Radical Interpretation, the Primacy of Communication, and the Bounds of Language

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Radical Interpretation, the Primacy of Communication, and the Bounds of Language Empedocles European Journal for the Philosophy of Communication Volume 1 Number 1 © 2009 Intellect Ltd Article. English language. doi: 10.1386/ejpc.1.1.123/1 Radical Interpretation, the primacy of communication, and the bounds of language Eli Dresner Tel Aviv University Abstract Keywords In the first section of this paper I review the notion of ‘Radical Interpretation’, Davidson introduced by Donald Davidson in order to account for linguistic meaning philosophy of and propositional thought. It is then argued that this concept, as embedded in communication Davidson’s whole philosophical system, gives rise to a view of communication interpretation as a key explanatory concept in the social sciences. In the second section of the paper it is shown how this view bears upon the question as to what the bounds of linguistic behaviour are. As opposed to major psychological and sociological perspectives on language, Davidson’s communication-centred position gives rise to an inclusive, context-dependent answer to this question. Donald Davidson was one of the main figures in twentieth century ana- lytic philosophy. In a long series of articles, collected in several volumes (Davidson 1980, 1984, 2001, 2004), Davidson develops a far-reaching yet unified philosophical system, with implications for numerous phil- osophical domains. Thus Davidson made significant contributions to such diverse philosophical areas as the philosophy of rationality and action, the metaphysics of events, and the analysis of metaphor. However, at the heart of Davidson’s philosophy stands his view of lan- guage – in particular, his anchoring both linguistic meaning and propo- sitional thought in communicative interaction (Dresner 2006). The concept that best expresses this aspect of Davidson’s views is ‘Radical Interpretation’, introduced in (Davidson 1984a) and discussed in many places since its formulation. The notion is a descendent of Quine’s ‘Radical Translation’ (Quine 1960) – a term coined to designate a hypothetical situation in which a linguist approaches a completely isolated linguistic community. In such a situation, all the linguist has to go on in breaking into the foreigners’ language is their behaviour, and thus the translation manual that the linguist ends up constructing cap- tures only such behavioural data. A key tenet of Quine’s is that this scenario exhausts the essentials not only of this arcane situation, but rather of linguistic interaction in general. His view is that when under- standing each other’s speech we correlate linguistic behaviour with our experience of the world around us, and that there is nothing to linguis- tic meaning beyond such correlation. Thus Quine is both an empiricist EJPC 1 (1) pp. 123–134 © Intellect Ltd 2009 123 EJPC_1.1_art_Dresner_123-134.indd 123 11/19/09 4:40:54 PM and a behaviourist, and there is no significant philosophical role in his philosophy for such traditionally (and intuitively) central notions as thought and truth. Davidson breaks away from this behaviourist, empiricist position in several important ways, but retains (at least) one key aspect of it: he endorses an intersubjectivist view of linguistic meaning. That is, Davidson holds that whatever the internal processes that give rise to our utterances may be, these processes are not accessible to our inter- locutors, and therefore cannot be part of the meaning of what we say, which must be available in principle to those we converse with. Thus Davidson subscribes to a constructivist view of communication (Buttny 1986; Deetz 1994): according to his position communication is not the context where meaning is manifested or transmitted, but rather the locus where it is created (more on this below). Davidson develops this key idea along several far-reaching trajec- tories (which are distinct from (and often inconsistent with) Quine’s views, as noted above). Here, in a nutshell, are three of them. (More detailed expositions can be found in many places (Evnine 1991, LePore and Ludwig 2007), including an overview from the perspective of com- munication theory in Dresner 2006.) First, Davidson maintains that we assign meaning to another’s utterances not by translating them into our own language, but rather by associating them with things in the world surrounding us. This is what is behind Davidson’s talk of radi- cal interpretation (rather than translation) as the hypothetical process that brings to the fore what is essential to linguistic communication. The way utterances are associated with the world in this process, according to Davidson, is through the notion of truth. That is, a sys- tematic assignment of truth-conditions to the sentences in someone’s language consists in understanding the literal meaning of these sen- tences. Such an assignment will require, among other things, a logical analysis of these sentences, and an association of the referring expres- sions that appear in them with objects in the world. (An