Least-Resistance Consensus: Applying Via Negativa to Decision-Making ∗

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Least-Resistance Consensus: Applying Via Negativa to Decision-Making ∗ Least-Resistance Consensus: applying Via Negativa to decision-making ∗ Aleksander Kampa [email protected] July 2019 Abstract This paper introduces Least-Resistance Consensus (LRC), a cardinal voting system that focuses entirely on measuring resistance. It is based on the observation that our \negative gut feeling" is often a strong, reliable indicator and that our dislikes are stronger than our likes. Measuring resistance rather than acceptance is therefore likely to provide a more accurate gauge when a choice between multiple options has to be made. But LRC is not just a voting system. It encourages an iterative process of consensus- seeking in which possible options are proposed, discussed, amended and then either discarded or kept for a further round of voting. LRC also proposes to take the structure of group opinion into account, with a view not only to minimizing overall group resistance but also to avoiding, as much as possible, there being sizeable groups of strong dissenters. 1 Introduction In Western societies, the opinion that parliamentary democracy based on majority rule is the best possible form of government is widely held. We do know that minority opinions are not always represented and, as is the case in the UK with its first-past-the-post system, a party can gain an absolute majority with far fewer than half of the votes, but this seems to be considered a minor issue. Not just in government but at all levels of society, majority voting holds sway. Members of tribal societies in Africa and elsewhere, who are used to the lengthy and complex processes needed for reaching a wide consensus among community members, would probably call the idea of majority voting primitive. It might even be difficult to convince some of them that such a patently absurd concept is actually used by humans. Majority voting is, by its very nature, an antagonistic process. It is about one group winning a debate by sheer force of numbers: a more civilized version of \might is right". There are, of course, ∗Research supported by Fantom Foundation 1 alternatives to majority voting that offer more nuanced procedures, but most are influenced by the concept of majority voting. Also, there is always the underlying and unspoken positive bias: the focus is on identifying the best solution. It is the positive, the affirmative, that underpins most of Western thinking. In this paper, we will present the Least-Resistance Consensus (LRC) method, which focuses on determining which solution encounters the least resistance from a group. To begin with, however, we present a brief historical perspective of voting research. 2 Traditional Voting Systems 2.1 Some famous names in voting theory The question of fair voting is probably as old as humanity. Plato proposed a multi-stage voting process more than 2,000 years ago, and Pliny the Younger wrote about strategic voting in the Roman Senate around 100 AD, as noted in Szpiro [1]. Many famous people have worked on election methods: the Medieval polymath and mystic Ramon Llull, the philosopher and cardinal Nicolaus Cusanus, the scientist Pierre-Simon Laplace and the Reverend Charles Dodgson, better known by his pen name, Lewis Carroll. Two other names that are associated with the history of voting systems are the Marquis de Con- dorcet and Jean-Charles de Borda. They were contemporaries, and, indeed, the two traditional election systems are associated with their names. 2.2 The Condorcet and Borda methods Apart from simple majority-voting, the limitations of which have been recognised since Antiquity, two classical voting methods have emerged. The first approach consists of asking voters to compare all possible pairs of candidates successively. The candidate who wins the most head-to-head contests wins the election (there are various ways to handle ties). This method was initially described by Llull and was later proposed by Condorcet. It is now often referred as the Condorcet method [2] or Copeland's method [3]1. If one candidate wins all head-to-head contests, she is called the Condorcet winner. In the second approach, voters are asked to rank all candidates, with the lowest-ranked candidate given 1 point, the second-lowest two points, etc. The winner is the candidate with the highest Borda count, which is the sum of points received from all voters. This method, called Borda's method, was used in the Roman Senate \beginning around 105 AD" [4]; it was proposed by Cusanus to elect Holy Roman Emperors2 and reinvented by Borda. Neither of these approaches is without drawbacks. For example, the Condorcet method sometimes does not yield a winner or a consistent ordering of the candidates - this is known as the Condorcet paradox. With Borda's method, the withdrawal of even a low-ranked candidate can sometimes change the winner of the election. To overcome such problematic behaviours, many variations of the Condorcet and Borda methods have been devised, including multi-stage methods. None of these voting methods proved to be without flaws. A very accessible introduction to the problems and paradoxes of the traditional voting systems is given in Powers [5] and in chapter 3 of Balinksi and Laraki [6]. 