Sophie Langenskiold AKADEMISK AVHANDLING

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sophie Langenskiold AKADEMISK AVHANDLING PEER INFLUENCE ON SMOKING: CAUSATION OR CORRELATION? Sophie Langenskiold AKADEMISK AVHANDLING som for avlaggande av ekonomie doktorsexamen vid Handelshogskolan i Stockholm framlaggs for offentlig granskning fredagen den 13 j anuari 2006, kl 15.15 i sal KAW, Handelshogskolan, Sveavagen 65, Stockholm '~\ST.OCKHOLMSC.HOOL (:"I:J OF ECONOMICS ~~.'" HANDELSH0GSKOLAN I STOCKHOLI\.1 EFI, The Economic Research Institute EFI Mission EFI, the Economic Research Institute at the Stockholm School of Economics, is a scientific institution which works independently of economic, political and sectional interests. It conducts theoretical and empirical research in the management and economic sciences, including selected related disciplines. The Institute encourages and assists in the publication and distribution of its research findings and is also involved in the doctoral education at the Stockholm School of Economics. At EFI, the researchers select their projects based on the need for theoretical or practical development of a research domain, on their methodological interests, and on the generality ofa problem. Research Organization The research activities at the Institute are organized in 23 Research Centres. Centre Directors are professors at the Stockholm School ofEconomics. EFIResearch Centre: Centre Director: Management and Organisation (A) Sven-Erik Sjostrand Centre for Ethics and Economics (CEE) Hans de Geer Centre for Entrepreneurship and Business Creation (E) Carin Holmquist Public Management (F) Nils Brunsson Information Management (1) Mats Lundeberg Centre for People and Organization (PMO) Andreas Werr (acting) Centre for Innovation and Operations Management (T) Christer Karlsson Centre for Risk Research (CFR) Lennart Sj oberg Economic Psychology (P) Guje Sevon Centre for Consumer Marketing (CCM) Magnus Soderlund Centre for Information and Communication Research (CIC) Per Andersson (acting) Marketing, Distribution and Industrial Dynamics (D) Bjorn Axelsson Centre for Strategy and Competitiveness (eSC) Orjan Salvell Centre for Business and Economic History (BEH) Hakan Lindgren Accounting and Managerial Finance (B) Johnny Lind Centre for Financial Analysis and Managerial Economics in Kenth Skogsvik Accounting (BFAC) Finance (FI) Clas Bergstrom Centre for Health Economics (CHE) Bengt Jonsson International Economics and Geography (LEG) Mats LundaW Economics (S) Lars Bergman Economic Statistics (ES) Anders Westlund Law (RY) Erik Nerep Centre for Tax Law (SR) Bertil Wiman Chair ofthe Board' Professor Carin Holmquist Director: Associate Professor Filip Wijkstrom Address EFI, Box 6501, SE-113 83 Stockholm, Sweden • Homepage: www.hhs.se/efi/ Telephone: +46(0)8-736 9000 • Fax: +46(0)8-31 62 70 • E-mail [email protected] PEER INFLUENCE ON SMOKING: CAUSATION OR CORRELATION? Sophie Langenskiold l:it, STOCKHOLM SCHOOL \~i:J OF ECONOMICS ~.~~.~ HANDELSHOGSKOLAN I STOCKHOLM EFI, The Economic Research Institute ,,";?ii3-~~ f'S'~'S'l Dissertation for the Degree of Doctor of Economics ".~~~.!' Stockholm School of Economics ABSTRACT: In this thesis, we explore two different approaches to causal inferences. The traditional approach models the theoretical relationship between the outcome variables and their explanatory variables, i.e., the science, at the same time as the systematic differences between treated and control subjects are modeled, i.e., the assignment mechanism. The alternative approach, based on Rubin's Causal Model (RCM), makes it possible to model the science and the assignment mechanism sepa­ rately in a two-step procedure. In the first step, no outcome variables are used when the assignment mechanism are modeled, the treated students are matched with similar control students using this mechanism, and the models for the science are determined. Outcome variables are only used in the second step when these pre-specified models for the science are fitted. In the first paper, we use the traditional approach to evaluate whether a husband is more prone to quit smoking when his wife quits smoking than he would have been had his wife not quit. We find evidence that this is the case, but that our analysis must rely on restrictive assumptions. In the subsequent two papers, we use the alternative RCM approach to evaluate if a Harvard freshman who does not smoke (observed potential outcome) is more prone to start smoking when