elaboration of – and criticisms against – the role allocated to truth in this account can be found in the aforementioned references.) Second, Davidson does not ignore propositional thought in his account of language (as behaviourists like Quine do). As a proponent of the constructivist conception of communication, though, he does not view meaning as flowing from thought to language; rather, the same process through which meaning is assigned to our utterances (i.e., interpretation) is viewed by Davidson as giving rise to the attach- ment of content to our internal mental states as well. In the process of interpretation we are not only assigning meaning to each other’s utter- ances, but rather also propositional content to each other’s beliefs and desires (as well as other propositional attitudes). Thus communicative interaction is viewed as constituting both linguistic meaning and prop- ositional thought, in an interdependent fashion. Third (and finally), Davidson views interpretation as a local, inter- subjective process that does not depend in any essential way on a social context or setting. Thus Davidson leaves no room for convention in his account of the most basic underpinnings of language. Of course, it 124 Eli Dresner EJPC_1.1_art_Dresner_123-134.indd 124 11/19/09 4:40:54 PM cannot be denied that there are elaborate conventions that govern the linguistic behaviour of the members of a given community, and that these conventions help make linguistic interaction easy and efficient. However, Davidson argues that the role of convention in language is regulative rather than constitutive: linguistic communication does not depend on a set of conventions for its practice (as, e.g., many games do) – it is similar in this respect to various other basic functions of ours (such as eating) that are subject to numerous conventions in most socie- ties but do not derive their identity and feasibility from such conven- tions. Interpretation, Davidson tells us, requires only two creatures facing each other and associating meaning with each other’s utterances in the way outlined above. They need not be aware of any convention, nor do they even have to manifest the same regularities in their speech: it is only necessary that each of them be interpretable to the other. Let us turn now to consider how these ideas bear upon the status of communication as an explanatory concept and as a field of research. The primacy and unity of communication as such are often chal- lenged. The field’s two main neighbouring disciplines – psychology and sociology – typically conceive of the questions that communica- tion scholars try to answer as auxiliary to the more basic problems that are found in their own respective domains. Psychology, on the one hand, construes content as primarily an attribute of cognition, and only secondarily of communication. Thoughts, that are internal to each agent, come first in the explanatory order, and the plethora of questions regarding the way they are transmitted from one agent to another come second. The transmission model of communication, which plays a central role within communication studies, echoes this perspective. Sociology, on the other hand, aims at explaining a variety of phenomena in the interpersonal and public domains through a set of concepts of normative character. Viewed from this perspective com- munication processes in general, and language in particular, are ana- lysed on a par with other aspects of social life. What are the conventions that govern human communication processes of various kinds? How are they related to such notions as group identity and boundaries, stratification and status? In this context, too, communi- cation does not play any special role: it is not the focus of attention in an account of systems of (social and cultural) meaning. Furthermore, if communication analysis is indeed subsumed under the sociological perspective, then various types of non-conventional communication (both in the human and the animal domains) are divorced from com- munication processes that are thought of in conventional terms (such as language): the latter (conventional) kinds of communication are of interest from the said perspective, while the former (non-conventional kinds) are not. We see that an adoption of either of these two perspectives, or a combination of the two, raises a formidable challenge to the coherence of a discipline that takes the notion of communication as the centre of inquiry. Those who do indeed adopt this critical view of the disci- pline may acknowledge the great practical importance of analysing Radical Interpretation, the primacy of communication, and the bounds… 125 EJPC_1.1_art_Dresner_123-134.indd 125 11/19/09 4:40:54 PM communication processes, especially in view of the rapid develop- ment of new communication technologies and the influence that these developments have on various aspects of our lives. However, such an acknowledgement does not entail the allocation of a special role to communication-related concepts in our understanding of human beings. The philosophy of Donald Davidson offers the scholar of commu- nication a way out of this predicament.
