Electoral Reform

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Electoral Reform Electoral Reform Max Taubenberger July, 2020 Executive Summary The United States once prided itself on being a bastion of democ- racy for the world to see. The resilience of our democracy, like so many of our institutions has atrophied and become sclerotic and ineffective. As of 2020, the US comes in at a measly 25th place on the Democ- racy Index1. Furthermore, the average American voter and grassroots organizations have little to no influence over the direction of public policy.2 take a cursory overview of the current circumstances and pro- pose several paths for reform and many different options that can be taken at the municipal, state, and federal levels to help restore the vitality of American democracy. 1https://infographics.economist.com/2020/democracy-index-2019/map.html 2https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/perspectives-on-politics/ article/testing-theories-of-american-politics-elites-interest-groups-and-average-citizens/ 62327F513959D0A304D4893B382B992B 1 Voting Systems 1.1 Presidential/Executive Presidential elections in the United States are an outlier in that they're the only major office that isn't directly elected by the people. Instead, there are electors (of which there are currently 538) that are sent to the Electoral College. Throughout the history of the US, the method of electoral appor- tionment has varied as the constitution gives full levity to states in how they choose to select electors. It wasn't until the election of 1872 that all states apportioned their electors predicated upon the popular vote in the en- tire state. Two states today (Nebraska and Maine) use a more proportional method where some electors are chosen by the popular vote in a congres- sional district. Like nearly all other elections, people cast a ballot with the plurality vote or first past the post (FPTP) method. These factors lead one to believe that a candidate has far more popular support than they really do (Bill Clinton never got more than 50% of the popular vote). There are several reform recommendations that would make presidential elections more open, transparent, and allow for more and higher quality candidates to have a fighting chance. First, change how electors are apportioned. The current methodology of electoral apportionment is inadequate for reflecting the will of the people. There are three options, each successive one being arguably bolder than the last. Move to proportional allocation of electors Move to the National Popular Vote (NPV) compact Eliminate the Electoral College The first two options are constitutionally sound3 as the constitution has no mandate on the states to apportion in a particular way as previously mentioned. Electors in this proportional allocation scenario would be done by a state by state basis (rather than nationally); electors would be chosen by using the total vote share of a candidate and taking it as a proportion of the total electors and rounding to the nearest whole integer (i.e Hillary Clinton would receive 16 electoral votes in Texas out of 38 with 43.24% of the vote, Trump would get 20 with 52.23% of the vote). The advantage is some- what better representation overall as candidates still get some electors, even if they don't get a plurality of votes. It is also the case that the Democratic 3There is a lot of legal debate over NPV 2 presidential primary uses a proportional allocation method for electors to the National Convention by state, so there is already some precedence for a method like this. The massive downside of this method is that it would likely lead to a number of elections determined by the House of Representatives as the Electoral College mandates that a candidate must have a majority of Electoral College votes to avoid a Contingent Election. In some cases, it would lead to just as unrepresentative (or even more so) a result than if we used the present system. The National Popular Vote compact is an interstate agreement among a number of states and the District of Columbia to award all of their electors to the winner of the popular vote nationally. Some clear advantages to this method are the likelihood of increased civic engagement, upholding the principle of voting equality (that some people don't have a stronger say than others), and increase the security of elections by reducing incentives to engage in suppression or misinformation campaigns from perni- cious actors, domestic or international. Some people worry that it "reduces the voices of small states". When borne out, this becomes a tenuous claim as the Senate is an institution that was designed to give overwhelming weight to small states. For example, a state like Wyoming with a population less than 600,000 inhabitants gets two senators (the same as California, which has nearly 40 million inhabitants) and a representative in the House of Rep- resentatives. Furthermore, the current system forces candidates to spend nearly all their time in swing states (typically in the most populated areas of those states) to try to tilt the popular vote of 5-10 states. Rural areas aren't visited, because the return on investment is parsimonious regardless of what electoral system you utilize; there just aren't enough people there to justify the candidate to spend a majority of time in those areas. For example, both Trump and Clinton spent the majority of their time in Pennsylvania, Ohio, Florida, and North Carolina in the final two months. Neither even visited 27 states, most of which were more rural states. Having to campaign for the entire country, and not just a handful of swing states would make can- didates have to earn the trust and support of Americans at large, not just a few. The third option is abolishing the Electoral College. The effects of this and the second option are nearly functionally identical. Abolition would be a considerably more arduous task and require the ratification of a 28th amendement, requiring a 2/3rd vote in both congressional chambers and 38 out of 50 states approving it. Unlike what some claim, the popular support for removing the EC entirely has been pretty high historically; support for abolition was in the 70s for much of the 1970s and 63% of Americans in 2013 still wanted to abolish it. The hyper-partisan election of 2016 lessened its support to a near tie, but it has rebounded to 55% as of 2019. Notably, more voters in both the Democratic and Republican parties supported amending 3 the constitution over an interstate compact. Figure 1: Support was high in the 1970s 4 Figure 2: 2013 sentiments 5 Figure 3: Support for amending is higher than the NPV The Second major change necessary is altering how primaries are done. The core components that should be altered are the voting system used, the timing, and the standards of debates. Regarding voting systems, all 50 states need to move to a direct voter election rather than the kludge that is caucuses (as we all saw in the bungled affair that was the Iowa Democratic Caucus). Furthermore, the voting method used must change away from FPTP. (as it should in the general as well). Here are a list of single winner voting methods that are available for use 6 First Past The Post (FPTP)/Plurality Voting Ranked Choice/Instant Runoff Voting (IRV) Borda Count Condorcet Range/Score Voting Approval Voting As follows is a concise description of each. Range voting is a voting method that involves scoring a list of candidates on a "range" (i.e 0-5 or 0-9). The scores are then either averaged or added and the candidate with the highest score is the winner. Approval voting is a degraded version of range voting where voters can either "approve" or "disapprove" the list of candidates standing for election (essentially like range voting if the range was 0-1). Like range, the highest count yields the winner. Plurality requires little introduction as it's the standard method for nearly all elections in Canada, the UK, and the US; voters mark one candidate and whoever gets the most votes wins. Instant Runoff Voting involves 3 or more candidates where voters do a preferential rank of each candidate. If no candidate gets an outright majority, the candidate with the least amount of votes is eliminated. The voters who had the eliminated candidate as their first choice have their votes added to their second choice. This process is iterated until a winner has been selected. Borda count is equivalent on the voter side as IRV (you rank candidates from 1 to n), but votes are tallied differently; the winner is calculated by awarding points in reverse proportion to the ranking voters assigned that candidate. For example, with n candidates, we award n points to first preferences, then n - 1 for second preferences, and so on until bottom preferences, which receive only 1 point. The points are tallied, and the one with the highest score wins. Borda is notable in that it is more consensus based than majoritarian. Condorcet describes several methods in which the winner is the candidate that can win a majority in any pairwise match with another candidate (against every other candidate one on one, they win). In evaluating the efficacy of these methods, there are a few salient param- eters to maximize for: minimizing Bayesian regret, ease of administering, and ease of comprehension for voters. The first parameter warrants consideration; Bayesian regret can be defined as the discrepancy of satisfaction choosing the selected candidate in a given voting system and the best candidate. It can be measured by running Monte Carlo simulations of virtual elections millions of times.