he shares a suite with at least one smoker, than he would have been had he shared a suite with only smokers (missing potential outcomes). We do not find evidence that this is the case, and the small and insignificant treatment effect is robust against various assumptions that we make regarding covariate adjustments and missing potential outcomes. In contrast, we do find such evidence when we use the traditional approach previously used in the literature to evaluate peer effects relating to smoking, but the treat­ ment effect is not robust against the assumptions that we make regarding covariate adjustments. These contrasting results in the two latter papers allow us to conclude that there are a number of advantages with the alternative RCM approach over the traditional approaches previously used to evaluate peer effects relating to smoking. Because the RCM does not use the outcome variables when the assignment mechanism is modeled, it can be re-fit repeatedly without biasing the models for the science. The assignment mechanism can then often be modeled to fit the data better and, because the models for the science can consequently better control for the assignment mechanism, they can be fit with less restrictive assumptions. Moreover, because the RCM models two distinct processes separately, the implications of the assumptions that are made on these processes become more transparent. Finally, the RCM can derive the two potential outcomes needed for drawing causal inferences explicitly, which enhances the transparency of the assumptions made with regard to the missing potential outcomes. KEYWORDS: Peer effects, smoking, Harvard freshmen, quasi-experimental study, Rubin's Causal Model, imputation, propensity score matching, Mahalanobis-metric matching, Bonferroni-adjusted p-Ievels. vii @EFI and the author, 2005 ISBN NR 91-7258-692-3 PRINTED BY: Elanders Gotab, Stockholm 2005 DISTRIBUTED BY: EFI, The Economic Research Institute Stockholn1 School of Economics POBox 6501, SE-113 83 Stockholn1 www.hhs.se/efi Contents Acknowledgements xi Part 1. Introduction 1 Description of thesis 3 Summary of papers 7 References 13 Part 2. Papers 15 Causal inference according to the traditional approach 17 1. Introduction 17 2. Theory 18 3. Empirical strategy 20 4. Data 23 5. Empirical results 25 6. Conclusion 31 7. Tables 32 References 39 Designing a study using Rubin's Causal Model (Part I) 41 1. Introduction 41 2. Theory and perspectives 44 3. The template experiment 49 4. Covariate data preparation 52 5. Replicating a randomized study 54 6. "Practice" outcome analyses 60 7. Conclusion 63 8. Tables 67 References 103 Analyzing the results using Rubin's Causal Model (Part II) 105 1. Introduction 105 2. Theory 107 3. Preparation 113 4. Analysis 116 ix x CONTENTS 5. "Hunting for results" 118 6. Conclusion 121 7. Tables 124 References 131 Part 3. A quasi-experimental study 133 A freshman study at Harvard College 135 1. Applying for approval 135 2. Recruiting students 136 3. Interviewing participants 138 4. Questionnaires 138 5. Informed consent forms 154 References 161 Acknowledgements Before I began my graduate studies, I knew that the experience would be a challenge. But I never quite understood how daunting a challenge it would be. In fact, the first semester was one of the hardest times in my life. Because I started my graduate stud­ ies five years after I finished my undergraduate studies, I had forgotten much of the basic requirements for the first two courses in mathematics and microeconomics. As a consequence, I sat through lectures that were completely incomprehensible to me from beginning to end. But, I got through these two courses, the rest of the coursework, and my thesis work. I would never have seen it through, however, without the support that I was fortunate enough to have from the people around me. I have been fortunate to have Professor Magnus Johannesson at Stockholm School of Economics as my advisor. Magnus has always been very dedicated to my work and available to discuss research and to comment on my written material on short notice. His support has been vital to n1e for finishing n1Y dissertation. Magnus also helped me get the most out of my graduate studies by encouraging my wish to spend nearly four years at Harvard University. Without his willingness to direct my research over the phone and his involvement in my applications for funding and other critical factors, I would not have had this opportunity. I have also had the opportunity