sincerity of the promoters. • A charlatan is a person who pretends or claims to have more knowledge or skill than s/he possesses, knows that his/her skills are not real, uses deception and usually does things to obtain money, fame or other advantages. • Why Fad Therapies Exist (Vyse, 2005): Incomplete effectiveness of available therapies Available treatments are onerous or distasteful Alternative treatments are supported by ideology Treatments are promoted by proprietary groups. • Why Fad Therapies Persist (Lilienfeld, Marshall, Todd & Shane, 2015): Desperation Poor sources of information Seductive appeal Savior effect Naïve realism Personal experiences Confirmation bias Cognitive dissonance Profit. Skepticism • A skeptic is a person who has a questioning attitude or has some degree of doubt regarding claims that are taken for granted elsewhere. • The word skepticism can characterize a position on a single claim, but more frequently it describes a lasting mindset. • Skepticism is an approach to accepting, rejecting, or suspending judgment on new information that requires the new information to be well-supported by evidence. -
Chapter 1. Introduction to Scientific Thinking
INTRODUCTION TO 1 SCIENTIFIC THINKING CHAPTER SUMMARY CHAPTER LEARNING OBJECTIVES 1.1 Science as a Method of Knowing 1. Define science and the scientific Science is one way of knowing about the world. The word science method. comes from the Latin scientia, meaning knowledge, and from a broad view, science is any systematic method of acquiring knowledge apart 2. Describe six steps for engaging in the from ignorance. To use the scientific method, we make observations scientific method. that can be directly or indirectly observed. 3. Describe five nonscientific methods distributeof acquiring knowledge. 1.2 The Scientific Method or 4. Identify the four goals of science. To engage in the scientific method, the process used to acquire 5. Distinguish between basic and knowledge is organized into six steps: applied research. Identify a problem. Identify an area of interest to you, and 6. Distinguish between quantitative then review the scientific literature, typically using online and qualitative research. search engines, to identify what is known and what can still post, 7. Delineate science from be learned about your area of interest. After conducting a pseudoscience. literature review, identify new ideas in your area of interest by making a statement of prediction called a research hypothesis. Develop a research plan. Oncecopy, a research hypothesis is stated, you need a plan to test that hypothesis. Identify the variables being tested and define them in terms of how they will be measured (i.e., state an operational definition). Identify a population of interest and determine how to select a sample of participants to observe from this larger population. -
Pre-Service Science Teachers' Discrimination Level Of
ORIGINAL ARTICLE Pre-service Science Teachers’ Discrimination Level of Science and Pseudoscience Murat Berat Uçar1* Elvan Sahin2 1Department of Mathematics and Science Education, M. R. Faculty of Education, Kilis 7 Aralik University, Kilis, Turkey, 2Department of Mathematics and Science Education, Faculty of Education, Middle East Technical University, Ankara, Turkey *Corresponding author: [email protected] ABSTRACT This quantitative study aimed to examine Turkish pre-service science teachers’ beliefs regarding the demarcating between science and pseudoscience. Participants completed the Science and Pseudoscience Distinction Scale. Data collected from the 123 pre-service science teachers were examined based on the dimensions of the instrument, namely science as a process of inquiry (SCI), demarcating between science and pseudoscience, and pseudoscientific beliefs (PS). This study found that these pre-service science teachers generally did not hold strong beliefs on distinguishing science and pseudoscience. Their beliefs regarding SCI were not highly favorable. Moreover, this study revealed that they had some PS. Considering the role of gender and year in the program, the results of two-way MANOVA indicated that there was no statistically significant difference on the related belief constructs for these pre-service science teachers. Thus, the present study intended to shed light on pre-service science teachers’ mindsets about identifying accurate scientific information rather than pseudoscientific confusions that could aid preparing scientifically -
The Markers of Pseudoscience
Advances in Economics, Business and Management Research, volume 128 International Scientific Conference "Far East Con" (ISCFEC 2020) The Markers of Pseudoscience R Livshits1 1Department of Philosophy, Social and Political Disciplines,Amur State University of Humanities and Pedagogy, Komsomolsk-on-Amur, Russia E-mail: [email protected] Abstract. Science classes require from a person intellectual, volitional and moral qualities, which not all people possess. Therefore, a number of people who do not have the appropriate abilities are tempted to imitate science. Such imitation is called pseudoscience. On the вasis of what attributes can pseudoscience be identified? In modern methodological literature, a number of attempts have been made to answer this question. Some markers can be detected relatively easily. Other markers need some substantive text exploration. However it is impossible to limit by the criteria based on the synthesis of practical experience. A guiding idea is necessary to puzzle out not only simple, but also difficult cases. In our view, we should proceed from the principle of the text conformity to the norms of the scientific ethos. We proceed from the classical understanding of scientific activity as a scrupulous search for truth. It leads to the interpretation of pseudoscience as activity pursuing goals lying outside the science limits: material gain, fame, social status, etc. Therefore, if the signs of lack of conscientiousness are detected in the text it can be qualified as pseudoscientific with a high degree of probability. This approach allows to identify a specific type of pseudoscience, that we call "would-be science". Moreover, this approach makes it possible to qualify as pseudoscientific those texts, which are not scientific according to previously proposed criteria. -