Recommended publications
  • Computational Social Choice
    (Computational) Social Choice Michal Jakob Artificial Intelligence Center, Dept. of Computer Science and Engineering, FEE, Czech Technical University AE4M36MAS Autumn 2018 - Lecture 11 Motivating Example top choice ranking > > > > > > > > > ? > ? > ? > ? > > > > > > OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Social Choice Social choice theory is a theoretical framework for making rational collective decisions based on the preferences of multiple agents. (does not consider payments: settings with payments auctions) OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Wide Range of Applications Elections Joint plans (MAS) Resource allocation Recommendation and reputation systems Human computation (crowdsourcing) Webpage ranking and meta-search engines Discussion forums OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Key Questions What does it mean to make collective rational choices? Which formal properties should such choices satisfy? Which of these properties can be satisfied simultaneously? How difficult is it to compute collective choices? Can voters benefit by lying about their preferences? OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Basic Definitions Social Choice OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Social Welfare Function Consider ▪ a finite set 푁 = {1, … , 푛} of at least two agents (also called individuals or voters), and ▪ a finite universe 푈 of at least two alternatives (also called candidates). ▪ Each agent 푖 has preferences over the alternatives in 푈, which are represented by a transitive
    [Show full text]
  • Ethereum Classic Treasury System Proposal
    ETHEREUM CLASSIC TREASURY SYSTEM PROPOSAL RESEARCH REPORT March 7th 2017 The Veritas Team Dmytro Kaidalov, Lyudmila Kovalchuk, Andrii Nastenko, Mariia Rodinko, Oleksiy Shevtsov, Roman Oliynykov IOHK.io Abstract We propose the Ethereum Classic Treasury System (ECTS) whose main purpose is to establish a decentralized funding mechanism for development and maintenance of the Ethereum Classic platform. Anyone can submit a project proposal and the stakeholders will decide on its necessity through a transparent voting procedure. The system is fully verifiable, having no significant influence on ETC performance. The report also takes into account ECIP 1017 that changes Ethereum Classic monetary policy and emission schedule. We expect that the ECTS implementation will increase stability and the outlook of the system, providing additional benefits both for stakeholders and miners from a more stable and predictable system. 1 Contents 1 Introduction 4 1.1 Objective and desired properties of the treasury system..........................................4 1.2 Overview of the proposed treasury system......................5 2 Ethereum Classic Treasury System6 2.1 Ethereum Classic Blockchain.............................7 2.2 Basic Treasury Model.................................8 2.2.1 Funding epochs.................................8 2.2.2 Epoch stages..................................9 2.3 Proposal submission.................................. 12 2.3.1 Proposal ballot formation........................... 12 2.3.2 Submission rules and cost........................... 13 2.3.3 Miscellaneous: revocation and money reducing............... 13 2.4 Voters.......................................... 13 2.4.1 Deposit submission and redemption..................... 14 2.4.2 Incentives.................................... 15 2.5 Treasury source.................................... 16 2.5.1 Funding within the ECIP-1017 monetary policy............... 16 2.5.2 Legacy monetary policy............................ 18 2.6 Election method...................................
    [Show full text]
  • Utilities, Preferences and Choice
    Utilities, Preferences and Choice By: Martin Kroh and Cees van der Eijk (both ASCoR/University of Amsterdam) First draft — Please comment copyright © 2003 by Martin Kroh & Cees van der Eijk Paper prepared for the joint sessions of workshops of the ECPR in Edinburgh, March 2003. Direct correspondence to: Martin Kroh. Universiteit van Amsterdam/ ASCoR. Oudezijds Achterburgwal 237, 1012 DL Amsterdam, the Netherlands. [email protected] Cees van der Eijk. Universiteit van Amsterdam/ ASCoR. Oudezijds Achterburgwal 237, 1012 DL Amsterdam, the Netherlands. [email protected]. 1 In this paper we argue that theories of party choice are implicitly not about choice, but about electoral preferences or utilities. This distinction is not trivial, as individual choice can be deduced from individual preferences or utilities, whereas the reverse is not necessarily true. In spite of this, a large part of empirical electoral research is (implicitly) based on the analysis of ‘revealed’ preferences, i.e. preferences that have been deduced from choice by using interpersonal comparison to make up the informational deficit at the individual level. We argue that the risks of this approach can be avoided by an alternative approach, that entails the empirical observation of electoral utility. A practical procedure for doing so is presented, and some validating analyses are reported. 1. Individual Choice Theory Theories of individual choice behavior conceptualize choice as a function of the characteristics of the decision maker, of the set of available alternatives and their attributes, and a decision rule. Given a fixed set of alternatives and their attributes, individual choice is commonly construed in two steps.
