<<

Symplectic Geometry

and Geometric

Matthias Blau

NIKHEFH

PO Box DB Amsterdam

The Netherlands

1

This is a preliminary version not intended for distribution outside this School Thank

You

2

email tnikhefhnikhefnl t

Contents

Introduction

Symplectic Geometry and Classical Mechanics

Symplectic Geometry

Relation with Classical Mechanics

What is Quantization

Geometric Quantization I Prequantization

The Prequantum Hilb ert Space

Examples

Geometric Quantization I I Polarizations

Polarizations

Real Polarizations

Kahler Polarizations

Geometric Quantization I I I Quantization

Polarized States and the Construction of Quantum Op erators

The Vertical Polarization and HalfDensities

Kahler Quantization and Metaplectic Correction

Real Polarizations and BohrSommerfeld Varieties

References

Introduction

At the macroscopic level our world seems to b e pretty much governed by the

laws of classical ie by Newtonian mechanics on the one hand and by

Maxwell theory on the other The former describ es the motion of particles

under the inuence of forces acting on them and applies to such diverse elds

as celestial mechanics and elasticity theory The latter covers almost the entire

sp ectrum of phenomena o ccurring in electromagnetism and optics The dynam

ics in these two theories is governed by deterministic equations of motion and

in principle it is p ossible given the initial conditions to predict the results of

measurements on the system at any later time

Classical physics could thus provide us with a very satisfactory description of

the world we live in were it not for the fact that it not only fails to give an

explanation for a number of phenomena observed at the microscopic level but

is in fact in plain contradiction with exp erimental evidence

As an illustration of what these phenomena are and what they may b e trying

to tell us ab out a theory which will have to replace I want

to mention just two examples The rst has to do with the stability of atoms

From scattering and other exp eriments it had b een deduced that atoms consist

of a tiny p ositively charged nucleus orbited at some distance by negatively

charged p ointlike particles called electrons Within the realms of classical

physics such structures are highly unstable and would b e predicted to collapse

within fractions of a second in glaring contradiction with the relative stability

of the world around us orbital motion is accelerated motion and according

to Maxwell theory accelerated charges emit radiation the electron would thus

radiate away energy and spiral into the nucleus of the atom It was also observed

that simple atoms like Hydrogen atoms were able to emit and absorb energy

only in certain discrete quantities Combining these two observations it thus

app eared to b e necessary to p ostulate the existence of stable orbits for electrons

at certain discrete radii energy levels This suggests that at the microscopic

level nature allows for a discrete or quantized structure quite unfamiliar from

classical physics

The second is the famous twoslit gedankenexperiment or other exp eriments

investigating the diraction and interference patterns of b eams of particles like

electrons These indicated that under certain circumstance particles like elec

trons can show interference patterns and thus a wavelike nature and that

under certain conditions light whose wavelike nature had nally b een univer

sally accepted showed b ehaviour characteristic of particles and not of waves In

short at the microscopic level nature was found to b e mindb ogglingly strange

and wonderful Or in the words of Dirac quoted from p the authorita

tive b o ok on

We have here a very striking and general example of the break

down of classical mechanics not merely an inaccurracy of its laws

of motion but an inadequacy of its concepts to supply us with a

description of atomic events

To make things worse the outcome of these exp eriments app eared to dep end

on the measuring pro cess itself ie on whether or not one was checking through

which slit the electron went This for the rst time p ointed to the necessity of

including the eects of observation of a system into a description of the system

itself In particular it had to b e taken into account that one can not make

any observations on a suitably small system without p erturbing the system

itself technically this is expressed in the uncertainty principle In the words

of Dirac p

A consequence of the preceding discussion is that we must revise

our ideas of causality Causality applies only to a system which is

left undisturb ed If a system is small we cannot observe it with

out pro ducing a serious disturbance and hence we cannot exp ect to

nd any causal connexion b etween the results of our observations

Causality will still b e assumed to apply to undisturb ed systems and

the equations which will b e set up to describ e an undisturb ed system

will b e dierential equations expressing a causal connexion b etween

conditions at one time and conditions at a later time These equa

tions will b e in close corresp ondence with the equations of classical

mechanics but they will b e connected only indirectly with the re

sults of observations There is an unavoidable indeterminacy in the

calculation of observable results the theory enabling us to calculate

in general only the probability of our obtaining a particular result

when making an observation

Heisenberg and Schrodinger provided two mathematical mo dels or recip es

later shown to b e equivalent which were able to repro duce the ab ove results

and make many other successfully tested predictions These mo dels collectively

known as quantum mechanics describ e the quantum b ehaviour of p oint par

ticles in at space under the inuence of external forces Supplemented by

some intepretation of roughly sp eaking the role of the measuring pro cess or

observer they constitute a ma jor step forward in the understanding of quantum

physics in general

At a conceptual level however the situation was not very satisfactory In par

ticular it was not clear how general the prop osed mo dels were which features

were to b e regarded as fundamental to any quantum version of a classical the

ory and which were to b e attributed to particular prop erties of the systems

considered so far

In an attempt to gain some insight into this question it was in particular

Dirac who emphasized the formal similarities b etween classical and quantum

mechanics and the necessity of prop erly understanding these Again in the

words of the master himself p

1

Recent exp eriments indicate that interference patterns will disapp ear whenever there is in

principle the p ossibility of detecting through which slit the particle photon electron went

regardless of whether there was actually a detector there switched on or not This highly

counterintuitive result app ears to b e in agreement with theory

The value of classical analogy in the development of quantum me

chanics dep ends on the fact that classical mechanics provides a valid

description of dynamical systems under certain conditions when the

particles and b o dies comp osing the system are suciently massive

for the disturbance accompanying an observation to b e negligible

Classical mechanics must therefore b e a limiting case of quantum

mechanics We should thus exp ect to nd that imp ortant concepts

in classical mechanics corresp ond to imp ortant concepts in quantum

mechanics and from an understanding of the general nature of the

analogy b etween classical and quantum mechanics we may hop e to

get laws and theorems in quantum mechanics app earing as simple

generalizations of wellknown results in classical mechanics

Abstracting from the analogy found b etween classical mechanics and Schrodinger

and Heisenberg quantum mechanics Dirac formulated a general quantum con

dition a guideline for passing from a given classical system to the corresp ond

ing quantum theory This pro cess in general is known as quantization And

roughly sp eaking quantization consists in replacing the classical algebra of ob

servables functions on by an algebra of op erators acting on some

Hilb ert space the quantum condition relating the commutator of two op erators

to the Poisson bracket of their classical counterparts I will explain these rules

of in section after having introduced the imp ortant

concepts in classical mechanics referred to in the ab ove quote Readers famil

iar with the mathematical description of classical mechanics may wish to move

right on to that section and read it as part of the introduction

Parenthetically I want to issue a word of caution at this p oint At rst sight

and p erhaps even at second sight the very concept of quantization app ears

to b e illfounded since it attempts to construct a correct theory from a theory

which is only approximately correct After all our world is quantum and while

it seems a legitimate task to try to extract classical mechanics in some limit from

quantum mechanics their seems to b e little reason to b elieve that the inverse

construction can always b e p erformed Furthermore there is no reason to

b elieve that such a construction would b e unique as there could well b e and in

fact are lots of dierent quantum theories which have the same classical limit

Unfortunately however it is conceptually very dicult to describ e a quantum

theory from scratch without the help of a reference classical theory Moreover

there is enough to the analogy b etween classical and quantum mechanics to

make quantization a worthwile approach Perhaps ultimately the study of

quantization will tell us enough ab out quantum theory itself to allow us to do

away with the very concept of quantization

But let us now return to less philosophical matters Unfortunately Diracs

quantum condition is not as general as one might have hop ed it to b e or at

least not suciently unambiguous Thus to make some headway it is desir

able to nd a more intrinsic and constructive description of this quantization

pro cedure This is the aim of Geometric Quantization which as the name sug

gests attempts to provide a geometric interpretation of quantization within

an extension of the mathematical framework of classical mechanics symplec

tic geometry More sp ecically geometric quantization abbreviated to GQ

henceforth refers to a b o dy of ideas pioneered indep endently by Souriau

and Kostant in the late s and early s

It is the purp ose of these lectures to provide an introduction to the role of

symplectic geometry in quantization in general and as a concrete realization

of this general picture to give an introductory account of GQ Unfortunately

although the fundamental ideas in GQ are very elegant and simple things

tend to b ecome more complicated and mathematically more demanding rather

quickly In these notes I have therefore tried to emphasize primarily these

basic ideas and to hint at or illustrate the more advanced machinery like half

density and halfform quantization BKS kernels Bohr Sommerfeld varieties

and distributional wave functions in terms of simple examples rather than

develop it in any great detail The reason for pro ceeding in this way is partly

lack of space and time and partly that I do not want to advocate GQ as an

ecient calculational to ol in quantum mechanics anyway in fact at present at

least it is far from b eing that but rather as a pro cedure of more conceptual

interest

Section is a crashcourse on the formalism of symplectic geometry It serves

mainly to introduce the nomenclature and dierential form notation to b e

used throughout Section explains why this is a natural framework for

classical mechanics

Section in a sense the heart of these notes is an introduction to the question

What is quantization It also deals with the no less imp ortant questions

What is it not and What should or can it not exp ected to b e My own

views on this sub ject have b een heavily inuenced by the article of Isham

which I warmly recommend to anyone interested in these questions

Section deals with the rst step of GQ known as prequantization This is

an elegant pro cedure which asso ciates to any quantizable symplectic manifold

a Hilb ert space carrying a faithful representation of the classical observable

algebra Section describ es the construction and contains a discussion of the

conditions for existence of a prequantization and their top ological classication

Certain simple and prototypical examples are discussed in section

Unfortunately the Hilb ert space provided by prequantization as elegant as

the pro cedure may b e is not the correct one for quantum mechanics and one

needs some way of cutting it in half This is achieved via the introduction

of a p olarization of the phase space Splitting the quantization pro cess into

these two steps is nevertheless useful b ecause it serves to isolate some of the

ambiguities inherent in passing from a classical to a quantum system The

ambiguity in the choice of a prequantum Hilb ert space corresp onds roughly

sp eaking to the presence of top ological sup erselection rules while the choice of

p olarization corresp onds to choosing a particular representation within a given

top ological sector I hop e that the meaning of this sentence will b ecome clearer

in the following sections

In section I try to explain why in the framework of GQ p olarizations arise

naturally at this p oint Section deals with real p olarizations in particular

with the vertical p olarization of a cotangent bundle Section describ es

the second imp ortant class of p olarizations namely Kahler p olarizations As

background material it also contains a synopsis of facts ab out complex and

Kahler vector spaces and manifolds

Section nally deals with the construction of the quantum Hilb ert space

asso ciated to a p olarization and with the construction of op erators acting on it