Recommended publications
  • Donald Davidson ERNEST LEPORE and KIRK LUDWIG
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVIII (2004) Donald Davidson ERNEST LEPORE AND KIRK LUDWIG avidson, Donald (Herbert) (b. 1917, d. 2003; American), Willis S. and Marion DSlusser Professor, University of California at Berkeley (1986–2003). Previ- ously Instructor then Professor in Philosophy at: Queens College New York (1947–1950), Stanford University, California (1950–1967), Princeton University (1967–1969), Rockefeller University, New York City (1970–1976), University of Chicago (1976–1981), University of California at Berkeley (1981–2003). John Locke Lecturer, University of Oxford (1970). One of the most important philosophers of the latter half of the twentieth century, Donald Davidson explored a wide range of fundamental topics in meta- physics, epistemology, ethics, and the philosophies of action, mind, and language. His impact on contemporary philosophy is second only to that of his teacher W. V. O. Quine, who, along with Alfred Tarski, exerted the greatest influence on him. Given the range of his contributions, his work emerges as surprisingly systematic, an expression and working out of a number of central guiding ideas. Among his most important contributions are 1. his defense of the common sense view that reasons, those beliefs and desires we cite in explaining our actions, are also causes of them [11], 2. his groundbreaking work in the theory of meaning, and his proposal, based on Tarski’s work on recursive truth definitions for formal languages, for how to formulate a compositional semantic theory for a natural language [29, 46, 47, 50, 51], 3. his development of the project of radical interpretation as a vehicle for investigating questions about meaning and the psychological attitudes involved in understanding action [7, 15, 42, 44, 48], 309 310 Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth and Meaning—In Perspective
    March 2008 March 2008 Truth and Meaning – In Perspective by Scott Soames School of Philosophy University of Southern California To Appear In Truth and Its Deformities Edited by Peter French Midwest Studies in Philosophy Volume XXXII 2008 Truth and Meaning – In Perspective Scott Soames My topic is the attempt by Donald Davidson, and those inspired by him, to explain knowledge of meaning in terms of knowledge of truth conditions. For Davidsonians, these attempts take the form of rationales for treating theories of truth, constructed along Tarskian lines, as empirical theories of meaning. In earlier work1, I argued that Davidson’s two main rationales – one presented in “Truth and Meaning”2 and “Radical Interpretation,”3 and the other in his “Reply to Foster”4 – were unsuccessful. Here, I extend my critique to cover an ingenious recent attempt by James Higginbotham to establish Davidson’s desired result. I will argue that it, too, fails, and that the trajectory of Davidsonian failures indicates that linguistic understanding, and knowledge of meaning, require more than knowledge of that which a Davidsonian truth theory provides. I begin with a look at the historical record. The Evolution of an Idea: A Historical Summary When Davidson enunciated his idea, in the 1960s, that theories of meaning can be taken to be nothing more than theories of truth, it met with a warm reception. For devotees of Ordinary Language, its attraction lay in its promise of providing a theoretically respectable way of grounding claims about meaning, and distinguishing them from claims about use, that those who still placed meaning at the center of philosophy had come to recognize the need for.5 For 1 Scott Soames, “Truth, Meaning, and Understanding,” Philosophical Studies, 65, 1992; 17-35, and chapter 12 of Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 2 (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press), 2003.
    [Show full text]
  • Davidson-Radical-Interpretation.Pdf
    Radical Interpretation by Donald DAVIDSON Kurt utters the words "Es regnet" and under the right conditions we know that he has said that it is raining. Having identified his utterance as intentional and linguistic, we are able to go on to interpret his wonds: we can say what his words, on that occasion, meant. We could we know that would enable us to do this? How could we come to know it? The first of these questions is not the same as the question what we do know that enables us to interpret the words of others. For there may easily be something we could know and don't, know- ledge of which would suffice for interpretation, while on the other hand it is not altogether obvious that there is anything we actually know which plays an essential role in interpretation. The second ques- tion, how we could come to have knowledge that would serve to yield interpretations, does not, of course, concern the actual history of lan- guage acquisition. It is thus a doubly hypothetical question: given a theory that would make interpretation possible, what evidence plau- sibly available to a potential interpreter would support the theory to a reasonable degree? In what follows I shall try to sharpen these questions and suggest answers. The problem of interpretation is domestic as well as foreign: it surfaces for speakers of the same language in the form of the question, how can it be determined that the language is 'the same? Speakers of the same language can go on the assumption that for them the same expressions are to be interpreted in the same way, but this does not indicate what justifies the assumption.