    [Show full text]
  • Crowdsourcing Applications of Voting Theory Daniel Hughart
    Crowdsourcing Applications of Voting Theory Daniel Hughart 5/17/2013 Most large scale marketing campaigns which involve consumer participation through voting makes use of plurality voting. In this work, it is questioned whether firms may have incentive to utilize alternative voting systems. Through an analysis of voting criteria, as well as a series of voting systems themselves, it is suggested that though there are no necessarily superior voting systems there are likely enough benefits to alternative systems to encourage their use over plurality voting. Contents Introduction .................................................................................................................................... 3 Assumptions ............................................................................................................................... 6 Voting Criteria .............................................................................................................................. 10 Condorcet ................................................................................................................................. 11 Smith ......................................................................................................................................... 14 Condorcet Loser ........................................................................................................................ 15 Majority ...................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • D21 – Janecek Method
    D21 { Janeˇcekmethod Karel Janeˇcek,PhD. December 28, 2020 Is it possible to find a voting system which maintains an equality of voting rights and at the same time gives greater impact to well- informed and engaged voters? Yes, it is possible. Our proposed vot- ing system solves this apparent paradox. In addition to this principal benefit, it also enables voters to re-balance the political spectrum away from extremists and reduce the threat of dishonest or corrupt political actors. 1 Representative democracy In 1947, Winston Churchill famously declared: \It has been said that democracy is the worst form of government, except all the others that have been tried." Is democracy really as weak, ineffective and unsatisfactory a form of government as it often appears? Might a better system than democracy exist? If not, does it mean that we, as a human society, must endure the ill effects of a system performing far under its potential? It is the author's core conviction that only systems with a democratic anchor will work properly in the long run. As soon as the essential principle of equal suffrage is breached, the risk that the social system will eventually degenerate into some form of authoritarianism or dictatorship, or another regime which discriminates against and mistreats certain individuals or groups of citizens, is significant. Such a system will necessarily be unstable from a long-term perspective and will lead to major social conflicts. Selection of high-quality political representation is a key factor for reaching the fairest and most effective functioning of society as a whole.
    [Show full text]
  • Landry, Celeste
    HB 5404: Study Ranked-Choice Voting in CT, Committee on Government Administration and Elections March 4, 2020 testimony by Celeste Landry, 745 University Ave, Boulder, CO 80302 Bio: I have been researching voting methods since 2012 and have given a variety of Voting Methods presentations including at the 2018 LWVUS convention, the 2019 Free and Equal Electoral Reform Symposium and the 2020 CO Dept of State Alternative Voting Method Stakeholder Group meeting. Four Proposed Amendments: Amendments #1 and #2 below address language in the current text, but Amendments #3 and #4 provide for better and broader resolutions to the bill’s limitations. Issue #1. The description of ranked-choice voting (RCV) in HB5404 is too limited. For instance, the 2018 Maine Congressional District 2 election would NOT fit the definition below: 6 are defeated and until one candidate receives over fifty per cent of the 7 votes cast, and (3) the candidate receiving over fifty per cent of the votes 8 cast is deemed to have been elected to such office. Such study shall Example: The Maine CD2 winner, Jared Golden, did NOT receive over 50% of the votes cast (144,813 out of 289,624). More people preferred Golden’s opponents to Golden. In the last round, Golden received over 50% of the votes if you only count the non-exhausted ballots. The definition of RCV in the bill effectively claims that more than two thousand cast votes were actually not cast! 2018 Maine CD2 election results: https://www.maine.gov/sos/cec/elec/results/results18.html#Nov6 Resolution: The definition should read 6 are defeated and until one candidate receives over fifty per cent of the 7 votes cast on non-exhausted ballots, and (3) the candidate receiving over fifty per cent of the votes 8 cast on non-exhausted ballots is deemed to have been elected to such office.
    [Show full text]
  • Transnational Electoral Lists
    Transnational electoral lists Ways to Europeanise elections to the European Parliament STUDY EPRS | European Parliamentary Research Service Author: Maria Diaz Crego Members' Research Service PE 679.084 – February 2021 EN Transnational electoral lists Ways to Europeanise elections to the European Parliament The creation of a pan-European constituency, comprising the whole territory of the European Union, in which a number of Members of the European Parliament would be elected from transnational electoral lists, figures high among proposals to enhance the European dimension of the elections to the European Parliament. Although the idea to create a European constituency gained momentum with 73 seats in the European Parliament due to become vacant as a consequence of the United Kingdom's withdrawal from the European Union, the proposal is far from new and has been debated in the European institutions and academia since the 1990s. This paper analyses the main proposals to create a European constituency (or constituencies) that have been discussed in the European Parliament, other European institutions and academia, and details the legal changes that would be needed at European and national level to bring the idea to fruition. EPRS | European Parliamentary Research Service AUTHOR María Díaz Crego, Members' Research Service, European Parliamentary Research Service (EPRS), European Parliament. Giulio Sabbati, Samy Chahri and Lucille Killmayer (EPRS) are responsible for the graphics. The author would like to thank the following policy analyst from the Members' Research Service for providing information in relation to the following Member States: the Netherlands and Finland (Ingeborg Odink); Czechia (Marketa Pape); Germany (Hendrik Alexander Mildebrath); Luxembourg (Marie-Laure Augère- Granier); Malta (Denise Chircop); Hungary (Gabriella Zana-Szabo); Poland (Rafal Manko); Croatia (Kristina Grosek); Slovenia (Anja Radjenovic).