It is at this crucial p oint that GQ b ecomes somewhat murky In section I

show how p olarization preserving observables give rise directly to op erators at

the quantum level and how the scheme needs to b e mo died to quantize other

observables via BKS kernels We then turn to the construction of the quantum

Hilb ert space I will describ e three prototypical situations vertical p olarizations

p ositive Kahler p olarizations and real p olarizations with nonsimply conected

leaves p oint out the complications arising in each of these and explain briey

how these problems can b e overcome

Here these notes end rather abruptly but I hop e that they will have prepared

the ground for further inquiries into the existing literature In particular I want

to draw attention to the recent investigations into the p olarization dep endence

of GQ in motivated by questions arising in top ological and conformal eld

theory and to the application of GQ to the quantization of constrained systems

which is a rather natural thing to attempt as constrained systems are

also describ ed most eectively in terms of symplectic geometry

The most glaring omission of these notes is probably the representation theoretic

asp ect of GQ ie the quantization of coadjoint orbits of a Lie group which I

only touch up on briey in section and when discussing the quantization of the

twosphere in sections and This relation b etween GQ and the representation

theory of Lie groups is imp ortant b oth mathematically and historically See

for that part of the story

The basic references for section are Abraham and Marsden and Arnold

A wealth of other information on symplectic geometry can b e found in

the b o ok by Guillemin and Sternberg My favourite references for section

are the b o ok by Dirac and the lectures by Isham Most of what I

will say ab out GQ and much more can b e found in the b o ok by Woo dhouse

Its imprints on these notes are rather obvious in sections and Other

monographs on GQ include and

Symplectic Geometry and Classical Mechanics

Symplectic Geometry is the adequate mathematical framework for describing

the Hamiltonian version of classical mechanics As such it is also the most

suitable starting p oint for a geometrization of the canonical quantization pro

cedure

The purp ose of section is to introduce the formalism of symplectic geometry

and the co ordinate indep endent dierential form notation we will use through

out these lectures Section serves to establish the relation of this formalism

with that of classical Hamiltonian mechanics

Symplectic Geometry

By a symplectic manifold M we will mean a smo oth real mdimensional

manifold M without b oundary equipp ed with a closed nondegenerate twoform

the symplectic form Closed means that

d

in lo cal co ordinates where d is the exterior dierential

i j k

k k

d M M d

on dierential forms on M And nondegenerate means that at each p oint

x M the antisymmetric matrix is nondegenerate ie

x

det x M

x

The most imp ortant example of a symplectic manifold is a cotangent bundle

M T Q This is nothing but the traditional phase space of classical mechan

ics Q b eing known as the conguration space in that context A cotangent

bundle has a canonical symplectic twoform which is globally exact

d

k

and hence in particular closed Any lo cal co ordinate system fq g on Q can

k

b e extended to a co ordinate system fq p g on T Q such that and are

k

lo cally given by

k

k

p dq dp dq

k k

We will return to the sp ecic case of cotangent bundles at the end of this section

when we discuss the relation with classical mechanics

Other examples of symplectic manifolds are orientable twodimensional surfaces

choose any volume form on as such it is certainly nondegenerate as a

twoform on a twodimensional manifold it is also certainly closed d is a three

form and and there are no antisymmetric threetensors in two dimensions and

although it is a fact known as Darb ouxs theorem that on any symplectic

manifold one can choose a lo cal co ordinate system such that takes the form

cannot b e globally exact in this case b ecause otherwise the volume of

would b e zero by Stokes theorem If d were true then

Z Z Z

Vol d

b ecause More generally all Kahler manifolds are symplectic and we

will come back to them in section

2

Like a Riemannian manifold M g is a manifold equipp ed with a nondegenerate sym

metric twotensor g the Riemannian metric

Condition has several imp ortant consequences First of all it implies

that M is evendimensional m n as an o dddimensional antisymmetric

matrix has zero determinant The same argument as ab ove shows that the

symplectic form of any compact symplectic manifold is cohomologically non

trivial ie closed but not globally exact b ecause otherwise the symplectic

volume

Z

n

V ol M

n

M

would b e zero

Moreover as is invertible at each p oint x M it gives an isomorphism

b etween the tangent and cotangent spaces of M at x

iso

T M T M

x x

x

expressed in lo cal co ordinates as

i i

X X

ik

Crudely sp eaking like a metric a symplectic form allows us to raise and lower

indices on tensors This extends to an isomorphism b etween TM and T M and

b etween vector elds and oneforms on M

X iX X M

here iX denotes the contraction of a dierential form with the vector eld

X as in ie the insertion of X into the rst slot of a dierential form

In particular therefore the existence of allows us to asso ciate a vector eld

X to every function f C M via

f

iX df

f

the minus sign is for later convenience only X the symplectic gradient

f

of f is known as the Hamiltonian vector eld of f It generates a ow on M

which leaves invariant as the Lie derivative of along X is zero

f

LX diX iX d ddf

f f f

Via the symplectic form provides an antisymmetric pairing ff g g b e

tween functions f g on M called the Poisson bracket of f and g It is dened

by

ff g g X X C M

g

f

and describ es the change of g along X or vice versa

f

ff g g iX iX iX dg LX g

g

f f f

In particular f is constant ie preserved along the integral curves of X The

f

Poisson bracket satises the Jacobi identity

ff fg hgg fff g g hg fg ff hgg

This can b e shown either by writing out explicitly d X X X is

g

f h

closed or by using the tensoriality of the Lie derivative and LX to

f

deduce

LX X X LX X X X LX X

g g g

f h f h f h

which is just a rewriting of This gives C M f g the structure of

an innite dimensional Lie algebra

One further imp ortant identity we will need which relates the Lie algebras of

vector elds and functions on M is

X X X

g

f

ff g g

which shows that the Hamiltonian vector elds also form an innite dimensional

Lie algebra Moreover regarding the map Lie algebra homomorphism f X

f

as an assignment of dierential op erators to functions the identity is also

an illustration of the quantization paradigm Diracs quantum condition

Poisson Brackets Commutators

and will play an imp ortant role in the following To prove one again

makes use of the tensoriality of the Lie derivative this time in the form

iX Y LX iY iY LX

to show that iX X iX

g

f

ff g g

Lastly we will need to consider certain submanifolds of symplectic manifolds

A subspace V j of a symplectic vector space W ie a vector space W

V

equipp ed with a nondegenerate antisymmetric twotensor is called isotropic

if j By linear algebra an isotropic subspace of W has dimension at most

V

dimW and in that case V is called a Lagrangian subspace of W Likewise

we now dene a Lagrangian submanifold of M to b e an ndimensional

submanifold N M such that j For example it is evident from

TN

that Q dened by p is a Lagrangian submanifold of M T Q as

k

is the bre T Q of the cotangent bundle at q Q Lo cally any Lagrangian

q

submanifold N is given by the vanishing of n functions F on M which are in

k

involution ie which satisfy

fF F g k l

k l

In fact it follows from this condition that the Hamiltonian vector elds X

F

k

T

fF g so that they lo cally span the tangent bundle TN are tangent to

l

l

Reading as X X then says that j

F F TN

k l

This concludes our crashcourse on symplectic geometry The second half of this

century has witnessed a great deal of activity in this eld which has established

itself as an indep endent mathematical descipline fertilized by the relation with

classical mechanics I have not mentioned any results of mo dern symplectic

geometry which can b e obtained within this framework and the adventurous

reader is referred to for a detailed account

3

The terminology arises from the relation b etween such subspaces and the HamiltonJacobi

theory of Lagrangian mechanics see

Relation with Classical Mechanics

Now what has all this got to do with classical mechanics In the simplest

mechanical systems the areana for classical mechanics in the Hamiltonian or

rst order formalism is the phase space a ndimensional real vector space

n n

R with co ordinates q q p p describing the p osition and the

n

momentum velocity of the particles involved The dynamics time evolution

of the system is governed by Hamiltons equations

H

k

d

q

dt

p

k

H

d

p

k

dt

k

q

k

where H q p the Hamiltonian is a function on phase space describing the

k

energy of the system

Typically H is of the form H T V where T p is the kinetic energy and

k

V V q is the p otential energy whose gradient descib es the forces acting on

the particles For example a harmonic oscillator in one dimension is describ ed

by the Hamiltonian H p q the equations of motion q p p q

leading to the characteristic oscillating b ehaviour q t q cos t p sin t

If H do es not dep end on time explicitly the equations of motion imply

that H is conserved along any tra jectory in phase space

H H

k

d

H p q

k

dt

k

q p

k

H H H H

k k

q p q p

k k

summation over rep eated indices b eing understo o d while the evolution of any

other function f on phase space observable is given by

f H H f

d

f

dt

k k

q p p q

k k

In our simple onedimensional example ab ove already determines the

phase space tra jectories uniquely to b e the circles p q const in agreement

with the explicit solution of the equations of motion

In general any constant of motion ie any function f on phase space in invo

lution with the Hamiltonian fH f g can b e used to reduce the dynamical

system to a lower dimensional one on the common level surfaces of the functions

H and f It follows from the Jacobi identity that the Poisson bracket

of any two constants of motion is also a constant of motion If it is p ossible

to nd n constants of motion in involution and indep endent in the sense that

their Hamiltonian vector elds are linearly indep endent the system is called

integrable and there are then standard metho ds available for solving the system

completely HamiltonJacobi theory actionangle variables Most text

b o ok examples of classical mechanics are integrable but integrability is by no

means prototypical and only o ccurs in systems with a high degree of symmetry

In the general case one has to resort to more qualitative instead of quantitative

metho ds of investigation For a detailed exp osition with numerous applications

eg to the rigid b o dy and celestial mechanics see

The equations characterising Hamiltonian mechanics arise natu

n n

rally if we think of R as the cotangent bundle T R of the conguration

n

space R with the canonical symplectic form Namely in that case the

k

Hamiltonian vector eld X of a function f q p is

f k

f f

X

f

k k

p q q p

k k

k

as it is easily veried that iX dp dq df cf Therefore the

f k

Poisson bracket is

g g f f

ff g g

k k

p q q p

k k

and in particular the canonical Poisson brackets classical canonical commu

tation relations b etween the co ordinates and momenta are

k l

fq q g fp p g

k l

l l

fp q g

k

k

k

The functions q and p form a complete set of observables in the sense that any

l

function which Poisson commutes has vanishing Poisson brackets with all of

them is a constant

The equations can now b e written succinctly as

k k

d d

q fH q g p fH p g

k k

dt dt

fH H g

d

f fH f g X f

H

dt

so that time evolution in classical mechanics is determined by the Hamiltonian

vector eld X of the Hamiltonian H

H

This formulation makes manifest the forminvariance of the equations of clas

sical mechanics under canonical transformations or dif

feomorphisms leaving the symplectic form invariant For instance Liouvilles

theorem that the volume of any p ortion of phase space is invariant under time

evolution ie b ehaves like an incompressible uid is a trivial consequence of

LX and is thus built into the formalism from the outset

H

It also has the added advantage of generalizing immediately to more compli

cated systems eg with constraints where the conguration space is some

curved manifold Q or even where the phase space is some compact symplectic

manifold and hence cannot p ossibly b e a cotangent bundle The necessity

to consider such more exotic systems in physics has arisen in recent years in

a number of dierent contexts eg for the description of internal degrees of

freedom and in top ological and conformal eld theory In mathematics quan

tization of compact symplectic manifolds plays a central role in representation

theory where the symplectic manifolds in question are coadjoint orbits

What is Quantization

In this section we take a rst step away from the classical theory outlined ab ove