to have Professor Donald Rubin at Harvard University as my advisor during the last couple of years. Donald has been very involved in the two last papers in this thesis and he has been tremendously generous, not only with his time, but also with his ideas and feedback. I have learned enormously from the many discussions that we have had, as well as the detailed feedback that I received from him on written work. Not only have I gained a deeper knowledge about the field that Donald has been instrun1ental in developing, but from him I also learned about the art of writing a paper and the responsibility that comes along with being a researcher. Donald's intuition for statistics and his intuitive
Recommended publications
  • 1 the University of Chicago the Harris School of Public
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO THE HARRIS SCHOOL OF PUBLIC POLICY PPHA 421: APPLIED ECONOMETRICS II Spring 2016: Mondays and Wednesdays 10:30 – 11:50 pm, Room 140C Instructor: Professor Koichiro Ito 157 Harris School [email protected] Office hours: Mondays 3-4pm TA: Katherine Goulde: [email protected] Course Description The goal of this course is for students to learn a set of statistical tools and research designs that are useful in conducting high-quality empirical research on topics in applied microeconomics and related fields. Since most applied economic research examines questions with direct policy implications, this course will focus on methods for estimating causal effects. This course differs from many other econometrics courses in that it is oriented towards applied practitioners rather than future econometricians. It therefore emphasizes research design (relative to statistical technique) and applications (relative to theoretical proofs), though it covers some of each. Prerequisites PPHA42000 (Applied Econometrics I) is the prerequisite for this course. Students should be familiar with graduate school level probability and statistics, matrix algebra, and the classical linear regression model at the level of PPHA420. In the Economics department, the equivalent level of preparation would be the 1st year Ph.D. econometrics coursework. In general, I do not recommend taking this course if you have not taken PPHA420: Applied Econometrics I or a Ph.D. level econometrics coursework. This course is a core course for Ph.D. students and MACRM students at Harris School. Those who are not in the Harris Ph.D. program, the MACRM program, or the economics Ph.D. program need permission from the instructor to take the course.
    [Show full text]
  • Donald Rubin Three-Day Course in Causality 5 to 7 February 2020 At
    Donald Rubin Three-day Course in Causality 5 to 7 February 2020 at Waldhotel Doldenhorn, Kandersteg About the Course Most questions in social and biomedical sciences are causal in nature: what would happen to individuals, or to groups, if part of their environment were changed? In the course, the world-renowned expert Donald Rubin (Prof. em. Harvard) presents statistical methods for studying such questions. The course will follow his book Causal Inference for Statistics, Social, and Biomedical Sciences (Cambridge University Press, 2016) and starts with the notion of potential outcomes, each corresponding to the outcome that would be realized if a subject were exposed to a particular treatment or regime. In this approach, causal effects are comparisons of such potential outcomes. The fundamental problem of causal inference is that we can only observe one of the potential outcomes for a particular subject. Prof. Rubin will discuss how randomized experiments allow us to assess causal effects and then turn to observational studies. They lay out the assumptions needed for causal inference and describe the leading analysis methods, including matching, propensity-score methods, and instrumental variables. Many detailed applications will be shown, with special focus on practical aspects for the empirical researcher. About the Lecturer Donald B. Rubin is Professor Emeritus of Statistics, Harvard University, where he has been professor from 1984 to 2018 and department chair for fifteen years. Since 2018 he is professor at the Yau Mathematical Sciences Center, Tsinghua University, China, and Murray Shusterman Senior Research Fellow at the Department of Statistical Science, Fox School of Business, Temple University, Philadelphia.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory with Applications to Voting and Deliberation Experiments!