    [Show full text]
  • Least-Resistance Consensus: Applying Via Negativa to Decision-Making ∗
    Least-Resistance Consensus: applying Via Negativa to decision-making ∗ Aleksander Kampa [email protected] July 2019 Abstract This paper introduces Least-Resistance Consensus (LRC), a cardinal voting system that focuses entirely on measuring resistance. It is based on the observation that our \negative gut feeling" is often a strong, reliable indicator and that our dislikes are stronger than our likes. Measuring resistance rather than acceptance is therefore likely to provide a more accurate gauge when a choice between multiple options has to be made. But LRC is not just a voting system. It encourages an iterative process of consensus- seeking in which possible options are proposed, discussed, amended and then either discarded or kept for a further round of voting. LRC also proposes to take the structure of group opinion into account, with a view not only to minimizing overall group resistance but also to avoiding, as much as possible, there being sizeable groups of strong dissenters. 1 Introduction In Western societies, the opinion that parliamentary democracy based on majority rule is the best possible form of government is widely held. We do know that minority opinions are not always represented and, as is the case in the UK with its first-past-the-post system, a party can gain an absolute majority with far fewer than half of the votes, but this seems to be considered a minor issue. Not just in government but at all levels of society, majority voting holds sway. Members of tribal societies in Africa and elsewhere, who are used to the lengthy and complex processes needed for reaching a wide consensus among community members, would probably call the idea of majority voting primitive.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mathematics of Voting: Paradox, Deception, and Chaos
    The Mathematics of Voting: Paradox, deception, and chaos Marcus Pivato Department of Mathematics, Trent University http://xaravve.trentu.ca/voting.pdf May 8, 2008 Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... ◮ ...Olympic judges must give the gold medal to Argentina, Brazil, Canada, or Denmark. Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... ◮ ...Olympic judges must give the gold medal to Argentina, Brazil, Canada, or Denmark. ◮ ...A committee must award a prize to one of four contestants Ariadne, Brynn, Chloe, or Desdemona. Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... ◮ ...Olympic judges must give the gold medal to Argentina, Brazil, Canada, or Denmark. ◮ ...A committee must award a prize to one of four contestants Ariadne, Brynn, Chloe, or Desdemona. ◮ ...Pick one dessert for the dinner party: Apple cobbler, Banana cream pie, Chocolate cake, or Dulce de leche. Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... ◮ ...Olympic judges must give the gold medal to Argentina, Brazil, Canada, or Denmark. ◮ ...A committee must award a prize to one of four contestants Ariadne, Brynn, Chloe, or Desdemona. ◮ ...Pick one dessert for the dinner party: Apple cobbler, Banana cream pie, Chocolate cake, or Dulce de leche. ◮ ...An federal election with four candidates: LiberAl, Bloc Quebecois, Conservative, or New Democratic. Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D.