It is in a sense a continuation of the introduction why quantum theory and

tries to give a general avour of what quantization is ab out without entering

to o far into the formalism and interpretation of quantum mechanics itself

Classically the space C M of observables has in addition to a Lie alge

bra structure provided by the Poisson bracket the structure of a commutative

algebra under p ointwise multiplication

f g x f xg x g f x

It app ears that it is this prop erty which has to b e sacriced when moving from

the classical to the quantum theory the noncommutative nature of observables

in the quantum theory b eing at the heart of the phenomena discussed in the

introduction More sp ecically quantization usually refers to an assignment

Q f Qf

of op erators Qf on some Hilb ert space to classical observables f This Hilb ert

space can b e nitedimensional in which case one can think of the Qf s sim

ply as nitedimensional matrices but will in general b e innitedimensional

The scalar pro duct in the Hilb ert space is necessary for the probabilistic inter

pretation of the theory and is thus of fundamental imp ortance This assignment

Q has to satisfy some more or less obvious requirements like

Q Rlinearity

Qr f g r Qf Qg r R f g C M

and the condition that

Q the constant function is mapp ed into the identity op erator or matrix

Q

Furthermore real functions should corresp ond to hermitian op erators as the

eigenvalues of Qf are the p ossible results of measurements in the quantum

theory and hence should b e real

Q

Qf Qf

But of course we need more guidelines than that to construct a quantum theory

from a classical theory even keeping in mind the limitations to this programme

mentioned in the introduction It is here where Diracs observation enters that

4 1

These are related by the Leibniz rule ff g hg ff g gh g ff hg and give C M the

structure of a Poisson algebra

5

Here and in the following I will gloss over functional analytic complications This is

however not meant to imply that they are not imp ortant

it is the commutator of two op erators which is the quantum counterpart of the

classical Poisson bracket More precisely to the conditions one adds

Q the quantum condition

Qf Qg ih Qff g g

Here h is Plancks constant a constant of nature dimension of an action

characteristic of quantum eects It is a very small number and for most

macroscopic considerations the fact that it is not zero can b e neglected This

is also reected in the fact that for h now treating h just as a parameter

one recovers from the commutative structure of classical mechanics At

the microscopic level however order h eects can no longer b e neglected and

this is where classical mechanics needs to b e replaced by quantum mechanics

It would p erhaps b e more natural if h app eared as a free parameter in the

theory see One could also contemplate the p ossibility of adding higher

order terms in h to the right hand side of this leads to what is known as

deformation quantization

Exp erience has taught that there is yet one more condition to b e imp osed for

the assignment to pro duce a valid quantization in those examples where

one knows what it should lo ok like This last requirement is some kind of

irreducibility condition A reasonably general and satisfactory way of phrasing

it makes use of the concept of a complete set of observables introduced in section

In complete analogy we dene a complete set of op erators to b e one such

that the only op erators which commute with all the op erators from that set are

multiples of the identity The condition then reads that

Q if ff f g is a complete set of observables fQf Qf g is a

k k

complete set of op erators

Unfortunately it is in general not p ossible to satisfy b oth Q for all f and g

and Q and the b est one can hop e for is some optimal compromise eg de

manding Q only for a complete set of observables and p erhaps some additional

observables which are of particular interest in the quantum theory Of course

nothing tells us how to nd a complete set of observables or which one to

choose Nor is it ruled out that dierent choices of complete sets will lead to

inequivalent quantum theories ie to inequivalent predictions for the result

of exp eriments It is here in what one means by optimal that extrane

ous information and requirements enter the construction of a quantum theory

eg certain symmetries or geometric prop erties of the classical system which

may make one complete set more natural than another

Common sense must b e used here to avoid embarking on an over

axiomatised and hence misguided piece of theoretical physics We

should not b e trapp ed into axiomatising theoretical ideas out of

existence p

This discussion shows that it is very dicult to address the question of exis

tence and classication of quantizations satsifying QQ in some sense in

general By changing slightly the rules of the game GQ nevertheless provides

one metho d for doing precisely this I will come back to this b elow

First it will b e instructive to see how all this works in the simplest case Q

n

R M T Q In that case we have already encountered a complete set of

k

observables in section namely the co ordinate functions q and p According

l

to the rule Q we demand the corresp onding op erators to satisfy the canonical

commutation relations

k l

Qq Qq Qp Qp

k l

k k

Qq Qp ih

l

l

This is the socalled Heisenberg algebra and by the Schur lemma rule Q is

now equivalent to nding an irreducible representation of the Heisenberg algebra

this is why I called Q some kind of irreducibility condition ab ove By the

Stone von Neumann theorem any such representation is unitarily equivalent

n k

to L Q L R with q and p represented by

l

k k

x Qq x x x Qp x hi

l

l

x

more precisely for this uniqueness theorem to hold one has to require that

the representations exp onentiate to representations of the

there are inequivalent representations of the Heisenberg algebra The sp ectrum

range of eigenvalues of these op erators is This is the standard

Schrodinger picture of quantum mechanics It is imp ortant to keep in mind

that the fact that in this case wave functions can b e represented by functions

on the conguration space is a consequence of our quantization rules QQ

and the Stone von Neumann theorem and not some fundamental dogma of

quantization as which it is often presented

Now the co ordinates and momenta are certainly not the only observables of

interest Can we quantize any others as well in accordance with the rule Q

Indeed we can alb eit not many more One imp ortant observable is the kinetic

k l

energy op erator p p p and evidently it should b e represented by the

k l

Laplacian

Qp p h

k l

k l

x x

h Qp h

k l

k l

x x

Likewise we have little choice but to represent observables quadratic in the co

ordinates by multiplication op erators Classically the Poisson bracket b etween

l

these two quadratic op erators is prop ortional to p q and we thus need to assign

k

an op erator to this third class of quadratic observables as well Imp osing either

the hermiticity condition Q or the quantum condition Q one nds

l l l

Qp Qq Qq Qp Qp q

k k k

l l

This can b e interpreted as a particular operator ordering of Qp q Qp Qq

k k

but note that a priori there is no logical necessity for the assignment Q to sat

isfy some condition like Qf g Qf Qg in general

The quadratic observables form a closed Lie algebra under Poisson brackets

i j k l

fp p p p g fq q q q g

i j

k l

j j

j

fp q p p g p p p p

i i i

k l l k

k l

j

l j l i j

p q fp q p q g q p

i i

k k

l

k

j k l k j l l j k

fp q q q g q q q q

i

i i

k l k l l k k l l k

fp p q q g p q p q p q p q

i j i i j j

j j i i

the symplectic Lie algebra spn in the noncompact form sp sl R

Thus what the ab ove means is that when we quantize a symplectic vector

space we can always obtain a representation of the symplectic Lie algebra on

the quantum Hilb ert space which reects the classical symplectic invariance

of the theory and which exp onentiates to a pro jective representation of the

symplectic group

If we now try to extend this quantization to cubic observables we run into con

ict with the quantum condition Q That this is not due to some particularly

unfortunate choices we have made but rather an inevitable consequence of the

rules QQ is the content of the Groenewald van Hove theorem for a careful

exp osition see Thus even in the simplest case of a symplectic vector

space no full in the sense that Q holds for all observables quantization ex

ists This is not a severe setback however since there is no reason to exp ect

any arbitrarily crazy classical observable to b e quantizable and to qualify as a

true observable of the quantum system The choice of classical functions which

are to b e promoted to quantum op erators dep ends on the system under con

sideration and should feed its way back into eg the choice of complete set of

observables entering the condition Q

n n

Let us now lo ok at the case when Q R M R Even if M is a cotangent

k

bundle M T Q canonical co ordinates q p will in general not exist glob

l

ally It thus makes little sense to choose these as a complete set of observables

and to imp ose the canonical commutation relations at the quantum level

If one do es that one is ignoring completely the geometry of the phase space and

is thus p erforming something that could b e regarded as only a tangent space

approximation to the true quantum theory

Take for instance the example M T S a cylinder with angular co or

dinate angular momentum p and symplectic form dpd If one required

the canonical commutation relations Q Qp ih this would imply that

the sp ectrum of b oth op erators is but this is wrong In fact it is

known that in quantum mechanics angular momentum is quantized in units of

h sp ecQp hZ while the sp ectrum of ought to b e The source of

the problem is of course the fact that is not a globally dened co ordinate

on the circle and that one is really dealing with the real line when one pretends

that it is

One way to get around this problem is to replace by a globally dened function

on the circle like sin If one do es that one is also forced to include cos to

obtain a complete set of functions closed under Poisson brackets One then

arrives at the following globally well dened canonical Poisson bracket algebra

of the cylinder

fp sin g cos fp cos g sin fsin cos g

Quantization of the cylinder then amounts to nding a representation of

and this yields the exp ected result

Is there a more systematic way of arriving at And what is going to

replace the canonical commutation relations in general A clue to this

comes from the following observation The fact that the canonical co ordinates

n

are globally dened for M T R implies that via their Hamiltonian vector

elds translations act on the phase space completeness corresp onding to the

fact that these translations act transitively The canonical Poisson bracket

algebra can thus b e regarded as a central extension of the translation

algebra and the quantization conditions instruct one to nd its irreducible

representations

This suggests a general strategy whenever the phase space is a homogenous

space ie one with a transitive action of some group G Assuming that this

action is generated by Hamiltonian vector elds the corresp onding functions

form roughly sp eaking a complete set of observables One then lo oks for

irreducible representations of their Poisson bracket algebra Thus the canonical

commutation relations of the Heisenberg algebra are replaced by those of the

canonical group G and the problem of quantization is again reduced to one

of representation theory In general there will b e no Stone von Neumann

theorem so that quantization will not b e unique And even if M T Q the

Hilb ert space of the quantum theory will not necessarily turn out to b e L Q

Applied to the ab ove example one nds that quantization of the cylinder amounts

to nding representations of the Euclidean group E which in turn can b e ex

pressed via the Poisson bracket relations as had b een anticipated ab ove

Note that the rst guess that the canonical group could b e chosen to b e S R

itself acting on the cylinder by rotations and translations fails b ecause the

generator p of translations is not globally Hamiltonian This is the same

problem in disguise we encountered ab ove with regard to the naive canonical

commutation relations For a detailed explanation of this programme with

many other nite and innite dimensional examples see

More generally one may say that whenever there is a preferred complete set of

observables in some sense there is a preferred class of quantizations and in

this form Ishams programme has b een applied successfully to gauge theories

and quantum gravity in the Ashtekar variables by the Syracuse group

In order to avoid these questions which require more of a case by case analysis

and to geometrize the question of existence and classication of quantizations

GQ fo cusses on a slightly dierent way of lo oking at quantum mechanics on

n k

R Essentially the concept of a complete set of observables like the q and

p is replaced by that of a maximally Poisson commuting set of observables

l

k

like the q Thus wave functions are considered to b e functions or sections of

some complex line bundle on the classical or quantum sp ectrum of a maximally

commuting set of observables which are diagonal in this representation

n

Alternatively still for Q R wave functions can b e characterized as functions

on phase space which are annihilated by the Hamiltonian vector elds of a max

imally commuting set of observables It is this way of lo oking at Schrodinger

quantization that generalizes most readily to other symplectic manifolds M In

section we had already seen that such a maximally commuting set fF g

k

denes a Lagrangian submanifold of M By varying the constants c in the

k

equations F c one then obtains a foliation of M by Lagrangian submani

k k

folds This is also called a real polarization of M The quantum Hilb ert space

is then constructed from those functions sections of a line bundle on M which

are covariantly constant along the leaves of this foliation It is roughly sp eak

ing this condition that replaces the quantization condition Q emphasizing the

role of a complete set of observables

At rst this approach to quantization app ears to b e rather restrictive In the

nite dimensional case however there is considerable overlap among the results

arising from this Ishams and other quantization schemes One of the reasons

for this is that the concept of a p olarization is more exible than it p erhaps

seems

First of all it is p ossible to replace real by complex p olarizations integrable La

grangian subbundles of the complexied tangent bundle of M see section

n

This is also familiar from ordinary quantum mechanics on R in the form of the

Bargmann representation in which wave functions are represented by holomor

k

phic functions of z q ip In many cases covered by Ishams scheme there

k k

are more or less natural p olarizations which are compatible with ie invariant

under the canonical group GQ can then b e used to construct representations

of this canonical group In this context it can thus b e regarded as investigating

the question to which extent representations of the canonical group featuring

in Ishams approach can b e constructed from symplectic geometry

Moreover it can b e seen in examples that with due care it is also p ossible to

apply GQ when the fF g or the real p olarization are not globally dened but

k

are singular somewhere Such singular p olarizations are more likely to exist

and thus extend the range of applicability of GQ

A nal word of warning it is p ossible that GQ is overambitious in attempting

to make quantization work for almost see section arbitrary symplectic

manifolds Since it is really quantum theory that should b e regarded as funda

mental there is no a a priori reason to b elieve that every classical theory has a