    Randomized Evaluation of Institutions: Theory with Applications to Voting and Deliberation Experiments Yves Atchadey and Leonard Wantchekonz June 24, 2009 Abstract We study causal inference in randomized experiments where the treatment is a decision making process or an institution such as voting, deliberation or decentralized governance. We provide a statistical framework for the estimation of the intrinsic e¤ect of the institution. The proposed framework builds on a standard set-up for estimating causal e¤ects in randomized experiments with noncompliance (Hirano-Imbens-Rubin-Zhou [2000]). We use the model to re- analyze the e¤ect of deliberation on voting for programmatic platforms in Benin (Wantchekon [2008]), and provide practical suggestions for the implementation and analysis of experiments involving institutions. 1 Introduction Randomized experiments are a widely accepted approach to infer causal relations in statis- tics and the social sciences. The idea dates back at least to Neyman (1923) and Fisher (1935) and has been extended by D. Rubin and coauthors (Rubin (1974), Rubin (1978), Rosenbaum and Rubin (1983)) to observational studies and to other more general experimental designs. In this approach, causality is de…ned in terms of potential outcomes. The causal e¤ect of a treatment, say Treatment 1 (compared to another treatment, Treatment 0) on the variable Y and on the statistical unit i is de…ned as Y i(1) Y i(0) (or its expected value) where Y i(j) is the value we would observe on unit i if it receives Treatment j. The estimation of this e¤ect is problematic because unit i cannot be given both Treatment 1 and Treatment 0.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1805.08845V4 [Stat.ML] 10 Jul 2021 Outcomes Such As Images, Sequences, and Graphs
    Counterfactual Mean Embeddings Krikamol Muandet∗ [email protected] Max Planck Institute for Intelligent Systems Tübingen, Germany Motonobu Kanagaway [email protected] Data Science Department, EURECOM Sophia Antipolis, France Sorawit Saengkyongam [email protected] University of Copenhagen Copenhagen, Denmark Sanparith Marukatat [email protected] National Electronics and Computer Technology Center National Science and Technology Development Agency Pathumthani, Thailand Abstract Counterfactual inference has become a ubiquitous tool in online advertisement, recommen- dation systems, medical diagnosis, and econometrics. Accurate modelling of outcome distri- butions associated with different interventions—known as counterfactual distributions—is crucial for the success of these applications. In this work, we propose to model counter- factual distributions using a novel Hilbert space representation called counterfactual mean embedding (CME). The CME embeds the associated counterfactual distribution into a reproducing kernel Hilbert space (RKHS) endowed with a positive definite kernel, which allows us to perform causal inference over the entire landscape of the counterfactual distri- bution. Based on this representation, we propose a distributional treatment effect (DTE) which can quantify the causal effect over entire outcome distributions. Our approach is nonparametric as the CME can be estimated under the unconfoundedness assumption from observational data without requiring any parametric assumption about the underlying dis- tributions. We also establish a rate of convergence of the proposed estimator which depends on the smoothness of the conditional mean and the Radon-Nikodym derivative of the un- derlying marginal distributions. Furthermore, our framework allows for more complex arXiv:1805.08845v4 [stat.ML] 10 Jul 2021 outcomes such as images, sequences, and graphs.