Science and Pseudoscience in Medicine: Evidence-Based Vs. Evidence-Biased Medicine
Psychiatria Danubina, 2016; Vol. 28, Suppl. 2, pp S186–S190 Medicina Academica Mostariensia, 2016; Vol. 4, No. 1-2, pp 2-6 Editorial © Medicinska naklada - Zagreb, Croatia SCIENCE AND PSEUDOSCIENCE IN MEDICINE: EVIDENCE-BASED VS. EVIDENCE-BIASED MEDICINE Miro Jakovljević1 & Ljerka Ostojić2 1University Hospital Centre Zagreb, Department of Psychiatry, Zagreb, Croatia 2School of Medicine, University of Mostar, Mostar, Bosnia and Herzegovina SUMMARY The concept of evidence-based medicine (EBM), as the highest standard of health care, came into existence in 1990s to promote a systematic approach to helping clinicians in their practice to be guided by the best available scientific evidence. However, there has been an increasing number of warning reports “that in modern research, misrepresented, false and unuseful findings may be the majority or even the vast majority of published research claims In spite of the huge scientific progress, pseudoscience and associated evidence biased medicine represent a serious threat to the concept of the EBM. Effective education in medicine, proper research motivation, sound systems and creative thinking and culture of scientific dialogue may significantly contribute to better science and evidence-based medicine. The seven key words of good science, research and publishing are: integrity, motivation, capacity, understanding, knowledge, experience, and creativity. Key words: science in medicine - evidence-based medicine – pseudoscience - evidence-biased medicine * * * * * Introduction Biomedical science has significantly empowered con- temporary evidence-based medicine (EBM), prolonged “Truth is a fruit which should not be plucked until it is ripe” Voltaire longevity in general population and improved quality of life. Modern clinical pharmacology has claimed itself as Pseudoscience and evidence biased medicine repre- scientific, rational and very much evidence-based. -
Beastly Fakes ‘Sasquatch’ Tracks — the Book Could Justi- Fiably Have Been a Compilation of Mockery and Humour
followed by other people faking evidence, until a self-reinforcing legend is established. As more monster hunters flock to find the beast, more dubious evidence is generated. Before you know it, there is a souvenir shop POPPERFOTO/GETTY POPPERFOTO/GETTY selling T-shirts. Yet it is the hunters — ranging from out- right rogues to serious, if misguided, research- ers — who make this a gripping read. For instance, Bernard Heuvelmans, referenced as the founder of modern cryptozoology, earned a doctorate studying aardvark teeth, worked as a jazz musician and comedian, escaped from the Nazis and befriended Tintin creator Georges Prosper Remi (known by the pen- name ‘Hergé’) before producing his work on “What cryptids of all kinds. emerges is On a 1958 expedi- a never less tion to Tibet to seek than rigorous the yeti (a kind of examination Himalayan Bigfoot), of the led by Texas oil baron evidence.” Tom Slick, some members of the group allegedly performed sleight of hand on a sacred relic, swapping human finger bones for purported yeti A purported yeti footprint from the Menlung Basin in Nepal. bones. The stolen bones were reportedly smuggled out of the country in the luggage CRYPTOZOOLOGY of actor James Stewart. Going by these and other anecdotes in Abominable Science! — such as people strapping on fake wooden feet to create Beastly fakes ‘Sasquatch’ tracks — the book could justi- fiably have been a compilation of mockery and humour. In fact, it is a sensitive but Daniel Cressey delves into a sceptics’ history of devastating takedown of an entire subcul- monster hunters and their mythical quarry. -
(1963). Science As Falsification by Karl R. Popper
The following excerpt was originally published in Conjectures and Refutations (1963). Science as Falsification by Karl R. Popper When I received the list of participants in this course and realized that I had been asked to speak to philosophical colleagues I thought, after some hesitation and consolation, that you would probably prefer me to speak about those problems which interests me most, and about those developments with which I am most intimately acquainted. I therefore decided to do what I have never done before: to give you a report on my own work in the philosophy of science, since the autumn 1919 when I first begin to grapple with the problem, "When should a theory be ranked as scientific?" or "Is there a criterion for the scientific character or status of a theory?" The problem which troubled me at the time was neither, "When is a theory true?" nor "When is a theory acceptable?" my problem was different. I wished to distinguish between science and pseudo-science; knowing very well that science often errs, and that pseudoscience may happen to stumble on the truth. I knew, of course, the most widely accepted answer to my problem: that science is distinguished from pseudoscience—or from "metaphysics"—by its empirical method, which is essentially inductive, proceeding from observation or experiment. But this did not satisfy me. On the contrary, I often formulated my problem as one of distinguishing between a genuinely empirical method and a non-empirical or even pseudo-empirical method — that is to say, a method which, although it appeals to observation and experiment, nevertheless does not come up to scientific standards.