quantum counterpart

Geometric Quantization I Prequantization

As mentioned a couple of times ab ove GQ accomplishes the quantization of

a symplectic manifold in a two or more step pro cedure The rst is the

construction of a faithful representation of the Poisson algebra of functions by

linear op erators on a Hilb ert space This is known as prequantization and

satises the quantization conditions QQ In a second step a variant of Q

is imp osed in terms of a p olarization at the inevitable exp ense of sacricing

part of the quantum condition Q

In section the construction of the prequantum Hilb ert space from a complex

line bundle over phase space is explained as well as the classication of line

bundles with connections Examples are discussed in section

The Prequantum Hilb ert Space

In order to geometrize the notion of quantization it is natural to attempt to

construct the quantum phase space Hilb ert space from the space of func

tions on the classical phase space M instead of regarding the two as completely

separate entities An imp ortant role is played by the identity

X X X

g

f

ff g g

which shows that Hamiltonian vector elds give a representation of the classical

Poisson bracket algebra by rst order dierential op erators on M In fact the

assignment

f ih X

f

satises the conditions Q obviously Q with resp ect to the Liouville mea

sure b ecause X leaves invariant and Q by However since the

f

zero vector eld is assigned to any constant function fails to satisfy Q

One may try to remedy this by replacing ihX by ihX f but this is also

f f

not quite right now violating Q A little further exp erimenting shows that

if M T Q where the symplectic form is globally the dierential of the

canonical oneform the assignment

P f P f

P f ih X X f

f f

indeed satises Q Q and thus gives a faithful representation of the Poisson

n

algebra by rst order dierential op erators on L M For Q R one has

k

denoting the multiplication op erator simply by q

k k

q P p ih P q ih

l

l

p

q

k

This evidently only reduces to the Schrodinger representation when acting

on functions of the co ordinates alone also shows that P fails to satisfy

the irreducibility condition Q as eg the op erator p commutes with all the

j

k

P q and P p Another problem with prequantization is that it certainly

l

fails to repro duce the second order dierential op erators asso ciated to

observables quadratic in the momenta To reobtain these from GQ requires

much more work The crucial p oint is that the op erator P p b eing linear in

the momenta do es not even act on the space of functions of the co ordinates

alone It thus changes the representation space or in the language of GQ the

p olarization Thus to asso ciate an op erator to p one has to comp ensate for

the change in the p olarization caused by the ow of p This is an analytically

rather involved pro cedure based on the socalled Blattner Kostant Sternberg

BKS kernels which is very incompletely understo o d in general We will only

come back to it briey in section

There is still one minor diculty with the ab ove construction Namely instead

of one could have chosen a symplectic p otential of the form df for some

function f on M This can b e comp ensated for by multiplying the functions of

L M by the phase factor expif h showing that the resulting prequan

tizations are unitarily equivalent f is however only determined by df up

to a constant resulting in an overall phase ambiguity of the prequantum wave

functions This suggests that it is more convenient to regard the op erators

P f as acting on the space of sections of a trivial complex line bundle L over

M equipp ed with a connection D which in a particular trivialization takes the

form

D d ih

As we will need the construction later on when switching from real to complex

p olarizations I will briey explain the reation b etween trivializations sections

and connection forms in the case at hand The same arguments apply to lo cal

trivializations whose existence is guaranteed by the denition of a b er bundle

in the general case of nontrivializable bundles

If there is a global nowhere vanishing section s of the complex line bundle L this

section gives us an identication L M C Conversely b eginning with M C

as we did ab ove b efore starting to worry ab out line bundles we can think of it

as a line bundle L with the natural trivializing section s m m Given

a connection covariant derivative D on L and a trivializing section s the

corresp onding connection oneform is dened by

s

D s i s

s

Any other section of L is of the form s for some complex valued function

and one has

D s d s D s d i s

s

which can b e read as

D d i

s

in lo cal co ordinates If one chooses a dierent trivializing section say s

expif s then the connection oneform will change according to

0

s D s D expif s i df s i

s

s

6

The more exotic p ossibility of replacing by where is a closed but nonexact

oneform on M will b e dealt with b elow It leads to a unitarily inequivalent theory

With resp ect to s the section s will b e represented by expif and this

recovers the argument given ab ove The upshot of this is that we should think

of as b eing valid in the trivializtion s m m and that we now

know how to relate changes in the symplectic p otential which it is o ccasion

ally convenient to p erform to changes of lo cal trivializations This p oint of

view actually b ecomes mandatory when one is dealing with general symplectic

manifolds M where is not necessarily exact In that case expressions like

and only make sense lo cally with say on a co ordinate patch

U while on overlaps U U of a go o d cover one has

df

where f is related to the transition function connecting the lo cal trivializing

sections s and s over U U

In terms of D the prequantum op erator P f can b e written as

P f ihD X f

f

There is another way of lo oking at P f which sheds some light on its denition

Via its Hamiltonian vector eld X the function f generates a ow

f

f f

m m

t t

of canonical transformations of M Up to an overall phase related to the

ambiguity f f c c a constant there is a unique way of lifting this ow to

an automorphism of L preserving the Hermitian structure and the compatible

connection This in turn induces a pullback action

f f

b b

t t

on sections of L and their lo cal representatives Introducing the quantity

L X f

f f

f

p f

k

p

k

the Lagrangian of f one nds that is given explicitly by

Z

t

f f f

i

b

L mdt m m exp

0

f

t t

t

h

Thus time evolution is given by the exp onential of the classical action some

thing that is highly reminiscent of the path integral There are numerous other

connections b etween GQ and path integrals see Anyway as P f can

b e expressed in terms of L as

f

P f ih X L

f f

it follows that P f is nothing but the derivative of at t

f

d

b

j P f ih

t

t

dt

We can thus interpret P f intrinsically as the generator of a connection pre

serving automorphism of L lifting the action of the Hamiltonian vector eld X

f

on M

Let us now retrun to more downtoearth matters It follows from that

the curvature of L dened by

X Y i D X D Y D X Y

is

iD h d h

The denition still makes sense for nontrivial line bundles and

P f P g ih P ff g g

is satised for all f and g provided that L is a line bundle with connection D

whose curvature twoform is h Moreover P f can still b e understo o d

as the generator of a connection preserving automorphism of L D

As is real there always exists a compatible Hermitian structure on L and we

thus arrive at the following

Denition A prequantization of a symplectic manifold M is a pair L D

where L is a complex Hermitian line bundle over M and D a compatible connec

tion with curvature h The prequantum Hilb ert space H is the completion

of the space of smo oth sections of L squareintegrable with resp ect to the Li

ouville measure on M and the Hermitian structure on the b ers

Topologically line bundles are classied by their rst Chern class c L

H M Z In de Rham cohomology c L can b e represented by the cur

vature form of any connection on L the cohomology class of the curvature

form is indep endent of the choice of connection Thus a necessary and in

fact sucient condition for a prequantization L D of a symplectic manifold

to exist is that h represent an integral cohomology class or in other

words that the integral of h over every closed orientable twosurface

in M b e an integer Such symplectic manifolds are called quantizable although

prequantizable would b e more accurate

Cotangent bundles T Q equipp ed with the canonical symplectic structure

d are always quantizable as is exact Moreover as the cohomology class of

is trivial so is any prequantum line bundle L over T Q as we had already

noted ab ove In certain cases however the quantizability condition imp oses

a quantization condition on parameters app earing in the classical system For

instance Diracs famous quantization condition on the electric charge e of a

particle moving in the eld of a magnetic monop ole can b e understo o d in this

way This is a consequence of the fact that the coupling of particles to an

Ab elian gauge eld connection A with eld strength curvature F dA can

b e accomplished by replacing the original symplectic structure d on T Q

by the charged symplectic structure

eF

F

which is still nondegenerate and closed This is equivalent to using the stan

k

dard minimal coupling prescription p p eA q with the unmo died

l l l

symplectic structure Quantizability of T Q is now equivalent to inte

F

grality of e h F If F represents a nontrivial cohomology class so that A

is only deined lo cally this gives a restriction on the p ossible values of e and

the prequantum line bundle L will b e nontrivial as well As an aside the cou

pling constant quantization conditions app earing in certain eld theories like

the WessZuminoWitten mo del and top ologically massive gauge theory can b e

understo o d in the same way

Likewise if M S the twosphere with radius r and is the volume form

r

r sin dd then is only integral for certain discrete values of r namely

r nh n Z It is by the way no coincidence that this lo oks like the

quantization rule for angular momentum or like representation theory of SU

S is a homogeneous space for SU S SU U in fact a coadjoint

orbit and quantization of S hence leads to representations of SU The

prequantum Hilb ert space is of course innite dimensional but by considering

only holomorphic sections of the prequantum line bundle which corresp onds

to a particular choice of complex p olarization one obtains nite dimensional

Hilb ert spaces which are irreducible representation mo dules of SU This

relation b etween transitive group actions homogeneous symplectic spaces and

irreducible representations is one of the origins of GQ It is appropriate to regard

GQ as a generalization of the BorelWeilBott theorem and Kirilovs metho d of

orbits to the nonhomogeneous case

As the ab ove examples may have given rise to the impression that all symplectic

manifolds M can b e made quantizable by a rescaling of the symplectic form

I will mention a simple counterexample the pro duct of two twospheres

M S S with incommensurate radii r and s Attempts have b een made

r s

to generalize GQ to such spaces but I will have nothing to say ab out this here

After having discussed this necessary condition for a prequantization to exist

we now turn to a brief discussion of the classication of prequantizations of a

quantizable symplectic manifold M As a key role is played by the con

nection D in the dention of prequantization the top ological classication of

line bundles by their Chern class is to o coarse to provide a classication of

prequantizations or prequantum line bundles on M What one needs is a

renement in which two prequantizations L D and L D are regarded as

equivalent if there is a bundle isomorphism f L L such that f D D

To address this problem in a somewhat more p edestrian manner we will need

the following terminology a connection is called at if its curvature vanishes a

at line bund le is a line bundle with a at connection Furthermore we will need

the fact that one can form the tensor pro duct E F of two vector bundles E and

F this is simply done b erwise and that the tensor pro duct of two complex

line bundles L and L is again a complex line bundle b ecause C C C

These tensor pro duct bundles inherit naturally a tensor pro duct connection

0

D D from connections on L and L In a lo cal trivialization if D

LL

D d i and D d i then D D d i Thus the curvature

of D D is simply the sum of the curvatures of D and D Furthermore

the curvature of the complex conjugate line bundle L D is minus that of

L D as D d i and L L D D d is the trivial at line bundle

with trivial connection d

This implies that given a prequantization L D and a at line bundle L D

the tensor pro duct L L D D is again a prequantization Conversely

given two prequantizations L D and L D they dier by a at line bundle

b ecause

L D L D L D L D

L D L D L D

and the second factor in the second line is at Thus the classication of

prequantizations of M amounts to the classication of at line bundles

on M and is in particular indep endent of This is quite standard and

can b e accomplished in a number of dierent ways An argument using Cech

cohomology and exact sequences can b e found in and leads to the result

that isomorphism classes of at line bundles and prequantizations are in one

toone corresp ondence with the elements of

H M U

the rst cohomology group of M with co ecients in U Alternatively one

can determine directly the mo duli space of at U connections on M mo dulo

gauge transformations which is well known to b e

Hom M U

where M is the fundamental group of M This result follows from the fact

that the holonomy of a at connection along a lo op is invariant under deforma

tions of the lo op so that a at connection is uniquely determined mo dulo gauge

transformations by its holonomies along homotopy classes of noncontractible

lo ops By the universal co ecient theorem the ab ove two expressions are

equal

There are two p ossible sources of nonequivalent at line bundles on M and

thus two kinds of contributions to H M U One is the p ossibility of having

nonequivalent at connections on a given line bundle It is of the form

b M

1

H M RH M Z U

with b M dim H M R the rst Betti number of M This can b e read as

saying that given a at connection D on the line bundle L so that any other

at connection on L is of the form D with a closed oneform D

is inequivalent to D provided that is neither integral nor a fortiori exact

We had already seen ab ove that symplectic p otentials diering by exact one

forms innitesimal gauge transformations lead to equivalent prequantizations

7 1 1 1

More precisely H M Z should b e replaced by its image i H M Z in H M R in



this expression where i is the inclusion i Z R

Connection forms diering by nontrivial integral oneforms on the other hand

are related by large gauge transformations We will see an example of this

torus worth of prequantizations b elow It has the interpretation of vacuum

angles or AharonovBohm phases

The second contribution comes from top ologically inequivalent at line bundles

As line bundles are top ologically classied by their Chern class c L

H M Z and the curvature form represents the image of this class in H M R

these corresp ond to the kernel

Ker i H M Z H M R

i kills the torsion in H M Z I will not give an example where such a

p ossibility o ccurs but want to just mention that the choice of isomorphism class

of at line bundles can in certain cases b e interpreted as a choice of statistics