    [Show full text]
  • Davidson Versus Chomsky: the Case of Shared Languages”
    Nordic NSP Studies in Pragmatism Helsinki — 2015 Jonathan Knowles “Davidson versus Chomsky: The Case of Shared Languages” In: Ulf Zackariasson (Ed.) (2015). Action, Belief and Inquiry—Pragmatist Perspectives on Science, Society and Religion (pp. 300–319). Nordic Studies in Pragmatism 3. Helsinki: Nordic Pragmatism Network. issn-l 1799-3954 issn 1799-3954 isbn 978-952-67497-2-3 Copyright c 2015 The Authors and the Nordic Pragmatism Network. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 3.0 Unported License. CC BY NC For more information, see http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/ Nordic Pragmatism Network, NPN Helsinki 2015 www.nordprag.org Davidson versus Chomsky: The Case of Shared Languages Jonathan Knowles Norwegian University of Science and Technology 1. Introduction Donald Davidson and Noam Chomsky are two giants in the contemporary study of language. Davidson is famous for employing Tarskian theories of truth as theories of meaning, and has made several concrete proposals concerning the semantical analysis of various constructions of English, such as belief reports and action sentences. Chomsky is the progenitor of modern theoretical linguistics. For him the analysis of the syntactical structures underlying natural languages is part of cognitive and ultimately biological science, insofar as its goal is to uncover certain aspects of the human brain, conceived at a certain level of abstraction. Both Davidson and Chomsky see a need for theorizing about language in formal or quasi- formal terms, and both see this need as at least partly grounded in the productive and systematic nature of language: its capacity for infinite expression and indefinite structural novelty.
    [Show full text]
  • Donald Davidson and the Mirror of Meaning , Was Written Between 1987 and 1991
    Davidson’s Holism: Epistemology in the Mirror of Meaning Jeff Malpas 1 To Margaret 2 The methodology of interpretation is... nothing but epistemology seen in the mirror of meaning. – Donald Davidson, ‘Thought and Talk’ 3 Table of Contents Foreword to the new edition Acknowledgements Introduction: radically interpreting Davidson I. From translation to interpretation 1. The Quinean background 1.1 Radical translation and naturalized epistemology 1.2 Meaning and indeterminacy 1.3 Analytical hypotheses and charity 2. The Davidsonian project 2.1 The development of a theory of meaning 2.2 The project of radical interpretation 2.3 From charity to triangulation II. Holism and interpretation 3. The idea of psychological holism 3.1 Holism and the psychological 3.2 Holism and anti-holism 3.3 Holism and rationality 3.4 The nature and extent of psychological holism 4. Indeterminacy and psychological structure 4.1 The indeterminacy and incompleteness of interpretation 4.2 The intentional-horizonal structure of the psychological 4.3 Dialogue, unity and world 5. Charity and understanding 4 5.1 The nature and role of charity 5.2 Charity, error and reference 5.3 The presupposition of agreement 5.4 The nature of understanding 5.5 Charity and morality III. Reality, knowledge and truth 6 A holistic ‘theory’ of knowledge 6.1 ‘The third dogma’ 6.2 Relativism, horizonality and psychological unity 6.3 Holism and skeptical doubt 7 Truth and the world 7.1 Skepticism, realism and anti-realism 7.2 Realism, anti-realism and truth 7.3 The centrality of truth 7.4 A horizonal account of truth Epilogue: Davidson, Brandom, and McDowell Bibliography Index 5 Foreword Although extensively revised during 2002, and again in 2010, the core of this book, originally published as Donald Davidson and the Mirror of Meaning , was written between 1987 and 1991.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Truth-Theoretic Semantics and Its Limits Kirk Ludwig Philosophy
    Preprint: forthcoming in a special issue of Argumenta on the anniversary of Donald Davidson's birth in 2017. Truth-theoretic Semantics and Its Limits Kirk Ludwig Philosophy Department Indiana University 1. Introduction Donald Davidson was one of the most influential philosophers of the last half of the 20th century, especially in the theory of meaning and in the philosophy of mind and action. In this paper, I concentrate on a field-shaping proposal of Davidson’s in the theory of meaning, arguably his most influential, namely, that insight into meaning may be best pursued by a bit of indirection, by showing how appropriate knowledge of a finitely axiomatized truth theory for a language can put one in a position both to interpret the utterance of any sentence of the language and to see how its semantically primitive constituents together with their mode of combination determines its meaning (Davidson 1965, 1967, 1970, 1973a). This project has come to be known as truth-theoretic semantics. My aim in this paper is to render the best account I can of the goals and methods of truth-theoretic semantics, to defend it against some objections, and to identify its limitations. Although I believe that the project I describe conforms to the main idea that Davidson had, my aim is not primarily Davidson exegesis. I want to get on the table an approach to compositional semantics for natural languages, inspired by Davidson, but extended and developed, which I think does about as much along those lines as any theory could. I believe it is Davidson’s project, and I defend this in detail elsewhere (Ludwig 2015; Lepore and Ludwig 2005, 2007a, 2007b, 2011).
