UC Santa Barbara UC Santa Barbara Electronic Theses and Dissertations

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

UC Santa Barbara UC Santa Barbara Electronic Theses and Dissertations UC Santa Barbara UC Santa Barbara Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Tracking down the Conditions for Singular Thought Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/8tf002wz Author Lee, Jeonggyu Publication Date 2018 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Santa Barbara Tracking down the Conditions for Singular Thought A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Jeonggyu Lee Committee in charge: Professor Nathan Salmon, Chair Professor Daniel Korman Professor Teresa Robertson September 2018 The dissertation of Jeonggyu Lee is approved. _____________________________________________ Daniel Korman _____________________________________________ Teresa Robertson _____________________________________________ Nathan Salmon, Committee Chair August 2018 Tracking down the Conditions for Singular Thought Copyright © 2018 by Jeonggyu Lee iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Studying philosophy in UCSB has been a very special experience for me. I was extremely lucky to have had the chance to study and interact with many nice people in the UCSB philosophy community. So, I first would like to thank everyone in this community. I have got much help from them not only academically but also socially and mentally. Being adjusted to the new environment was not easy, but with their help, I have been able to pursue my Ph.D., and this dissertation finally comes to have the property of existence. I am especially grateful to my committee members: Nathan Salmon, Daniel Korman, and Teresa Robertson. It was Teresa’s class that I took for the first time in UCSB, so this class considerably affected me to build my way to do philosophy. From her, I have learned some basic skills, which are essential for being a good scholar in the tradition of analytic philosophy. As a committee member for both of my qualifying paper and dissertation, she also has provided me with extremely helpful comments for my dissertation; we sometimes discuss it via Skype. I would like to express my deepest gratitude for all of her help. Dan has been the best critic of some of my ideas. He has always provided insightful comments and forceful objections. It was sometimes really challenging to come up with replies to his comments; we sometimes debated more than 2 hours at a café in Santa Barbara downtown. It is undeniable that having a debate with him, the quality of my dissertation has significantly improved. He has also helped me know how to formulate my ideas in a clear and neutral way, and I sometimes got the information of related articles from his extensive knowledge about anthologies. Dan might not agree with this, but I would like to heartfully appreciate the fact that Dan is not an ordinary object but is an extraordinarily helpful object for me. iv My greatest philosophical debt is to Nathan. The motivation of this dissertation is from Nathan’s thought-provoking seminars in Spring 2013 and in Spring 2015, and especially from his insightful paper, “How to Measure the Standard Meter”. I was first interested in the contingent a priori , and wanted to develop the idea in his paper. However, studying this topic, I realized that since it is about knowing the singular contingent proposition a priori , I had to study about the conditions for singular thought first, which constitutes the main part of my dissertation. I can’t thank Nathan enough for being patient with me to write this dissertation. I think that I am fortunate to be on the right track for studying philosophy as a beginning scholar in that his teaching has made me stay focused on trying to know well about some foundational issues for studying philosophy. He has always been willing to help me, and now I got more than 10 hardcopy papers with his written comments. I come to have the tendency to think that the name “Nathan” is the abbreviation of the definite description “the greatest academic advisor of mine”. I also would like to thank so much to Kyle Dickey, Paolo Bonardi, Jordan Dopkins, Sam Cumming, Billy Dunaway, and Noa Latham for their helpful written comments on some parts of my dissertation. Very special thanks to my English advisor, David Mokriski. He has proofread almost most parts of my dissertation (except these acknowledgements. So, if there is some clumsy English wording here, then it is my fault.) I am also grateful to people outside of UCSB. First, I must thank Jinho Kang, my former advisor in Seoul National University, for introducing me philosophy of language when I was in South Korea. He