Fermi versus Bose for instance

Examples

In this section we will take a brief lo ok at some twodimensional examples the

cylinder T S and the twosphere S Each has its own characteristic features

which serves to illustrate one or the other of the issues encountered ab ove in a

rather more abstract manner

Example M T S

As M is a cotangent bundle the symplectic form dpd is globally exact

d pd

and the prequantum line bundle L is trivial A prequantization of M is given

by the connection D d ih As M is not simply connected

M Z H M U U

we exp ect however to nd not a unique but a U s worth of prequantiztions

This exp ectation is indeed b orne out d is a nonexact closed oneform the

generator of H M R and we can thus mo dify the prequantum connection to

D d ih id

One way of seeing that for these are all mutually inequivalent is the

following The prequantum op erator P p of p with resp ect to the connection

D is

h P p ih

As L is trivial we can identify the prequantum Hilb ert space with the space of

functions on M which are in particular p erio dic in Likewise the Hilb ert

space in the Schrodinger representation on which is a well dened op

erator is L S Thus the sp ectrum of i is the integers and that of

P p is also discrete as exp ected and is

sp ec P p fn h n Zg

As these are only equal when is an integer this shows that for all the

quantum theories obtained from the prequantization L D are inequivalent

The parameter leads to an additional contribution to the holonomy picked up

by a state up on parallel transp ort around the circle It can thus b e regarded as

a simple toymodel of the AharonovBohm eect d representing a magnetic

eld running through the interior of the circle Alternatively the ab ove example

can b e regarded as an embryonic illustration of the eld theoretic phenomenon

of vacuum angles or theta vacua Such top ological quantization ambiguities

sup erselection sectors o ccur almost always when the conguration space

is not simply connected most prominently in fourdimensional gauge theories

where they are related to the strong CP problem

Example M S

Ab ove we have already discussed the conditions for M to b e quantizable Here

R

h so that M k is quantizable we will x the volume form by

M

i k Z As H M Z Z and M there is a unique prequantum

line bundle L D with iD k h in every top ological monop ole

k k k

sector Moreover from the arguments of the previous section we can deduce

that L is the k th tensor p ower of L and D the corresp onding tensor pro duct

k k

connection Thus all we need to determine is the generator L D I will

give three dierent descriptions of this bundle

The rst is in terms of the Hopf bration The threesphere is itself a U

bundle over S with monop ole Chern number By letting U act on

the complex plane C in the standard fashion one can asso ciate to this

U bundle over S a complex line bundle over S which is just L This

description is useful b ecause it shows that element of the prequantum

Hilb ert space H sections of the nontrivial bundle L can b e represented

by complex valued functions on S transforming equivariantly under the

action of U on S

The second makes use of the identication of S with the complex pro

jective plane CP the space of complex lines in C Over CP there

is a natural complex line bundle obtained by attaching to each p oint of

CP the complex line it represents For obvious reasons this bundle is

called the tautological line bund le and it again represents L This de

scription is useful b ecause it makes it evident that L can b e regarded as

a holomorphic line bundle

Finally the last description is in terms of lo cal co ordinates Think of

in R Let x b e x x S as b eing given by the equation x

the north and south p oles of S determined by x Then on the

co ordinate neighbourho o ds U S nfx g one can introduce the complex

co ordinates

x ix

z

x

related by z z on the overlaps of the two regions As the U are

top ologically trivial any line bundle is trivial when restricted to one of

these Thus all we have to do is to give a prescription for glueing these

trivial bundles together over say the equator If one do es this with the

k k

transition function z z one obtains the line bundle L The

k

advantage of this description is that it provides us with explicit expressions

for the symplectic p otentials and hence for the prequantum connection

D Namely on U the symplectic form can b e written as

k

dz dz

ih

jz j

and the symplectic p otentials can b e chosen to b e

z dz

ih

jz j

This explicit description will also allow us to read o immediately the

dimension of the space of holomorphic sections of L which is k the

k

dimension of the spin k representation of SU see section

Geometric Quantization I I Polarizations

Up to now GQ has b een quite straightforward and elegant Unfortunately

prequantization is not the end of the story and some additional structures have

to b e introduced to obtain a quantization of a symplectic manifold in the

sense of section from this In GQ one of these is a p olarization and this

leads to rather severe technical complications in general Most of them are

related to the fact that there is no natural measure on the space of quantum

states and that even when there is GQ is still not completely correct One is

then forced to mo dify the quantization scheme to what is known as halfform

or metaplectic quantization And although at this stage GQ b ecomes quite

successful it simultanously b ecomes rather complicated and unwieldy

In section I will show that the concept of a p olarization arises rather natu

rally in GQ when one tries to cut down the prequantum Hilb ert space The

theory of real and complex p olarizations and of Lagrangian submanifolds of

symplectic manifolds is very rich and rewarding but I will not attempt to go

far b eyond the formal denition of a p olarization

In practice there are two classes of symplectic manifolds for which GQ is

fairly well understo o d and works with comparative ease cotangent bundles and

Kahler manifolds These have natural and wellbehaved p olarizations which we

will take a lo ok at in sections and Although there are compact sym

plectic manifolds which are not Kahler and symplectic manifolds which admit

no p olarization whatso ever an understanding of these two cases is usually suf

cient for sp ecic applications

The construction of the quantum Hilb ert space and of op erators acting on it is

then the sub ject of section

Polarizations

In section we have already seen that a p ossible generalization of Schrodinger

n

quantum mechanics on T Q R is based not on the concept of a complete set

of observables as in Q but rather on that of a maximal commuting set We

have also seen that from that p oint of view it is p ossible to regard the Hilb ert

space L Q as the space of functions on the phase space constant along the

leaves of a p olarization

As this may app ear to b e a rather contrived and unnecessarily complicated

way of arriving at the Hilb ert space I will now show that the concept of a

p olarization arises quite naturally if one attempts to construct the quantum

Hilb ert space from the prequantum Hilb ert space H I want to p oint out

however that the physical justication for this pro cedure

is not based on general mathematical results such as the Borel

Weil theorem but on the way in which the construction works in

particular examples It generalizes and unies a number of quan

tization techniques that in the past have not app eared to have

any obvious connection with each other and that have sometimes

seemed overspecialized with applications only to particular physical

systems p

Roughly sp eaking the problem with the prequantum Hilb ert space H is that it

is to o large consisting of functions which dep end on all the n co ordinates

of the symplectic manifold M A way of eliminating half of these is to

demand that the wave functions are constant along n vector elds on M As

ordinary dierentiation has no invariant meaning for sections of a bundle one

must take this to mean that they are covariantly constant Thus one way to

pro ceed is to choose some ndimensional subbundle P of the tangent bundle

TM of M and to consider only those wave functions that satisfy

D X X P

where X P is short and sloppy for X is a section of P Now there could

b e nontrivial integrability conditions for those equations which would form an

obstruction to nding any or a sucient number of solutions to From

it follows that D X D Y for all X Y P Combined with

this leads to the integrability condition

D X Y ih X Y X Y P

We see that this condition is automatically satised provided that

X P Y P X Y P

and

X P Y P X Y

The rst condition means that P is integrable so that lo cally there exist integral

manifolds in M through P As these are ndimensional the second condition

means that these integral manifolds are Lagrangian We have thus arrived

precisely at the denition of a real p olarization given in section We see that

there are no lo cal integrability conditions if we demand the wave functions to

b e covariantly constant along the leaves integral manifolds of a p olarization

P ie of a Lagrangian subbundle of TM This approach which is a natural

generalization of that based on a maximal commuting set of observables thus

arises quite naturally from prequantization and is the one adopted in GQ

Life is of course not as simple as that The problem with the ab ove denition of

a p olarization is that it is far to o restrictive For instance on a twodimensional

surface a p olarization corresp onds to a nowhere vanishing vector eld S has

none and among the closed twodimensional surfaces the torus is the only one

which has The way to get around this problem is to complexify the tangent

c

bundle of M TM TM and to consider integrable Lagrangian subbundles

c

of TM These are more likely to exist while the integrability condition

is still satised We thus make the following

Denition Let M b e a symplectic manifold A p olarization P of M is

an integrable maximally isotropic Lagrangian subbundle of the complexied

c

tangent bundle TM of M

Naively one would now like to construct the quantum Hilb ert space from the

space P L of polarized sections ie sections of the prequantum line bundle L

covariantly constant parallel along P This is not as straightforward as one

might have hop ed it to b e eg b ecause H P L may b e empty We will

come back to this problem in section after having seen some examples of

p olarizations

For technical reasons one imp oses some additional conditions on P The rst

usually included in the denition of a p olarization is that the dimension of

P P T M b e constant Here P denotes the b er of P at m M and

m m m m

P the complex conjugate of P To state the other conditions we note that

m m

c

any complex subbundle F of TM satisfying F F is the complexication of

c c c

c

some real subbundle F of TM F F Thus the complex subbundles P P

c

c

and P P of TM are of the form

c c

P P D P P E

where

D P P TM E P P TM

this notation is standard no confusion with the prequantum connection D

should arise As P is integrable so is D We assume that the integral manifolds

of D are complete and we denote by M D the space of all integral manifolds of

D A p olarization is called strongly admissible if E is integrable and the spaces