    [Show full text]
  • Truth and Meaning Redux
    Philos Stud DOI 10.1007/s11098-010-9536-x Truth and meaning redux Ernie Lepore • Kirk Ludwig Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010 Abstract In this paper, we defend Davidson’s program in truth-theoretical semantics against recent criticisms by Scott Soames. We argue that Soames has misunderstood Davidson’s project, that in consequence his criticisms miss the mark, that appeal to meanings as entities in the alternative approach that Soames favors does no work, and that the approach is no advance over truth-theoretic semantics. Keywords Donald Davidson Á Truth-theoretic semantics Á Meaning Á Scott Soames 1 Introduction Forty-three years ago, Donald Davidson, in ‘‘Truth and Meaning’’ (1967), suggested that insight into meaning might be gained by reflection on how to construct and to confirm a Tarski-style truth theory for a natural language. The suggestion has been influential, but it has not been well understood. In a recent paper, Scott Soames argues that this project has now run its course (2008). He argues that Davidson’s two rationales for his project were unsuccessful and that what he sees as the most promising recent attempt along the same lines, by Affiliation of K. Ludwig after July 1, 2010: Department of Philosophy, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN 47405-7005, USA. E. Lepore (&) Center for Cognitive Science, Rutgers University-New Brunswick, Piscataway, NJ 08854-8020, USA e-mail: [email protected] K. Ludwig Philosophy Department, University of Florida, Gainesville, FL 32611-8545, USA e-mail: ludwig@ufl.edu 123 E. Lepore, K. Ludwig Jim Higginbotham, is likewise unsuccessful.
    [Show full text]
  • Donald Davidson ERNEST LEPORE and KIRK LUDWIG
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVIII (2004) Donald Davidson ERNEST LEPORE AND KIRK LUDWIG avidson, Donald (Herbert) (b. 1917, d. 2003; American), Willis S. and Marion DSlusser Professor, University of California at Berkeley (1986–2003). Previ- ously Instructor then Professor in Philosophy at: Queens College New York (1947–1950), Stanford University, California (1950–1967), Princeton University (1967–1969), Rockefeller University, New York City (1970–1976), University of Chicago (1976–1981), University of California at Berkeley (1981–2003). John Locke Lecturer, University of Oxford (1970). One of the most important philosophers of the latter half of the twentieth century, Donald Davidson explored a wide range of fundamental topics in meta- physics, epistemology, ethics, and the philosophies of action, mind, and language. His impact on contemporary philosophy is second only to that of his teacher W. V. O. Quine, who, along with Alfred Tarski, exerted the greatest influence on him. Given the range of his contributions, his work emerges as surprisingly systematic, an expression and working out of a number of central guiding ideas. Among his most important contributions are 1. his defense of the common sense view that reasons, those beliefs and desires we cite in explaining our actions, are also causes of them [11], 2. his groundbreaking work in the theory of meaning, and his proposal, based on Tarski’s work on recursive truth definitions for formal languages, for how to formulate a compositional semantic theory for a natural language [29, 46, 47, 50, 51], 3. his development of the project of radical interpretation as a vehicle for investigating questions about meaning and the psychological attitudes involved in understanding action [7, 15, 42, 44, 48], 309 310 Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig 4.
    [Show full text]
  • One Hundred Years of Donald Davidson Introduction
    One Hundred Years of Donald Davidson Introduction Maria Cristina Amoretti University of Genova Mario De Caro Roma Tre University Francesca Ervas University of Cagliari 1. Some Hints on Davidson’s Philosophy Donald Davidson (1917-2003) is one of the few contemporary philosophers of the analytic tradition who offered significant contentious contributions to many dif- ferent areas of philosophy while preserving a semi-systematic character in his writ- ings. His output was huge, ranging from decision theory to philosophy of lan- guage, from metaphysics to philosophy of action, from philosophy of mind to epistemology. In this introduction we shall focus on a limited number of themes, which we believe better exemplify the originality of Davidson’s thought. 1.1 Theory of Meaning and Radical Interpretation According to Davidson’s first theory of meaning, a satisfactory theory of mean- ing for natural languages (that is, a theory specifying a systematic interpretation of all the potential sentences of a specific language) must take the form of an ax- iomatic theory. To begin with, the meaning of the words of a certain natural language must be defined by way of a finite set of axioms. Next, the meaning of all the sentences of that language must be derived through suitable rules of in- ference that define a potentially infinite number of theorems of the form ‘s means that p’. The most original aspect of his project is its purely extensional nature. Fol- lowing his teacher Quine, Davidson rejects intentional entities, such as inten- tions, meanings or translations, as they would create exactly the same kinds of problems that a good theory of meaning is supposed to resolve.