1In fact, there are many variations of the Condorcet method, with Copeland's method being the simplest. 2His proposal was not adopted. 2 2.3 Arrow's impossibility theorem The reason why no perfect solution was ever found in the traditional setting became clear in 1951 when Kenneth Arrow published his famous impossibility theorem. Assume that voters are asked to (strictly) rank at least three candidates. We require a ranking function that ranks all candidates and satisfies the following criteria: A1. The function produces a ranking for all possible inputs (\unrestricted domain"); A2. if all voters prefer A to B, then A will rank higher than B (\unanimous decision"); A3. the relative rank of A and B does not depend on any other candidate (\independence of irrelevant alternatives", or IIA); A4. no single voter determines the outcome of the vote (\nondictatorial"). What Arrow proved is that such a function does not exist. For this and other work, he later received a Nobel prize in economics. The usual way of proving Arrow's theorem is to show that any ranking function satisfying A1, A2 and A3 is, in fact, equal to the ranking of one specific voter and ignores the input of all other voters, thus failing condition A4. See Geanakoplos [7] (3rd proof) for a short and extremely elegant proof; Fey [8] also provides a simple proof. Note that the impossibility holds even without requiring other conditions. For example, one desirable feature of a voting system is \monotonicity": placing a winning candidate higher should never cause that candidate to lose. So if there is a configuration where candidate A is ranked first by the ranking function and one or more voters place that candidate higher, then this should not cause A to be ranked lower. Several instant-runoff methods violate monotonicity. Another desirable feature is resistance to strategic manipulation. 2.4 A note on modern democracies The inconsistencies observed in various Condorcet and Borda voting systems are quite minor compared to seemingly unfair results seen in democracies that use first-past-the-post voting. In the 1983 UK general election, the Alliance of the Liberals and SDP received over 25% of the popular vote but won only 3.5% of the seats (23 out of 650) in Parliament. For Labour, 28% of the popular vote translated into 32% of the seats (209 seats), while the Conservatives received 42% of the vote and had an absolute majority of 61% of the seats in Parliament. In the 2007 presidential election in France, it is considered almost certain that Fran¸coisBayrou would have won one-to-one against any of the other candidates. But because Bayrou did not advance to the second round, Nicolas Sarkozy became president. In the 2015 UK general election, Labour added 0.74 million voters but lost 26 seats. The Conser- vatives gained 24 seats while adding only 0.63 million voters and obtained a slim parliamentary majority. UKIP received 12.6% of the popular vote but ended up with only one of 650 seats in Parliament - a mere 0.15%. It is interesting, and somewhat puzzling, to note that the Condorcet and Borda methods, whatever their flaws, are often superior to voting methods used in some democratic countries today. 3 From ordinal to cardinal voting In their book \Majority Judgement", published in 2010, Balinski and Laraki argue that voting theory should be looking beyond traditional methods ([6] p. 56): Perhaps the most astonishing aspect of the theory of voting is that despite Arrow's celebrated impossibility theorem and others, the search for a best method has continued 3 within the basic framework first conceived by Llull and Cusanus almost a millennium ago (...) We already know that plurality voting is highly problematic. Ordinal voting, which ranks candi- dates, is better but also flawed. We need to focus on cardinal voting, which evaluates candidates3 rather than ranking them. The question is: why has it taken so long for this realisation to sink in? Arrow explicitly rejected cardinal utility in his famous book, Social Choice and Individual Values, which was published in 1951. Only two years later, however, Harsanyi, also a future Nobel prize winner, made a strong case for cardinal utility [9], and in 1955 essentially showed that Arrow's impossibility theorem does not hold when cardinal utility is used [10]. Writing in 2005, Hillinger [11] provides interesting background information and describes how Arrow, as well as others, failed to take much notice of Harsanyi's work for decades { even though Arrow was Harsanyi's thesis advisor! Hillinger concludes his historical perspective by writing: Given the long history of voting theory, it is surprising that the first step towards UV4, in the form of AV5, was taken as late as the 1970s and the second step, the introduction of a scale with arbitrary divisions, was taken in 2000 with Smith's paper on RV6.