M D and M E are smo oth Hausdor manifolds

In the following we will deal almost exclusively with p olarizations which are

either real

P P

8

There can still b e global integrability conditions related to the holonomy of D along the

leaves of P We will encounter these later on in the guise of BohrSommerfeld conditions

ie the complexication of a real p olarization or Kahler

P P fg

c

In the former case D E so that P D is strongly admissible if the space

of leaves of the underlying real p olarization D is smo oth and Hausdor In the

latter D fg and hence E TM so that any Kahler p olarization is strongly

admissible Other prop erties of p olarizations will b e mentioned b elow in the

context of either real or Kahler p olarizations

Real Polarizations

As noted ab ove real p olarizations are characterized by the prop erty P P

c

which implies that P D The prime example of a real p olarization is the

vertical polarization of a cotangent bundle M T Q In lo cal co ordinates it is

spanned by the vectors p tangent to the b ers of T Q Thus D is the

k

vertical tangent bundle P its complexication and the integral manifolds of

n

D are the b ers T Q isomorphic to R The space M D of integral manifolds

q

is just the conguration space Q itself and all our regularity conditions are

obviously satised

As this vertical p olarization always exists for cotangent bundles so do es once

the question of the measure has b een settled see section the Schrodinger

representation of quantum mechanics on Q based on the Hilb ert space L Q

Whether this is go o d or bad may b e a matter of debate after all in section

n

we had understo o d the emergence of L Q for Q R as a consequence of

the Stone von Neumann theorem which is not available for general Q but

this is what GQ predicts

There are real p olarizations that are not vertical p olarizations of some cotangent

bundle but there are not many more p ossibilities satisfying our rather stringent

regularity conditions To see an example of such a p olarization let us go back

to the cylinder M T S discussed as example of section Instead of

choosing the vertical p olarization spanned by p we can also choose a

horizontal p olarization spanned by as far as b eing Lagrangian and

integrable is concerned there is nothing to prove when n This leads to

n

what is known for Q R as the momentum representation In this case the

integral manifolds of D are circles S and M D R

However in general something like a horizontal p olarization momentum rep

resentation will not exist at all And even when it do es it will not necessarily

b e of the naive form is a function of the momenta This is something that

is often ignored and therefore go o d to keep in mind Again see In fact

although Q is a Lagrangian submanifold of T Q via the zero section say

it cannot b e an integral manifold of some p olarization unless Q has the rather

k nk

sp ecial form Q T R This is a consequence of the interesting result that

9

There are some interesting subtleties arising in this representation related to the emer

gence of vacuum angles and the discreteness of the sp ectrum of the momentum op erator on

the real line M D of momenta See section and

under our regularity conditions the integral manifold of a real p olarization of

any symplectic manifold M is necessarily of this form This can easily b e

proven by showing that the op erator r dened by

ir Y iX diY for X Y D

X

satises all the conditions of a partial connection and restricts to a torsion

free and at ane connection on each leaf of D r is called the Weinstein

connection For instance

X Y D r Y D

X

is equivalent to

r Y Z Z D

X

by the maximality of P and follows from the formulae of section

r Y Z ir Y Z

X X

iZ iX diY

LX iZ iY iX Z iY

Likewise the prop erty that r is torsion free

r Y r X X Y

X Y

can b e established by calculating

ir Y r X iX diY iY diX

X Y

iX LY LY iX iX Y

etc Thus the most general p ossibility is indeed an integral manifold of the

k nk

form T R The two ab ove examples are of the type k and k n

resp ectively And if the leaves are simply connected k then essentially

the only p ossibility is the vertical p olarization

This concludes our discussion of real p olarizations Polarizations with k

have their subtleties and generally force one to consider either distributional or

cohomological wave functions see section

Kahler Polarizations

Kahler p olarizations are characterized by the condition P P fg They

have this name b ecause every Kahler manifold complex manifold with a com

patible symplectic structure has a natural Kahler p olarization and conversely

the existence of such a p olarization implies that M is pseudo Kahler the

pseudo referring to the p ossible indeniteness of the Kahler metric

10

The precise statement is that if k and if there is some Lagrangian submanifold

N of M intersecting each leaf nicely transversally in exactly one p oint then there is a



natural identication of M with T N

We shall rst take a lo ok at what this means and how it works in the case of a

ndimensional symplectic vector space V where for concreteness we can

n

think of V T R We b egin with some linear algebra V is a real vector

space A complex structure on V is a linear transformation J V V with

J Such a J gives V the structure of a complex vector space where

multiplication by the complex number a ib is dened by

a ibv av bJ v

The complex structure J is called compatible with the symplectic structure

if

J v J w v w v w V

In that case v J w is symmetric in v and w and denes a nondegenerate

symmetric bilinear form g and a Hermitian metric h on V via

g v w v J w

hv w g v w i v w

h is antilinear in the rst entry and linear in the second so that eg

hJ v w ihv w

J is called p ositive if g is p ositive denite A symplectic structure with a

compatible complex structure is called a pseudo Kahler structure and a Kahler

structure if J is p ositive

c c

V can b e complexied in the obvious J indep endent way V V and V is

a complex ndimensional vector space If J is a complex structure on V then

c

J can b e diagonalized in V The i eigenspaces of J are denoted by V and

V and are spanned by vectors of the form v iJ v Obviously V and

V are complex ndimensional complex conjugates of each other and satisfy

V V fg

If J is compatible with then V and V are Lagrangian subspaces of

c c

V Conversely a Lagrangian subspace P of V satisfying P P fg denes

a compatible complex structure on V such that P is its i or i eigenspace

c

in V we will by a slightly misleading usage of terms refer to the latter as

a holomorphic polarization b ecause the corresp onding p olarized states can b e

represented by holomorphic functions

Comparing with our ab ove denition of a Kahler p olarization we see that a

Kahler p olarization equips each tangent space of M with a compatible com

plex structure A smo othly varying complex structure on the tangent bundle

of a manifold M is called an almost complex structure If this almost complex

structure is integrable in the sense that the i eigenbundles are integrable J is

called a complex structure on M and gives M the structure of a complex man

ifold ie there are lo cal holomorphic co ordinates with holomorphic transition

functions Thus b ecause p olarizations are integrable a Kahler p olarization

gives M the structure of a complex manifold with a compatible symplectic

structure Such manifolds are called pseudo Kahler manifolds And conversely

every Kahler structure J on M denes a p ositive holomorphic Kahler p o

c

larization of M via P T M the i eigenspace subbundle of TM

k

In lo cal holomorphic co ordinates z one has

j k

i dz dz

j k j k k j

it would b e b etter to introduce barred and unbarred indices at this p oint but

I will refrain from doing so Lo cally any Kahler form can b e written as

i K

for some real valued function K the Kahler p otential where

k

k

dz dz

k k

z z

d

Thus natural lo cal symplectic p otentials on a Kahler manifold are i K and

i K

n

All this is b est illustrated in the case of a at phase space M T R with

k

co ordinates q p and the canonical symplectic form We will give it the

l

n n

structure of a at Kahler manifold R C by introducing the complex

co ordinates

k k

p

p iq z

k

corresp onding to the complex structure dened by

k

J p q J q p

k k k

The symplectic form can b e written as

k l

i dz dz i K

k l

k l

K z z jz j

k l

k

The holomorphic p olarization P is spanned by the vectors z or equiva

k

lently by the Hamiltonian vector elds of the co ordinate functions z Later on

we will use the symplectic p otential i K which vanishes on P so that

K

the covariant derivative along directions in P takes the particularly simple form

k k

D z z This has the advantage that P p olarized sections can b e

identied directly with holomorphic functions in the corresp onding trivializa

tion Generally a connection p otential vanishing on a given p olarization P

j is called adapted to P Under our regularity conditions lo cal adapted

P

p otentials always exist

Another example of a Kahler manifold is the twosphere which we investigated

from the p oint of view of prequantiztion in section For the third description

of its prequantum line bundle we introduced complex co ordinates on S CP

We now recognize the symplectic form as a Kahler form with Kahler

p otential

K h log jz j

The lo cal symplectic p otentials given in are also adapted to the holomor

phic p olarization spanned lo cally by z

Geometric Quantization I I I Quantization

Now nally after having accumulated all these bits and pieces of information

we come to the quantization of symplectic manifolds This involves the deter

mination of the quantum Hilb ert space H corresp onding to a p olarization P

P

and the construction of op erators acting on H

P

After some general remarks we will lo ok at the question how to construct op

erators on the quantum Hilb ert space This turns out to b e straightforward

for observables preserving the p olarization but a rather drastic mo dication

of that pro cedure is required to asso ciate op erators to observables whose ow

moves the p olarization This will lead us to the pairing construction of Blattner

Kostant and Sternberg and to BKS kernels whose construction I will sketch in

the simplest of cases a family of p ositive Kahler p olarizations

We will then deal sep erately with the three examples of p olarizations we have

discussed ab ove vertical p olarizatons section Kahler p olarizations sec

tion and real p olarizations with nonsimply connected leaves section

They all have their particular complications and pitfalls Initially one is likely

to exp ect the example of a vertical p olarizations to b e the least problematic

of the lot coresp onding just to the familiar Schrodinger representation gener

alized to curved conguartion spaces However it turns out that there is no

natural measure on the space of p olarized states and although certain more or

less ad ho c resolutions of this problem are conceivable one is eventually con

fronted with the necessity of mo difying the entire quantization scheme I will

present a version of the halfdensity quantization scheme which is fairly easy

to understand Eventually this would have to b e replaced by the signicantly

less transparent halfform quantization scheme but this will only make a brief

app earance in the following

In the case of a general real p olarization the situation is even worse b ecause there

may b e no p olarized sections at all One is then forced to p ermit distributional

wave functions to app ear whose supp ort is concentrated on the socalled Bohr

Sommerfeld varieties in M D In section we will see how these arise in the

case of the cylinder and the harmonic oscillator in the energy representation

Given all these diculties it may thus come as a surprise that in the case of

Kahler p olarizations there is a natural measure on the space of p olarized states

and no obstruction to constructing H In fact a p ositive Kahler p olarization

P

just picks out a particular subspace of the prequantum Hilb ert space H Un

fortunately this construction fails to give correct results in even the simplest

of quantum mechanical examples the harmonic oscillator The same wrong

sp ectrum of the harmonic oscillator is also predicted if one tries to quantize the

system in a real p olarization The required mo dication is again that which

works in the case of vertical p olarizations namely halfform or metaplectic

quantization This scheme also app ears to account correctly for changes in the

p olarization and for the quantization of certain op erators which do not preserve

a given p olarization but the general theory is far from completely understo o d

at the moment

Polarized States and the Construction of Quantum Op era

tors

We b egin with some general remarks Let us x a prequantization L D of a

symplectic manifold M and a strongly admissible p olarization P The basic

idea is as mentioned rep eatedly ab ove to construct the quantum Hilb ert space

from the linear space P L of P p olarized sections of L D ie of smo oth

sections of L satisfying

D X X P

Ideally one would like to go ahead and dene the quantum Hilb ert space H as

P

H H P L ie as the space of P p olarized sections of L square integrable

P

with resp ect to the Liouville measure on M This however usually do es

not work either b ecause p olarized sections are not square integrable eg the

Schrodinger wave functions which dep end only on the co ordinates so that the

momentum integral will diverge or b ecause there are no smo oth p olarized

sections of L at all These diculties are b est illustrated by concrete examples

and we will do this b elow First however we will come to the issue of quantum

op erators acting on p olarized states which can b e stated and addressed in more

generality

In section to every function on M we were able to asso ciatexd a prequantum

op erator P f

P f ihD X f

f

acting on the sections of L and satisfying the quantization conditions QQ

in particular

Q P f P g ihP ff g g f g C M

On the basis of our exp erience with at space quantum mechanics and keeping

in mind the Gro enewald van Hove theorem we exp ect to have to sacrice at

least parts of when moving from prequantization to quantization We

also exp ect to have to mo dify the assignment P in general b ecause we dont

exp ect nor want all quantum op erators to b e at most rst order dierential

op erators In fact we know from quantum mechanics that the usual

kinetic energy term quadratic in the momenta should come out as prop ortional

n

to the Laplacian at least if Q R

The rst step is to check which of the prequantum op erators P f can b e

promoted directly to op erators on P L the necessary mo dications due to half

density quantization are irrelevant for our present purp oses and will b e given in

the next section The requirement is obviously that P f map p olarized states

to p olarized states ie

D X X P D X P f X P

The obstruction to this comes from the term D X X so that is equiv

f

alent to

X X P X P

f

X P P

f

This is a very intuitive result b ecause it says that a classical observable f denes