encouraged me to study philosophy of language abroad, which now turned out the very good decision. I also thank Wooram Lee, who started his Ph.D. at USC in the same year I did. Studying philosophy abroad, we become familiar friends by having v casual philosophical discussions, sharing our difficulties as a typical Asian student in philosophy, but especially by making philosophically terrible and sarcastic jokes. Some people in the Korean community in Santa Barbara deserve more than common thanks. Changmin Lee, a postdoc researcher in materials at UCSB, has built lots of unforgettable memories I have in the past six years. Joonho Back, a graduate student in ECE, and I have explored various aspects of American culture as much as possible. My colleague Sangsu Kim has always supported me and made the department life more pleasant. I also thank Hoontaek Oh and Seon Kim for being my friends in Santa Barbara. Finally, I would like to thank my old friends and family. Thanks to Kwangdong Roh, Jongbong Lee, Jeongwoo Park and Seonghoon Jeong for providing me the emotional support. Above all, this dissertation is dedicated to my parents, Kyunjae Lee and Jinhee Ahn (as well as my brother Seonggyu Lee). Without their support, financial, emotional, and otherwise, I would be entirely incapable of pursuing my Ph.D. in philosophy and of writing this dissertation. vi VITA OF JEONGGYU LEE July 2018 EDUCATION B.S. Physics Education, Seoul National University (2007) B.A. Philosophy, Seoul National University (2007) M.A. Western Philosophy, Seoul National University (2009) Ph.D. Student Philosophy, Seoul National University (2009 – 2012) M.A. Philosophy, University of California, Santa Barbara (2015) Ph.D. (expected) Philosophy, University of California, Santa Barbara (2018) PROFESSIONAL EMPLOYMENT 2010-12: Teaching Assistant, Department of Philosophy, Seoul National University 2013-2017: Teaching Assistant, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Santa Barbara PUBLICATIONS “In Defense of Hume’s Skeptical Argument against Induction” (2015) Chulhak (Philosophy) 123: 153-169 “Contextualism, Relativism, and the ‘Faultless Disagreement’” (2012) Chulhakjuk Bunsuk (Philosophical Analysis) 26: 45-73 “On the Problem of Fixing the Reference of a Name and a New Description Theory” (in Korean) (2010) Chulhak (Philosophy) 102: 81-107 PRESENTATIONS “Tracking down the Conditions for Singular Thought” Conference on Contemporary Philosophy in East Asia , National Chengchi University, Taiwan (August 2018) Berkeley-Stanford-Davis Grad Conference , Stanford University (May 2018) “Against Predicativism about Names” the Society for Exact Philosophy , University of Connecticut (May 2018) American Philosophical Association Pacific Division Colloquium Session, San Diego (March 2018) Central States Philosophical Association ,Washington University in St. Louis (October 2017) “Knowing-wh and Singular Thought” Grad Colloquium , University of California, Santa Barbara (December 2016) “In Defense of Skepticism about Knowing Contingent Truths A Priori ” Conference on Contemporary Philosophy in East Asia , Seoul National University, South Korea (August 2016) “Logical Pluralism as Contextualism” Language & Epistemology Workshop , Yonsei University, South Korea (September 2014) “Contextualism, Relativism, and the ‘Faultless Disagreement’” Seoul Philosophy Graduate Student Conference , Yonsei International Campus, South vii Korea (May 2012) “Towards a New Description Theory of Reference” BESETO Conference of Philosophy , Peking University, Beijing, China (January 2011) “A New Description Theory of Reference Fixing and a Solution to Semantic Objections” BESETO Conference of Philosophy , Seoul National University, South Korea (January 2010) “The Fundamentality of Success in Science” BESETO Conference of Philosophy , University of Tokyo, Japan (January 2009) “Is A Posteriori Necessary Truth Possible?” World Congress of Philosophy , Seoul National University, South Korea (July - August 2008) “The Problem of Reference in Science” Philosophy Graduate Workshop , Chinese University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong (February 2008) SCHOLARSHIPS The Ralph W. Church Scholarship, University of California, Santa Barbara (2012 – 2017) The Brain Korea 21 Scholarship, Department of Philosophy, Seoul National University (2007 –2012) Full Scholarship, Department of Philosophy, Seoul National University (2012) Honor Student Scholarship, Department of Physics Education, Seoul National University (2002-2006) AWARDS The Aida and Philip F. Siff Prize in Philosophy for Best Essay, University of California, Santa Barbara (2018) The Woogok Grand Prize for the best M.A. Thesis, Department of Philosophy, Seoul National University (2009) The Myungkyung Grand Prize for the best B.A. Thesis, Department of Philosophy, Seoul National University (2007) The Excellence Prize for Essay Writing Competition, Center for Teaching and Learning, Seoul