    [Show full text]
  • The Neyman-Rubin Model of Causal Inference and Estimation Via Matching Methods∗
    The Neyman-Rubin Model of Causal Inference and Estimation via Matching Methods∗ Forthcoming in The Oxford Handbook of Political Methodology, Janet Box-Steffensmeier, Henry Brady, and David Collier, eds. Jasjeet S. Sekhon † 11/16/2007 (15:57) ∗I thank Henry Brady, Wendy Tam Cho, David Collier and Roc´ıo Titiunik for valuable comments on earlier drafts, and David Freedman, Walter R. Mebane, Jr., Donald Rubin and Jonathan N. Wand for many valuable discussions on these topics. All errors are my responsibility. †Associate Professor, Travers Department of Political Science, Survey Research Center, UC Berkeley. [email protected], HTTP://sekhon.berkeley.edu/, 510.642.9974. “Correlation does not imply causation” is one of the most repeated mantras in the social sciences, but its full implications are sobering and often ignored. The Neyman-Rubin model of causal inference helps to clarify some of the issues which arise. In this chapter, the model is briefly described, and some consequences of the model are outlined for both quantitative and qualitative research. The model has radical implications for work in the social sciences given current practices. Matching methods, which are usually motivated by the Neyman-Rubin model, are reviewed and their properties discussed. For example, applied researchers are often surprised to learn that even if the selection on observables assumption is satisfied, the commonly used matching methods will generally make even linear bias worse unless specific and often implausible assumptions are satisfied. Some of the intuition of matching methods, such as propensity score matching, should be familiar to social scientists because they share many features with Mill’s methods, or canons, of inference.
    [Show full text]
  • To Adjust Or Not to Adjust? Sensitivity Analysis of M-Bias and Butterfly-Bias
    To Adjust or Not to Adjust? Sensitivity Analysis of M-Bias and Butterfly-Bias The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Ding, Peng, and Luke W. Miratrix. 2015. “To Adjust or Not to Adjust? Sensitivity Analysis of M-Bias and Butterfly-Bias.” Journal of Causal Inference 3 (1) (January 1). doi:10.1515/jci-2013-0021. Published Version 10.1515/jci-2013-0021 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:25207409 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Open Access Policy Articles, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#OAP Page 1 of 24 Journal of Causal Inference 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Abstract 8 9 “M-Bias”, as it is called in the epidemiological literature, is the bias intro- 10 11 duced by conditioning on a pretreatment covariate due to a particular “M-Structure” 12 between two latent factors, an observed treatment, an outcome, and a “collider”. 13 This potential source of bias, which can occur even when the treatment and the out- 14 come are not confounded, has been a source of considerable controversy. We here 15 16 present formulae for identifying under which circumstances biases are inflated or 17 reduced. In particular, we show that the magnitude of M-Bias in Gaussian linear 18 structural equationFor models Review tends to be relatively Only small compared to confounding 19 bias, suggesting that it is generally not a serious concern in many applied settings.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the University of Chicago the Harris School of Public
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO THE HARRIS SCHOOL OF PUBLIC POLICY PPHA 42100: APPLIED ECONOMETRICS II Spring 2020: Tuesday and Thursday 9:30 – 10:50 am Instructor: Professor Koichiro Ito 157 Harris School [email protected] Office hours: Thursday 11-noon TA: TBA Office hours: TBA Course Description The goal of this course is for students to learn a set of statistical tools and research designs that are useful in conducting high-quality empirical research on topics in applied microeconomics and related fields. Since most applied economic research examines questions with direct policy implications, this course will focus on methods for estimating causal effects. This course differs from many other econometrics courses in that it is oriented towards applied practitioners rather than future econometricians. It therefore emphasizes research design (relative to statistical technique) and applications (relative to theoretical proofs), though it covers some of each. Prerequisites • PPHA420 (Applied Econometrics I) is the prerequisite for this course. Students should be familiar with PhD-level probability and statistics, matrix algebra, and the classical linear regression model at the level of PPHA420. In the Economics department, the equivalent level of preparation would be the 1st year Ph.D. econometrics coursework. • In general, I do not recommend taking this course if you have not taken PPHA420 or a Ph.D. level econometrics coursework. This course is a core course for Ph.D. students and MACRM students at Harris School. Therefore, although the course name 1 is Applied Econometrics, we'll cover a lot of theoretical econometrics with intensive math. Your problem sets and exams will be based on these materials.