an op erator on the space of P p olarized states via the prequantum assignment

f P f provided that its ow leaves the p olarization P invariant This

f

leaves P invariant follows also from the argument given in if

t

one can use directly to dene the op erator Qf on p olarized states Let

M us call the space of these functions which is not particularly large C

P

It is closed under Poisson brackets and contains in particular the functions

whose Hamiltonian vector elds span the p olarization The latter are diagonal

on p olarized states in the sense that

Qf f

For example in the case of the vertical p olarization of a cotangent bundle one

nds

P k f C T Q X

f

P

p

k

2 2

f P k f

l l

p p p

p q q

l k l

k

2

f

p p

k l

so that f C T Q i it is at most linear in the momenta

P

k

f C T Q f q p f q f q p

k

P

For such f the quantum op erator is

k

Qf q f q q ih f q

k

q

This expression will still have to b e mo died by a correction term coming from

the measure see b elow By the same reasoning as ab ove one nds that

the only real valued observables preserving the holomorphic p olarization on

n n

T R C see section are of the form

k k k l

f z z f f z f z f z z

k k k l

where f R and f and f f are complex constants This makes the

k k l l k

holomorphic representation particularly suitable for the quantization of the har

monic oscillator whose Hamiltonian is prop ortional to jz j see section

For the time b eing this is all I have to say ab out p olarization preserving observ

ables and we are now confronted with the question what to do with functions

which move the given p olarization P Another way of stating this in which the

f

b

p olarization plays a more passive role is that via its canonical lift

t

to L D the Hamiltonian ow on M generated by such a function f moves a

P p olarized state out of P L The evolved state

f

b

t

t

is now p olarized with resp ect to the pulledback p olarization

f

P P

t

t

P L P L

t t

Thus evidently what we need is a way of relating states to each other which are

p olarized with resp ect to dierent p olarizations To pro ceed let us make the

simplifying assumption that the quantum Hilb ert spaces H H constructed

t P

t

from the family of p olarizations P can all b e regarded as subspaces of the

t

prequantum Hilb ert space H This assumption holds for instance when P is

t

a family of p ositive Kahler p olarizations In that case we have the orthogonal

wrt the scalar pro duct on H pro jections

0 0

H H

t

t t t

H H H

t t t P

available to pro ject the state back to H Thus in analogy with we

t P

can now attempt to dene the quantum op erator Qf on H by

P

d

j Qf ih

t t t

dt

f

d

b

ih j

t t

t

dt

This is the basic idea of the Blattner Kostant Sternberg construction Even

in this situation determining when exists when it exists as a selfadjoint

op erator and when the pro jections are unitary is a highly nontrivial problem

In the general case when the quantum Hilb ert spaces cannot b e regarded as

subspaces of H the orthogonal pro jection op erators have to b e replaced by

some other less natural linear maps from one Hilb ert space H to the other

P

0

and the problem b ecomes corresp ondingly more dicult H

P

One case which is tractable is the following Consider a symplectic vector space

n

regarded as the at symplectic manifold M T R and let P P and P b e

the vertical horizontal and holomorphic p olarization resp ectively In all three

cases we have an irreducible representation of the Heisenberg group on the

corresp onding quantum Hilb ert space Thus by the Stone von Neumann

theorem section the existence of unitary linear op erators from H to

P

00 0

is guaranteed The former is just the Fourier transform and H to H H

P

P P

from the co ordinate to the momentum representation and the latter is the

Bargmann transform realizing the unitary equivalence of the conguration and

holomorphic representations

It can moreover b e shown that in the case of a vertical p olarization the quan

tum op erator asso ciated to the kinetic energy function in at space comes out

correctly to b e the Laplacian plus scalar curvature terms in the case of a

curved conguration space The calculation is unfortunately to o lengthy to

b e repro duced here see

By such considerations one is also naturally led to the imp ortant and subtle

question to which extent the resulting quantum theory dep ends on the choice of

p olarization and which p olarizations give rise to unitarily equivalent theories

Some interesting progress has b een made on this question recently motivated

by top ological and conformal eld theory Unfortunately I will not b e able to

go into this here For an explanation of halfform quantization from this p oint

of view see

The Vertical Polarization and HalfDensities

We now discuss the construction of the quantum Hilb ert space in the most

familiar lo oking case of the vertical p olarization Recall that this is the p olar

c

ization P D spanned by the tangents to the b ers of a cotangent bundle

M T Q The prequantum line bundle L D is trivializable and in terms

of the trivializing section s m m the Hermitian structure on the b ers

and the compatible connection p otential are

k

s s m h h p dq

k

is adapted to the vertical p olarization so that the covariant derivative along

the b ers of P is simply the ordinary derivative acting on functions on T Q

D p p

k k

Thus p olarized sections coresp ond to functions which are indep endent of the

momenta p ie to functions on Q We now need to turn this into a Hilb ert

k

space The rst guess would b e to use the Hilb ert space structure on the

prequantum Hilb ert space H and to dene the quantum Hilb ert space H as

P

H P L ie as the space of sqare integrable P p olarized sections of L Un

fortunately this space is empty as p indep endent wave functions are certainly

k

not square integrable with resp ect to the Liouville measure the integral over

the b ers diverges

In this particular example a partial remedy to the problem immediately comes

to mind one should integrate p olarized sections not over M but over Q which

is more invariantly to b e regarded as the space M D of leaves of the p olariza

tion However there is no natural measure on Q If a metric on Q is given

k l

p erhaps implicitly via a Hamiltonian of the form H g p p then

k l

p

n

g d q g det g which can b e used to dene one can construct the density

k l

a scalar pro duct on P L Alternatively and more generally one can try to

work from the outset with a bundle whose p olarized sections are squarero ots

of densities nforms on Q so that the scalar pro duct of two such ob jects is

automatically well dened This leads to the halfdensity quantization scheme

Under the assumption that Q is oriented we can following pro ceed as

follows for the full edged halfdensity quantization scheme see or the rst

edition of The material will b e presented in such a way that the extension

to other real p olarizatons with simply connected leaves should b e selfevident

Let us introduce the determinant line bundle

n c

Det Q T Q

whose sections are complex valued volume forms on Q As we assumed Q to b e

orientable and oriented we can form the square ro ot Det Q eg by choos

ing real and p ositive transition functions for Det Q and using their p ositive

square ro ots to dene Det Q Via the pro jection T Q Q we can pull

these line bundles back to T Q where we denote them by

Det Q K

D

Det Q K

D D

It should b e kept in mind that as bundles over T Q their spaces of sections are

now C T Qmo dules ie sections can b e multiplied by functions on T Q

Thus sections of K are not necessarily pullbacks of volume forms on Q We

D

would now like to replace the prequantum line bundle L by L L In

D D

order to dene P p olarized sections we need the notion of a covariant derivative

of sections of along P We dene the covariant derivative of a section of

D

K along P by

D

D X iX d

This partial connection is at

D X D Y D X Y

b ecause d can have at most one vertical direction and is the pullback

of an nform on Q i it is covariantly constant along P gives rise to a

covariant derivative on sections of via the obvious denition

D

D X D X D X or D X

For vector elds preserving the vertical p olarization one can also dene the

Lie derivative of sections of K via the usual formula L di id for

D

dierential forms Obviously LX D X if X P L extends to

D

in the same way as D in

Sections of L are of the form s where s is a section of L and a section of

D

and we call s a P wave function if

D

D X s D X s s D X X P

As the pro duct of two sections of is a section of K and the scalar pro duct

D D

on the b ers

s s s s

is parallel along P by we can identify it with an nform on Q We have

thus arrived at our goal of dening a natural scalar pro duct on the space of

p olarized sections namely

Z

s s s s

Q

The quantum Hilb ert space H is now dened to b e the L completion of the

P

space of smo oth P wave functions with resep ct to this scalar pro duct

The construction of quantum op erators acting on H now pro ceeds exactly

P

as in section For a p olarization preserving function f we saw that the

prequantum op erator P f was well dened on the space P L of P p olarized

sections of L It thus remains to dene its action on sections of Keeping

P

in mind that P f is nothing but the generator of the canonical ow of X

f

on sections of L and that its generator on dierential forms is the Lie

derivative we set

Qf s P f s ihsLX

f

In particular if we x a volume element on Q then P wave functions are of

the form s q with scalar pro duct

Z

Q

and the required mo dication to is

k k

ih div f q q ih f q Qf q f q

k

q

Here the divergence of a vector eld Y on Q with resp ect to is the function

on Q dened by

div Y LY diY

This correction term can b e regarded as arising from a particular symmetric

k

op erator ordering of the classical expression f p an issue which as such is

k

p

n

not present in GQ It vanishes eg when g d q and Y is a Killing vector

of the metric g

k l

The construction of op erators corresp onding to observables not preserving the

vertical p olarization pro ceeds via BKS kernels whose naive construction I indi

cated in section Matters are complicated by the fact that one has to take

into account the variation in In order to keep track of relative phase factors

D

t

in the corresp onding Hilb ert spaces one eventually has to mo dify the denition

of in such a way that it do es not dep end on the orientation of M D The

D

resulting quantization is halfform or metaplectic quantization Virtually the

same correction term as ab ove app ears as the metaplectic correction to a p o

larization preserving op erator in other p olarizations In that form it will turn

out to b e resp onsible for the ground state energy of the harmonic oscillator see

the discussion in sections and

Kahler Quantization and Metaplectic Correction

We now deal with the simpler case of a p ositive Kahler p olarization We thus

consider a Kahler manifold M J a prequantum line bundle L D and

choose P T M see section to b e the p olarization spanned by the i

k

eigenspaces of J Lo cally P is spanned by the vector elds z where the

k

z are holomorphic co ordinates on M The space of holomorphic P p olarized

sections of L D can b e shown to b e a closed subspace of the prequantum

Hilb ert space H It is thus a Hilb ert space in its own right which we take to b e

the quantum Hilb ert space H of the system

P

To obtain a more explicit description of H it is useful to work with lo cal

P

connection p otentials adapted to P We noted in section that a convenient

choice is i K where K is the Kahler p otential Let us see how this

K

works in the case of a Kahler vector space According to K is given by

k l

K z z

k l

so that

l k

i z dz

K

k l

To account for this change from to we have to change the lo cal trivializing

K

section Tracing through the formulae of section one nds that s is to b e

replaced by

k l k l k

q q p p ip q s s exp

K

k l k l k

h

Polarized sections of the trivial prequantum line bundle are thus of the form

sz z s z z z

K

n

where z is a holomorphic function on C It follows from s s and

that the Hermitian structure in this trivialization is given by

s s z z expjz j h expK h

K K

From this we can also read o that with resp ect to the canonical symplectic

p otential and the section s p olarized wave functions are of the form

z z z exp jz j h

k

as could of course also have b een deduced directly from solving D z s

in this trivialization Either way H can b e identied with the space of holo

P

n

morphic functions on C with scalar pro duct

Z

n n

z z exp K h d p d q

n

C

It is clear from this expression that the Hilb ert space would have b een empty if

we had chosen a nonp ositive Kahler p olarization with K corresp onding to an

indenite quadratic form b ecause there would not have b een any normalizable

holomorphic functions

As we already noted ab ove this holomorphic representation with

k k k

z Qz z z z Qz h

k

z

is unitarily equivalent to the Schrodinger representation It is also known as

k k

the oscil lator representation with Qz and Qz interpreted as creation and

annihilation op erators resp ectively As one has a direct particle o ccupation

number interpretation in this representation it is the conventional starting

p oint in canonical quantum eld theory

This representation is particularly convenient for quantizing the harmonic os

cillator as its Hamiltonian we take n for notational convenience

H q p p q z z

preserves the holomorphic p olarization cf Acting on holomorphic func

tions the corresp onding pre quantum op erator is

z QH z h z

z

n

which sp ells do om b ecause its eigenfunctions are the monomials z with eigen

values nh It is of course well known from quantum mechanics that this is

incorrect and that the sp ectrum should b e shifted by the ground state energy

h In the standard treatment this term arises from symmetrizing

z z z z H z z

b efore substituting the op erators for z and z so that one obtains the

quantum op erator

b

H hz

z

This shows that in spite of the fact that everything has run so smo othly so

far in the case of p ositive Kahler p olarizations the necessity arises to mo dify