    [Show full text]
  • Gumm Colostate 0053N 11776.Pdf
    THESIS DAVIDSON AND THE IDIOLECTIC VIEW Submitted by Derek Gumm Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University Fort Collins, Colorado Summer 2013 Master’s Committee: Advisor: Michael Losonsky Jane Kneller Edwin Chong Copyright by Derek Gumm 2013 All Rights Reserved ABSTRACT DAVIDSON AND THE IDIOLECTIC VIEW In this thesis, I defend and expand Donald Davidson’s view of language and linguistic meaning. I begin by looking at two positions that appreciate the sociality of language and linguistic meaning in two different ways. One view, as exemplified by Michael Dummett, sees the meaning of words as a feature of a language that holds independently of any particular speaker, while the other view, as exemplified by Davidson, sees meaning as depending on particular speakers and interpreters, their intentions, and their interactions. I find a serious tension in the former view and side with the latter, which I dub the idiolectic view of language. In the second chapter, I analyze Davidson’s claim that understanding gives life to meaning. Using this analysis as a jumping off point, I outline the primary features of the Davidsonian idiolectic program. Finally, I conclude that the idiolectic features of this position place a special emphasis on the moment at which two people’s personal understanding of language overlap and that such an emphasis is best understood in terms of events as particulars. In the third and final chapter, I argue that an ontology that countenances events as particulars is required for the idiolectic view of interpretation to get off the ground.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Cambridge University Press 0521790433 - Donald Davidson Edited by Kirk Ludwig Excerpt More information Introduction KIRK LUDWIG Donald Davidson has been one of the most influential philosophers work- ing in the analytic tradition in the last half of the twentieth century. He has made seminal contributions to a wide range of subjects: the philos- ophy of language and the theory of meaning, the philosophy of action, the philosophy of mind, epistemology, metaphysics, and the theory of ra- tionality. His principal work, spread out in a series of articles stretching over nearly forty years, exhibits a unity rare among philosophers contribut- ing to so many different topics. His essays are elegant, but they are also noted for their compact, sometimes cryptic style, and for their difficulty. Themes and arguments in different essays overlap, and later papers often presuppose familiarity with earlier work. Together, they form a mosaic that presents a systematic account of the nature of human thought, action, and speech, and their relation to the natural world, that is one of the most subtle and impressive systems to emerge in analytic philosophy in the last fifty years. The unity of Davidson’s work lies in the central role that reflection on how we are able to interpret the speech of another plays in understanding the nature of meaning, the propositional attitudes (beliefs, desires, inten- tions, and so on), and our epistemic position with respect to our own minds, the minds of others, and the world around us. Davidson adopts as method- ologically basic the standpoint of the interpreter of the speech of another whose evidence does not, at the outset, presuppose anything about what the speaker’s words mean or any detailed knowledge of his propositional attitudes.
    [Show full text]
  • Donald Davidson on Truth, Meaning and the Mental
    Introduction: Davidson’s philosophical project Ernie Lepore and Kirk Ludwig Donald Davidson’s work has had a pervasive influence on analytic philosophy throughout the last half century. His contributions lie primarily in the theory of meaning, the philosophy of mind and action, epistemology, and metaphysics. This volume focuses on themes connected with his work in the theory of meaning, philosophy of mind, and epistemology. The introduction first provides an overview of Davidson’s work. We pay special attention to his work on truth-theoretic semantics and its integration with the project of radical interpretation, his conception of the nature of mental states, and his account of our knowledge of things around us and of our own minds. This will set the stage for a brief overview of the more detailed examinations of particular themes connected with Davidson’s work that follow. 1 Truth-theoretic semantics In a series of papers in the 1960s and 1970s, beginning in 1965 with “Theories of Meaning and Learnable Languages” (Davidson 2001a) and in 1967 with “Truth and Meaning” (Davidson 2001c), Davidson introduced and defended one of the few really novel approaches to the theory of meaning in the latter half of the twentieth century. Central to his proposal was the suggestion that an axiomatic truth theory modeled after the truth definitions that Tarski showed how to construct for formal languages could be used to give what he called “a constructive account of the meaning of the sentences” in a natural language (Davidson 2001a, p. 3). The exact import of David- son’s suggestion and whether he took himself to be pursuing a traditional project in a novel way, a reduction of meaning to truth conditions, or urging a reform of the aims of semantics, has been a matter of controversy.
    [Show full text]