    [Show full text]
  • Elections and Strategic Voting: Condorcet and Borda * Partha
    Elections and Strategic Voting: Condorcet and Borda * Partha Dasgupta† and Eric Maskin†† Preliminary August 2019 * This is a revised version of a manuscript first drafted in 2010. We thank Sergiu Hart for useful comments and Cecilia Johnson for research assistance. † Faculty of Economics and Politics, University of Cambridge, Cambridge UK. [email protected] †† Department of Economics, Harvard University, Cambridge MA 02138 USA. [email protected] Higher School of Economics, Moscow 1 Abstract We show that majority rule is uniquely characterized among voting rules by strategy-proofness, the Pareto principle, anonymity, neutrality, independence of irrelevant alternatives, and decisiveness. Furthermore, there is an extension of majority rule that satisfies these axioms on any preference domain without Condorcet cycles when voters are sufficiently risk-averse. If independence is dropped, then, for the case of three candidates, the remaining axioms characterize exactly two voting rules – majority rule and rank-order voting – on rich domains (domains for which no candidate is always extremal, i.e., best or worst). 2 1. Introduction How should society choose public officials such as presidents? The obvious answer is to hold elections. However, there are many possible election methods, called voting rules, to choose from. Here are a few examples. In plurality rule, each citizen votes for a candidate, and the winner is the candidate with the most votes, even if short of majority. In runoff voting there are two rounds. First, each citizen votes for one candidate. If some candidate gets a majority, she wins. Otherwise, the top two vote-getters face each other in a runoff, which determines the winner.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparative Table on Proportional Electoral Systems
    Strasbourg, 28 November 2014 CDL(2014)058 Study No. 764/2014 Or. bil. EUROPEAN COMMISSION FOR DEMOCRACY THROUGH LAW (VENICE COMMISSION) COMPARATIVE TABLE ON PROPORTIONAL ELECTORAL SYSTEMS: THE ALLOCATION OF SEATS INSIDE THE LISTS (OPEN/CLOSED LISTS) This document will not be distributed at the meeting. Please bring this copy. www.venice.coe.int CDL(2014)058 - 2 - Proportional systems, Proportional systems: Electoral systems, Proportional systems, methods of allocation of Country Legal basis System of representation closed or open party main relevant provision(s) methods of allocation of seats seats list system? inside the lists Constitution Proportional system: Constitution Largest remainder Closed Party List No preference Article 64 All the 140 members of the Article 64 (amended by Law no. d'Hondt, then Sainte-Laguë system Not indicated in the law but Parliament are elected through 9904, dated 21.04.2008) formulas No preference implicitly clear that there is Electoral Code a proportional representation 1. The Assembly consists of 140 no preference. (approved by Law system within constituencies deputies, elected by a proportional See the separate document for no. 10 019, dated 29 corresponding to the 12 system with multi-member electoral Articles 162-163. December 2008, administrative regions. zones. and amended by The threshold to win 2. A multi-member electoral zone According to the stipulations in Law no. 74/2012, parliamentary representation is coincides with the administrative Articles 162 and 163 of the Electoral dated 19 July 2012) 3 percent for political parties division of one of the levels of Code, the number of seats is Articles 162 & 163 and 5 per cent for pre-election administrative-territorial calculated for each of the coalitions coalitions.
    [Show full text]
  • Ordinal Versus Cardinal Voting Rules: a Mechanism Design Approach
    ORDINAL VERSUS CARDINAL VOTING RULES: A MECHANISM DESIGN APPROACH [JOB MARKET PAPER] SEMIN KIM November 8, 2013 Abstract. We consider the performance and incentive compatibility of voting rules in a Bayesian environment: agents have independent private values, there are at least three alternatives, and monetary transfers are prohibited. First, we show that in a neutral environment, i.e., when alternatives are symmetric ex-ante, essentially any ex- ante Pareto efficient ordinal rule is incentive compatible. But, importantly, we can improve upon ordinal rules. We show that we can design an incentive compatible cardinal rule which achieves higher utilitarian social welfare than any ordinal rule. This cardinal rule, applied in an environment with exactly three alternatives, is closely connected to the (A,B)-scoring rules in Myerson (2002). Finally, we show that in the non-neutral environment introduced in Majumdar and Sen (2004), every incentive compatible ordinal rule on the domain of single-peaked preferences is a peak-only rule. Keywords: Ordinal rule, Pareto efficiency, Incentive compatibility, Bayesian mechanism design. JEL Classification: C72, D01, D02, D72, D82. I am greatly indebted to Yaron Azrieli for his thoughtful guidance. I am also grateful to Paul Healy, James Peck, Katherine Baldiga Coffman, Christian Hellwig, Dan Levin, Caleb Cox, Ian Krajbich, Tilman Börgers, Roberto Serrano, Jack Rouzer, Robert Munk, and seminar participants at The Ohio State University Theory and Experiments Group Meetings, 2013 North America Summer Meeting of Econometric Society at University of Southern California, and 6th Alexander Hamilton Center Con- ference on Political Economy at New York University for their helpful comments and suggestions.
    [Show full text]