    [Show full text]
  • Causality Causality Refers to the Relationship
    Causality Causality refers to the relationship between events where one set of events (the effects) is a direct consequence of another set of events (the causes). Causal inference is the process by which one can use data to make claims about causal relationships. Since inferring causal relationships is one of the central tasks of science, it is a topic that has been heavily debated in philosophy, statistics, and the scientific disciplines. In this article, we review the models of causation and tools for causal inference most prominent in the social sciences, including regularity approaches, associated with David Hume, and counterfactual models, associated with Jerzy Neyman, Donald Rubin, and David Lewis, among many others. One of the most notable developments in the study of causation is the increasing unification of disparate methods around a common conceptual and mathematical language that treats causality in counterfactual terms---i.e., the Neyman- Rubin model. We discuss how counterfactual models highlight the deep challenges involved in making the move from correlation to causation, particularly in the social sciences where controlled experiments are relatively rare. Regularity Models of Causation Until the advent of counterfactual models, causation was primarily defined in terms of observable phenomena. It was philosopher David Hume in the eighteenth century who began the modern tradition of regularity models of causation by defining causation in terms of repeated “conjunctions” of events. In An Enquiry into Human Understanding (1751), Hume argued that the labeling of two particular events as being causally related rested on an untestable metaphysical assumption. Consequently, Hume argued that causality could only be adequately defined in terms of empirical regularities involving classes of events.
    [Show full text]
  • Donald Rubin∗ Andrew Gelman† 3 Oct 2017
    Donald Rubin∗ Andrew Gelmany 3 Oct 2017 Donald Rubin (1943{) is a statistician who has made major contributions in statistical mod- eling, computation, and the foundations of causal inference. He is best known, perhaps, for the EM algorithm (a mathematical framework for iterative optimization, which has been useful for mixture models, hierarchical regression, and many other problems for which closed-form solutions are unavailable); multiple imputation as a method for accounting for uncertainty in statistical analysis with missing data; a Bayesian formulation of instrumental-variables analysis in economics; propensity scores for controlling for multiple predictors in observational studies; and, especially, the potential-outcomes framework of causal inference. Causal inference is central to social science. The effect of an intervention on an individual i (which could be a person, a firm, a school, a country, or whatever particular entity is being affected by the treatment) is defined as the difference in the outcome yi, comparing what would have happened under the intervention to what would have happened under the control. If these T C T C potential outcomes are labeled as yi and yi , then the causal effect for that individual is yi − yi . 0 1 But for any given individual i, we can never observe both potential outcomes yj and yj , thus the causal effect is impossible to directly measure. This is commonly referred to as the fundamental problem of causal inference, and it is at the core of modern economics and policy analysis. Resolutions to the fundamental problem of causal inference are called \identification strate- gies"; examples include linear regression, nonparametric regression, propensity score matching, instrumental variables, regression discontinuity, and difference in differences.
    [Show full text]
  • ASA 1999 JSM Teaching Causal Inference Dr. Donald Rubin in Experiments and Observational Studies
    ASA 1999 JSM Teaching Causal Inference Dr. Donald Rubin In Experiments and Observational Studies TEACHING CAUSAL INFERENCE IN EXPERIMENTS AND OBSERVATIONAL STUDIES Donald B. Rubin, Harvard University I Oxford St., 6th fl., Cambridge, MA 02138 Key Words: potential outcomes, Rubin Causal Model (RCM), Fisherian inference, Neymanian inference, Bayesian inference, experiments, observational studies, instrumental variables, noncompliance, statistical education Inference for causal effects is a critical activity in many branches of science and public policy. The field of statistics is the one field most suited to address such problems, whether from designed experiments or observational studies. Consequently, it is arguably essential that departments of statistics teach courses in causal inference to both graduate and undergraduate students. This presentation will discuss some aspects of such courses based on: a graduate level course taught at Harvard for a half dozen years, sometimes jointly with the Department of Economics (with Professor Guido Imbens, now at UCLA), and current plans for an undergraduate core course at Harvard University. An expanded version of this brief document will outline the courses' contents more completely. Moreover, a textbook by Imbens and Rubin, due to appear in 2000, will cover the basic material needed in both courses. The current course at Harvard begins with the definition of causal effects through potential outcomes. Causal estimands are comparisons of the outcomes that would have been observed under different exposures of units to treatments. This approach is commonly referred to as 'Rubin's Causal Model - RCM" (Holland, 1986), but the formal notation in the context of randomization-based inference in randomized experiments goes back to Neyman (1923), and the intuitive idea goes back centuries in various literatures; see also Fisher (1918), Tinbergen (1930) and Haavelmo (1944).