Recommended publications
  • Computational Social Choice
    (Computational) Social Choice Michal Jakob Artificial Intelligence Center, Dept. of Computer Science and Engineering, FEE, Czech Technical University AE4M36MAS Autumn 2018 - Lecture 11 Motivating Example top choice ranking > > > > > > > > > ? > ? > ? > ? > > > > > > OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Social Choice Social choice theory is a theoretical framework for making rational collective decisions based on the preferences of multiple agents. (does not consider payments: settings with payments auctions) OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Wide Range of Applications Elections Joint plans (MAS) Resource allocation Recommendation and reputation systems Human computation (crowdsourcing) Webpage ranking and meta-search engines Discussion forums OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Key Questions What does it mean to make collective rational choices? Which formal properties should such choices satisfy? Which of these properties can be satisfied simultaneously? How difficult is it to compute collective choices? Can voters benefit by lying about their preferences? OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Basic Definitions Social Choice OPEN INFORMATICS / MULTIAGENT SYSTEMS: SOCIAL CHOICE Social Welfare Function Consider ▪ a finite set 푁 = {1, … , 푛} of at least two agents (also called individuals or voters), and ▪ a finite universe 푈 of at least two alternatives (also called candidates). ▪ Each agent 푖 has preferences over the alternatives in 푈, which are represented by a transitive
    [Show full text]
  • Governance in Decentralized Networks
    Governance in decentralized networks Risto Karjalainen* May 21, 2020 Abstract. Effective, legitimate and transparent governance is paramount for the long-term viability of decentralized networks. If the aim is to design such a governance model, it is useful to be aware of the history of decision making paradigms and the relevant previous research. Towards such ends, this paper is a survey of different governance models, the thinking behind such models, and new tools and structures which are made possible by decentralized blockchain technology. Governance mechanisms in the wider civil society are reviewed, including structures and processes in private and non-profit governance, open-source development, and self-managed organisations. The alternative ways to aggregate preferences, resolve conflicts, and manage resources in the decentralized space are explored, including the possibility of encoding governance rules as automatically executed computer programs where humans or other entities interact via a protocol. Keywords: Blockchain technology, decentralization, decentralized autonomous organizations, distributed ledger technology, governance, peer-to-peer networks, smart contracts. 1. Introduction This paper is a survey of governance models in decentralized networks, and specifically in networks which make use of blockchain technology. There are good reasons why governance in decentralized networks is a topic of considerable interest at present. Some of these reasons are ideological. We live in an era where detailed information about private individuals is being collected and traded, in many cases without the knowledge or consent of the individuals involved. Decentralized technology is seen as a tool which can help protect people against invasions of privacy. Decentralization can also be viewed as a reaction against the overreach by state and industry.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethereum Classic Treasury System Proposal
    ETHEREUM CLASSIC TREASURY SYSTEM PROPOSAL RESEARCH REPORT March 7th 2017 The Veritas Team Dmytro Kaidalov, Lyudmila Kovalchuk, Andrii Nastenko, Mariia Rodinko, Oleksiy Shevtsov, Roman Oliynykov IOHK.io Abstract We propose the Ethereum Classic Treasury System (ECTS) whose main purpose is to establish a decentralized funding mechanism for development and maintenance of the Ethereum Classic platform. Anyone can submit a project proposal and the stakeholders will decide on its necessity through a transparent voting procedure. The system is fully verifiable, having no significant influence on ETC performance. The report also takes into account ECIP 1017 that changes Ethereum Classic monetary policy and emission schedule. We expect that the ECTS implementation will increase stability and the outlook of the system, providing additional benefits both for stakeholders and miners from a more stable and predictable system. 1 Contents 1 Introduction 4 1.1 Objective and desired properties of the treasury system..........................................4 1.2 Overview of the proposed treasury system......................5 2 Ethereum Classic Treasury System6 2.1 Ethereum Classic Blockchain.............................7 2.2 Basic Treasury Model.................................8 2.2.1 Funding epochs.................................8 2.2.2 Epoch stages..................................9 2.3 Proposal submission.................................. 12 2.3.1 Proposal ballot formation........................... 12 2.3.2 Submission rules and cost........................... 13 2.3.3 Miscellaneous: revocation and money reducing............... 13 2.4 Voters.......................................... 13 2.4.1 Deposit submission and redemption..................... 14 2.4.2 Incentives.................................... 15 2.5 Treasury source.................................... 16 2.5.1 Funding within the ECIP-1017 monetary policy............... 16 2.5.2 Legacy monetary policy............................ 18 2.6 Election method...................................