the quantization pro cedure for Kahler manifolds as well Interestingly it turns

out that the halfform quantization scheme which solves a number of problems

arising in the context of real p olarizations also takes care of the present short

coming Namely one of the consequences of the metaplectic correction is that

it gives rise to an additional term in the expression for the quantum op erator of

a p olarization preserving observable similar to the one encountered in

A recip e for constructing the corresp onding quantum op erator will b e given

b elow For the harmonic oscillator the eect of this will b e precisely to replace

by This is quite remarkable b ecause a priori it is not at all clear

what halfforms have to do with op erator ordering

A general rule of thumb for including the metaplectic correction to the op erator

corresp onding to a p olarization preserving ob ervable is the following see

Let the p olarization P b e spanned by the n complex vector elds X k

k

n If f preserves the p olarization P there is a matrix af a f of

k l

functions on M satisfying

l

X X a f X

f k l

k

In terms of this matrix the halfform corrected quantum op erator is

Qf P f ih traf

In the case of the harmonic oscillator P is spanned by and the Hamiltonian

z

vector eld is

z X iz

H

z z

Thus

i X

H

z z

leading to the corrected expression

QH h z

z

and the energy sp ectrum

sp ecQH fn h n g

In the general case of a Kahler manifold M J everything works as ab ove In

particular expressions like and are still valid lo cally and allow one

to represent p olarized sections lo cally by holomorphic functions on M Certain

interesting and new features arise when M is compact so that the only globally

dened holomorphic functions on M are the constants To explain these I will

make use of some algebraic geometry see eg

First of all we can use lo cal nonvanishing p olarized sections of L as trivializing

sections Then the transition functions will b e holomorphic and hence give L

the structure of a holomorphic Hermitian line bundle over M The space of

holomorphic sections of L can b e identied with the zeroth sheaf cohomology

of M with values in the sheaf L of germs of holomorphic sec group H M L

tions of L By general theorems this is nite dimensional so that the quantum

Hilb ert space will b e nite dimensional as well

dim H dim H M L

P

It is for this reason that compact symplectic manifolds are usually used to

n

introduce internal degrees of freedom For instance if one quantizes T R M

using the vertical p olarization in the rst and the holomorphic representation

in the second factor the resulting Hilb ert space is a tensor pro duct of L Q

with the nite dimensional Hilb ert space H M If M is eg a coadjoint orbit

P

of a group G such that H M carries an irreducible representation of G then

P

the resulting tensor pro duct wave functions are usually interpreted as wave

functions taking values in this representation or carrying a representation of G

I will illustrate this in the case of the twosphere whose prequantization we had

discussed in Example of section Recall that we introduced two co ordinate

patches U with lo cal complex co ordinates z and that the transition functions

k k

for the line bundle L were given by z z Furthermore for k

k

the Kahler p otential symplectic form and adapted symplectic p otential were

K h log jz j

dz dz

ih

jz j

z dz

ih

K



jz j

see To determine the global holomorphic sections of L in

k

this trivialization we have to check which lo cal holomorphic functions on U

can b e patched together via the transition functions This is easy A basis for

l

holomorphic functions on U is given by the monomials z and on U by

m

z for l and m nonnegative integers We thus have to nd the solutions to

the equation

l k m

z z z

This gives

l k m

which has nonnegative integer solutions for l k and m k Thus the

dimension of the space of holomorphic sections is k precisely the dimension

of the spin k representation of SU As the patch U covers everything

but one p oint on S we can dene the scalar pro duct by integration over U

alone As in the Hermitian structure on the b ers of L gives an extra

k

contribution to the measure of the form we now call z simply z

k

expk K h jz j

so that overall the scalar pro duct with the standard normalization is

Z

i z z dz dz

k

jz j

the additional p ower of two coming from the symplectic form

There are two other things worth noting ab out On the one hand if the

Kahler p olarization is not p ositive then dim H M L and the Hilb ert

space is empty as in the noncompact case On the other hand if L is

suciently p ositive then the dimension of H can b e computed from the

P

RiemannRo ch theorem More precisely the RR theorem expresses the Euler

characteristic

X

i i

dim H M L M L

i

in terms of characteristic classes

Z

M L chLT M

M

Here chL is the Chern character of L and can b e represented by exp h

while T M is the Todd class of M whose precise form will not interest us If

k

one replaces L by L and hence by k for some p ositive integer k then

for some suciently large value of k the higher cohomology groups in

will vanish and the right hand side of calculates directly the dimension

of H In particular T M do es not contribute for k and one nds see

P

Z

n

n k n

k k

dim H M L Vol M

n

h

h n

M

The limit k can b e interpreted as the semiclassical limit h and one

thus recovers the folklore wisdom that in the semiclassical limit the number

of quantum states is equal to the number of cells in phase space measured in

units of h Equation has b een used recently by Witten to calculate the

symplectic volume of certain mo duli spaces of at connections from quantum

eld theory

Real Polarizations and BohrSommerfeld Varieties

In this nal section we will following take a brief lo ok at the compli

cations which can arise when the leaves of a real p olarization are not simply

connected In that case there can b e global integrability conditions to the equa

tion dening p olarized states These lead to the necessity of p ermitting

distributional wave functions whose supp ort is restricted to lower dimensional

subvarieties of M

c

Let P D b e a real p olarization and L D a prequantization of M

We denote by a leaf integral manifold of D and more sp ecically by

m

the leaf passing through m M The op erator D restricted to covariant

dierentiation along P induces a at connection D on Lj If is not simply

connected then it is p ossible for D to have nontrivial holonomy along the

noncontractible lo ops in On the other hand the condition implies

that is a covariantly constant section of L It is thus invariant under

parallel transp ort and in particular cannot pick up a phase from the non

trivial holonomy of D Therefore either or the holonomy group of D

is trivial ie D is the trivial at connection Call S M the union of p oints

in M such that D is trivial S is known as the Bohr Sommerfeld variety

m

and S M if all the are simply connected From the ab ove it follows that

m

p olarized sections of L D vanish in the complement of S

P L supp S

Instead of working with such distributional wave functions it is p ossible to

work with socalled cohomological wave functions ie one trades singularities

for cohomology as is familiar from algebraic geometry see

The relation with the usual Bohr Sommerfeld quantization conditions is that

I

m S expih

for all lo ops in where is a lo cal symplectic p otential In terms of lo cal

m

k k

canonical co ordinates q p one can write as p dq and thus b ecomes

l k

the quantization condition

I

k

p dq hn n Z

k

Taking into account the contribution exp id to the holonomy from the

at connection on the bundle of halfforms d dened up to an integer one

obtains the modied Bohr Sommerfeld conditions

I

k

p dq h n d

k

As the ab ove discussion was rather abstract let us now take a lo ok at two simple

examples where these distributional wave functions and the corresp onding Bohr

Sommerfeld conditions arise quite naturally and turn out to b e imp ortant

The rst of these is the cylinder whose prequantization and quantization in

the vertical p olarization we have already dealt with in Example of section

Here we shall lo ok at the same mo del in the momentum representation

This is the representation dened by the horizontal p olarization spanned

by Consequently p olarized sections have to satisfy

D

recall equation or

i

p p h p

h

Polarized sections are thus of the form

i

p h p p exp

h

where p is some function of the momentum The rst thing to note is that

this is not what one would naively have exp ected the momentum representation

to lo ok like The phase factor app ears b ecause of the choice of symplectic

p otential pd If we had b een able to choose dp as a symplectic

p otential adapted to the horizontal p olarization p olarized states would have

b een of the exp ected form p However this p otential is not globally dened

and the fact that we are dealing with quantum mechnics on the circle and not

on the real line is reected in the p eculiar form of the wave functions It is this

which guarantees that the vacuum angle is equally visible in the momentum

representation although the space of momenta itself is top ologically trivial

Now we have to remember that the prequantum Hilb ert space is the space of

L functions on the cylinder so that in particular has to b e p erio dic in

From it follows that this is only p ossible if the supp ort of p is restricted

to those p which satisfy

p n h

for some integer n This is nothing but the Bohr Sommerfeld condition

and obviously leads inevitably to distributional wave functions with supp ort on

S Z Along the way we have also recovered the discrete and shifted sp ectrum

of the momentum op erator diagonal in this representation

As a second example let us take a brief lo ok at the onedimensional harmonic

oscillator in the real energy representation This corresp onds to the p olarization

dened by the Hamiltonian vector eld X of the Hamiltonian H In p olar

H

co ordinates r on the plane we have

r H r

r dr d dH d

X

H

To avoid having to deal with singular p olarizations we remove the origin from

the plane and thus the phase space is R nfg with the ab ove symplectic form

Polarized wave functions are of the form

i

D X r exp r r

H

h

so that single valuedness of imp oses the Bohr Sommerfeld condition

r nh

Unfortunately this is only almost correct as it leads to the same wrong energy

sp ectrum we initally found in the previous section As is also apparent from the

form of the wave function top ologically this example is the same as the cylinder

we discussed ab ove so that we could obtain the correct sp ectrum by netuning

However this is rather ad ho c A more the value of the vacuum angle to

satisfactory way of obtaining the result is to take into account the contribution

from the bundle of halfforms In the previous section this changed the form

of the energy op erator Here it gives rise to the mo died Bohr Sommerfeld

condition The at connection on the bundle of halfforms is nontrivial

with d This leads to the same shift in the sp ectrum as the choice

and to the correct result

References

PAM Dirac The Principles of Quantum Mechanics Fourth Edition Clarendon

Press Oxford

JM Souriau Quantication Geometrique Commun Math Phys

Structure des Systemes Dynamiques Duno d Paris

B Kostant Quantization and Unitary Representations in Lecture Notes in Math

ematics Vol Springer Berlin

CJ Isham Topological and Global Aspects of Quantum Theory in Relativity

Groups and Topology II North Holland Amsterdam

S Axelro d S della Pietra and E Witten Geometric Quantization of Chern

Simons Gauge Theory J Di Geom

MJ Gotay Constraints Reduction and Quantization J Math Phys

A Ashtekar and M Stillerman Geometric Quantization and Constrained Systems

J Math Phys

M Blau Constraints and Polarizations Phys Lett B On the

Geometric Quantization of Constrained Systems Class Quantum Grav

AA Kirilov Elelements of the Theory of Representations Springer Berlin

R Abraham and JE Marsden Foundations of Mechanics Second Edition Ben

jamin Reading MA

VI Arnold Mathematical Methods of Classical Mechanics Springer New York

V Guillemin and S Sternberg Symplectic Techniques in Physics Cambridge Uni

versity Press Cambridge

NMJ Woo dhouse Geometric Quantization Second Edition Clarendon Press

Oxford

J Sniatycki Geometric Quantization and Quantum Mechanics Springer New

York

NE Hurt Geometric Quantization in Action Reidel Dordrecht

R Bott and LW Tu Dierential Forms in Algebraic Topology Springer New

York

M Blau What happens to the Vacuum Angle in the Momentum Representation

Mo d Phys Lett A On the Representation Independence of Topolog

ical Eects in Quantum Field Theory Int J Mo d Phys A

F Hirzebruch Topological Methods in Algebraic Geometry Springer New York

E Witten Quantum Gauge Theories in Two Dimensions Commun Math Phys