    [Show full text]
  • ^^.^-3 Causal Diagrams for Empirical Research C^-J-H Di^^I^)
    ^^. ^-3 Biometrika (1995), 82,4, pp. 669-710 Printed in Great Britain Causal diagrams for empirical research C^-j-h di^^i^) BY JUDEA PEARL Cognitive Systems Laboratory, Computer Science Department, University of California, Los Angeles, California 90024, U.S.A. SUMMARY The primary aim of this paper is to show how graphical models can be used as a mathematical language for integrating statistical and subject-matter information. In par- ticular, the paper develops a principled, nonparametric framework for causal inference, in which diagrams are queried to determine if the assumptions available are sufficient for identifying causal effects from nonexperimental data. If so the diagrams can be queried to produce mathematical expressions for causal effects in terms of observed distributions; otherwise, the diagrams can be queried to suggest additional observations or auxiliary experiments from which the desired inferences can be obtained. Some key words: Causal inference; Graph model; Structural equations; Treatment effect. 1. INTRODUCTION The tools introduced in this paper are aimed at helping researchers communicate quali- tative assumptions about cause-effect relationships, elucidate the ramifications of such assumptions, and derive causal inferences from a combination of assumptions, experi- ments, and data. The basic philosophy of the proposed method can best be illustrated through the classi- cal example due to Cochran (Wainer, 1989). Consider an experiment in which soil fumi- gants, X, are used to increase oat crop yields, Y, by controlling the eelworm population, Z, but may also have direct effects, both beneficial and adverse, on yields beside the control of eelworms. We wish to assess the total effect of the fumigants on yields when this study is complicated by several factors.
    [Show full text]
  • Potential Outcome and Directed Acyclic Graph Approaches to Causality: Relevance for Empirical Practice in Economics∗
    Potential Outcome and Directed Acyclic Graph Approaches to Causality: Relevance for Empirical Practice in Economics∗ Guido W. Imbensy August 2019 Abstract In this essay I discuss potential outcome and graphical approaches to causality, and their relevance for empirical work in economics. I review some of the work on directed acyclic graphs, including the recent \The Book of Why," ([Pearl and Mackenzie, 2018]). I also discuss the potential outcome framework developed by Rubin and coauthors, building on work by Neyman. I then discuss the relative merits of these approaches for empirical work in economics, focusing on the questions each answer well, and why much of the the work in economics is closer in spirit to the potential outcome framework. ∗I am grateful for help with the graphs by Michael Pollmann and for comments by Alberto Abadie, Jason Abaluck, Josh Angrist, Gary Chamberlain, Stephen Chaudoin, Rebecca Diamond, Dean Eckles, Ernst Fehr, Avi Feller, Paul Goldsmith-Pinkham, Chuck Manski, Paul Milgrom, Evan Munro, Franco Perrachi, Michael Pollmann, Jasjeet Sekhon, Samuel Skoda, Korinayo Thompson, and Heidi Williams. They are not responsible for any of the views expressed here. yProfessor of Economics, Graduate School of Business, and Department of Economics, Stanford University, SIEPR, and NBER, [email protected]. 1 Introduction Causal Inference (CI) in observational studies has been an integral part of econometrics since its start as a separate field in the 1920s and 1930s. The simultaneous equations methods developed by [Tinbergen, 1930], [Wright, 1928], and [Haavelmo, 1943] and their successors in the context of supply and demand settings were from the beginning, and continue to be, explicitly focused on causal questions.
    [Show full text]