    [Show full text]
  • Utilities, Preferences and Choice
    Utilities, Preferences and Choice By: Martin Kroh and Cees van der Eijk (both ASCoR/University of Amsterdam) First draft — Please comment copyright © 2003 by Martin Kroh & Cees van der Eijk Paper prepared for the joint sessions of workshops of the ECPR in Edinburgh, March 2003. Direct correspondence to: Martin Kroh. Universiteit van Amsterdam/ ASCoR. Oudezijds Achterburgwal 237, 1012 DL Amsterdam, the Netherlands. [email protected] Cees van der Eijk. Universiteit van Amsterdam/ ASCoR. Oudezijds Achterburgwal 237, 1012 DL Amsterdam, the Netherlands. [email protected]. 1 In this paper we argue that theories of party choice are implicitly not about choice, but about electoral preferences or utilities. This distinction is not trivial, as individual choice can be deduced from individual preferences or utilities, whereas the reverse is not necessarily true. In spite of this, a large part of empirical electoral research is (implicitly) based on the analysis of ‘revealed’ preferences, i.e. preferences that have been deduced from choice by using interpersonal comparison to make up the informational deficit at the individual level. We argue that the risks of this approach can be avoided by an alternative approach, that entails the empirical observation of electoral utility. A practical procedure for doing so is presented, and some validating analyses are reported. 1. Individual Choice Theory Theories of individual choice behavior conceptualize choice as a function of the characteristics of the decision maker, of the set of available alternatives and their attributes, and a decision rule. Given a fixed set of alternatives and their attributes, individual choice is commonly construed in two steps.
    [Show full text]
  • Democracy Lost: a Report on the Fatally Flawed 2016 Democratic Primaries
    Democracy Lost: A Report on the Fatally Flawed 2016 Democratic Primaries Election Justice USA | ElectionJusticeUSA.org | [email protected] Table of Contents I. INTRODUCTORY MATERIAL........................................................................................................2 A. ABOUT ELECTION JUSTICE USA...............................................................................................2 B. EXECUTIVE SUMMARY...............................................................................................................2 C. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS..............................................................................................................7 II. SUMMARY OF DIRECT EVIDENCE FOR ELECTION FRAUD, VOTER SUPPRESSION, AND OTHER IRREGULARITIES.......................................................................................................7 A. VOTER SUPPRESSION..................................................................................................................7 B. REGISTRATION TAMPERING......................................................................................................8 C. ILLEGAL VOTER PURGING.........................................................................................................8 D. EVIDENCE OF FRAUDULENT OR ERRONEOUS VOTING MACHINE TALLIES.................9 E. MISCELLANEOUS........................................................................................................................10 F. ESTIMATE OF PLEDGED DELEGATES AFFECTED................................................................11
    [Show full text]
  • Crowdsourcing Applications of Voting Theory Daniel Hughart
    Crowdsourcing Applications of Voting Theory Daniel Hughart 5/17/2013 Most large scale marketing campaigns which involve consumer participation through voting makes use of plurality voting. In this work, it is questioned whether firms may have incentive to utilize alternative voting systems. Through an analysis of voting criteria, as well as a series of voting systems themselves, it is suggested that though there are no necessarily superior voting systems there are likely enough benefits to alternative systems to encourage their use over plurality voting. Contents Introduction .................................................................................................................................... 3 Assumptions ............................................................................................................................... 6 Voting Criteria .............................................................................................................................. 10 Condorcet ................................................................................................................................. 11 Smith ......................................................................................................................................... 14 Condorcet Loser ........................................................................................................................ 15 Majority ...................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 2016 US Presidential Election Herrade Igersheim, François Durand, Aaron Hamlin, Jean-François Laslier
    Comparing Voting Methods: 2016 US Presidential Election Herrade Igersheim, François Durand, Aaron Hamlin, Jean-François Laslier To cite this version: Herrade Igersheim, François Durand, Aaron Hamlin, Jean-François Laslier. Comparing Voting Meth- ods: 2016 US Presidential Election. 2018. halshs-01972097 HAL Id: halshs-01972097 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-01972097 Preprint submitted on 7 Jan 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. WORKING PAPER N° 2018 – 55 Comparing Voting Methods: 2016 US Presidential Election Herrade Igersheim François Durand Aaron Hamlin Jean-François Laslier JEL Codes: D72, C93 Keywords : Approval voting, range voting, instant runoff, strategic voting, US Presidential election PARIS-JOURDAN SCIENCES ECONOMIQUES 48, BD JOURDAN – E.N.S. – 75014 PARIS TÉL. : 33(0) 1 80 52 16 00= www.pse.ens.fr CENTRE NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE – ECOLE DES HAUTES ETUDES EN SCIENCES SOCIALES ÉCOLE DES PONTS PARISTECH – ECOLE NORMALE SUPÉRIEURE INSTITUT NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE AGRONOMIQUE – UNIVERSITE PARIS 1 Comparing Voting Methods: 2016 US Presidential Election Herrade Igersheim☦ François Durand* Aaron Hamlin✝ Jean-François Laslier§ November, 20, 2018 Abstract. Before the 2016 US presidential elections, more than 2,000 participants participated to a survey in which they were asked their opinions about the candidates, and were also asked to vote according to different alternative voting rules, in addition to plurality: approval voting, range voting, and instant runoff voting.
    [Show full text]
  • Electoral Reform
    Electoral Reform Max Taubenberger July, 2020 Executive Summary The United States once prided itself on being a bastion of democ- racy for the world to see. The resilience of our democracy, like so many of our institutions has atrophied and become sclerotic and ineffective. As of 2020, the US comes in at a measly 25th place on the Democ- racy Index1. Furthermore, the average American voter and grassroots organizations have little to no influence over the direction of public policy.2 take a cursory overview of the current circumstances and pro- pose several paths for reform and many different options that can be taken at the municipal, state, and federal levels to help restore the vitality of American democracy. 1https://infographics.economist.com/2020/democracy-index-2019/map.html 2https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/perspectives-on-politics/ article/testing-theories-of-american-politics-elites-interest-groups-and-average-citizens/ 62327F513959D0A304D4893B382B992B 1 Voting Systems 1.1 Presidential/Executive Presidential elections in the United States are an outlier in that they're the only major office that isn't directly elected by the people. Instead, there are electors (of which there are currently 538) that are sent to the Electoral College. Throughout the history of the US, the method of electoral appor- tionment has varied as the constitution gives full levity to states in how they choose to select electors. It wasn't until the election of 1872 that all states apportioned their electors predicated upon the popular vote in the en- tire state. Two states today (Nebraska and Maine) use a more proportional method where some electors are chosen by the popular vote in a congres- sional district.
    [Show full text]
  • D21 – Janecek Method
    D21 { Janeˇcekmethod Karel Janeˇcek,PhD. December 28, 2020 Is it possible to find a voting system which maintains an equality of voting rights and at the same time gives greater impact to well- informed and engaged voters? Yes, it is possible. Our proposed vot- ing system solves this apparent paradox. In addition to this principal benefit, it also enables voters to re-balance the political spectrum away from extremists and reduce the threat of dishonest or corrupt political actors. 1 Representative democracy In 1947, Winston Churchill famously declared: \It has been said that democracy is the worst form of government, except all the others that have been tried." Is democracy really as weak, ineffective and unsatisfactory a form of government as it often appears? Might a better system than democracy exist? If not, does it mean that we, as a human society, must endure the ill effects of a system performing far under its potential? It is the author's core conviction that only systems with a democratic anchor will work properly in the long run. As soon as the essential principle of equal suffrage is breached, the risk that the social system will eventually degenerate into some form of authoritarianism or dictatorship, or another regime which discriminates against and mistreats certain individuals or groups of citizens, is significant. Such a system will necessarily be unstable from a long-term perspective and will lead to major social conflicts. Selection of high-quality political representation is a key factor for reaching the fairest and most effective functioning of society as a whole.
    [Show full text]
  • Landry, Celeste
    HB 5404: Study Ranked-Choice Voting in CT, Committee on Government Administration and Elections March 4, 2020 testimony by Celeste Landry, 745 University Ave, Boulder, CO 80302 Bio: I have been researching voting methods since 2012 and have given a variety of Voting Methods presentations including at the 2018 LWVUS convention, the 2019 Free and Equal Electoral Reform Symposium and the 2020 CO Dept of State Alternative Voting Method Stakeholder Group meeting. Four Proposed Amendments: Amendments #1 and #2 below address language in the current text, but Amendments #3 and #4 provide for better and broader resolutions to the bill’s limitations. Issue #1. The description of ranked-choice voting (RCV) in HB5404 is too limited. For instance, the 2018 Maine Congressional District 2 election would NOT fit the definition below: 6 are defeated and until one candidate receives over fifty per cent of the 7 votes cast, and (3) the candidate receiving over fifty per cent of the votes 8 cast is deemed to have been elected to such office. Such study shall Example: The Maine CD2 winner, Jared Golden, did NOT receive over 50% of the votes cast (144,813 out of 289,624). More people preferred Golden’s opponents to Golden. In the last round, Golden received over 50% of the votes if you only count the non-exhausted ballots. The definition of RCV in the bill effectively claims that more than two thousand cast votes were actually not cast! 2018 Maine CD2 election results: https://www.maine.gov/sos/cec/elec/results/results18.html#Nov6 Resolution: The definition should read 6 are defeated and until one candidate receives over fifty per cent of the 7 votes cast on non-exhausted ballots, and (3) the candidate receiving over fifty per cent of the votes 8 cast on non-exhausted ballots is deemed to have been elected to such office.
    [Show full text]
  • Transnational Electoral Lists
    Transnational electoral lists Ways to Europeanise elections to the European Parliament STUDY EPRS | European Parliamentary Research Service Author: Maria Diaz Crego Members' Research Service PE 679.084 – February 2021 EN Transnational electoral lists Ways to Europeanise elections to the European Parliament The creation of a pan-European constituency, comprising the whole territory of the European Union, in which a number of Members of the European Parliament would be elected from transnational electoral lists, figures high among proposals to enhance the European dimension of the elections to the European Parliament. Although the idea to create a European constituency gained momentum with 73 seats in the European Parliament due to become vacant as a consequence of the United Kingdom's withdrawal from the European Union, the proposal is far from new and has been debated in the European institutions and academia since the 1990s. This paper analyses the main proposals to create a European constituency (or constituencies) that have been discussed in the European Parliament, other European institutions and academia, and details the legal changes that would be needed at European and national level to bring the idea to fruition. EPRS | European Parliamentary Research Service AUTHOR María Díaz Crego, Members' Research Service, European Parliamentary Research Service (EPRS), European Parliament. Giulio Sabbati, Samy Chahri and Lucille Killmayer (EPRS) are responsible for the graphics. The author would like to thank the following policy analyst from the Members' Research Service for providing information in relation to the following Member States: the Netherlands and Finland (Ingeborg Odink); Czechia (Marketa Pape); Germany (Hendrik Alexander Mildebrath); Luxembourg (Marie-Laure Augère- Granier); Malta (Denise Chircop); Hungary (Gabriella Zana-Szabo); Poland (Rafal Manko); Croatia (Kristina Grosek); Slovenia (Anja Radjenovic).
    [Show full text]
  • The Mathematics of Voting: Paradox, Deception, and Chaos
    The Mathematics of Voting: Paradox, deception, and chaos Marcus Pivato Department of Mathematics, Trent University http://xaravve.trentu.ca/voting.pdf May 8, 2008 Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... ◮ ...Olympic judges must give the gold medal to Argentina, Brazil, Canada, or Denmark. Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... ◮ ...Olympic judges must give the gold medal to Argentina, Brazil, Canada, or Denmark. ◮ ...A committee must award a prize to one of four contestants Ariadne, Brynn, Chloe, or Desdemona. Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... ◮ ...Olympic judges must give the gold medal to Argentina, Brazil, Canada, or Denmark. ◮ ...A committee must award a prize to one of four contestants Ariadne, Brynn, Chloe, or Desdemona. ◮ ...Pick one dessert for the dinner party: Apple cobbler, Banana cream pie, Chocolate cake, or Dulce de leche. Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D. e.g.... ◮ ...Olympic judges must give the gold medal to Argentina, Brazil, Canada, or Denmark. ◮ ...A committee must award a prize to one of four contestants Ariadne, Brynn, Chloe, or Desdemona. ◮ ...Pick one dessert for the dinner party: Apple cobbler, Banana cream pie, Chocolate cake, or Dulce de leche. ◮ ...An federal election with four candidates: LiberAl, Bloc Quebecois, Conservative, or New Democratic. Elections (2/84) Suppose people must choose between four alternatives A, B, C, or D.
    [Show full text]