Recommended publications
  • Peter Thomas Geach, 1916–2013
    PETER GEACH Peter Thomas Geach 1916–2013 PETER GEACH was born on 29 March 1916 at 41, Royal Avenue, Chelsea. He was the son of George Hender Geach, a Cambridge graduate working in the Indian Educational Service (IES), who later taught philosophy at Lahore. George Geach was married to Eleonore Sgnonina, the daughter of a Polish civil engineer who had emigrated to England. The marriage was not a happy one: after a brief period in India Eleonore returned to England to give birth and never returned to her husband. Peter Geach’s first few years were spent in the house of his Polish grandparents in Cardiff, but at the age of four his father had him made the ward of a former nanny of his own, an elderly nonconformist lady named Miss Tarr. When Peter’s mother tried to visit him, Miss Tarr warned him that a dangerous mad woman was coming, so that he cowered away from her when she tried to embrace him. As she departed she threw a brick through a window, and from that point there was no further contact between mother and son. When he was eight years old he became a boarder at Llandaff Cathedral School. Soon afterwards his father was invalided out of the IES and took charge of his education. To the surprise of his Llandaff housemaster, Peter won a scholarship to Clifton College, Bristol. Geach père had learnt moral sciences at Trinity College Cambridge from Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore, and he inducted his son into the delights of philosophy from an early age.
    [Show full text]
  • Hacker's Complaint
    VOL. NO. JULY CONTENTS ARTICLES Intentionalism and the Imaginability of the Inverted Spectrum Eric Marcus Metaphysical Arguments against Ordinary Objects Amie L. Thomasson Kant’s Transcendental Strategy John J. Callanan True Emotions Mikko Salmela Wittgenstein and Strong Mathematical Verificationism Cyrus Panjvani DISCUSSIONS Hacker’s Complaint Scott Soames Are There Non-Existent Intentionalia? Alberto Voltolini CRITICAL STUDY The Sort of Creature You Are Anselm W. Müller BOOK REVIEWS BLACKWELL PUBLISHING FOR THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB AND THE UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. , No. July ISSN – DISCUSSIONS HACKER’S COMPLAINT B S S My goal in writing ‘Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century’ was to identify and explain the most important achievements of analytic philosophy which every student of the subject should be aware of, as well as those of its failures from which we have the most to learn. I attempted to do this by constructing a history that was itself a piece of analytic philosophy in its emphasis on analysis, reconstruction and criticism of arguments. In rebutting Hacker’s critique of it, I explain how my goal shaped my selection of topics, with special reference to the ordinary language period. I correct his misrepresentations of my treatment of the philosophers of this period, I demonstrate his failure to grasp, or understand the significance of, the Kripkean necessary a posteriori, and I reveal the misconceptions in his criticism of my interpretation of the ‘Tractatus’. I I am grateful to the Editors for inviting me to reply to P.M.S. Hacker’s review in this journal of my Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century.1 I begin with his complaint about the materials I chose to discuss: In its selection of materials it is unrepresentative: significant figures are omitted and pivotal works are not discussed ..
    [Show full text]
  • Wholes, Parts, and Numbers Author(S): Nathan Salmon Source: Noûs, Vol
    Wholes, Parts, and Numbers Author(s): Nathan Salmon Source: Noûs, Vol. 31, Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives, 11, Mind, Causation, and World (1997), pp. 1-15 Published by: Blackwell Publishing Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2216122 Accessed: 05/03/2009 14:22 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Blackwell Publishing is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Noûs. http://www.jstor.org Philosophical Perspectives, 11, Mind, Causation, and World,1997 WHOLES, PARTS, AND NUMBERS The Fifth Philosophical Perspectives Lecture Nathan Salmon University of California, Santa Barbara If it'snot one thing, it's two.
    [Show full text]
  • Pp. 555-595. Understanding Belief Reports David Braun in This Paper, I
    Appeared in Philosophical Review 105 (1998), pp. 555-595. Understanding Belief Reports David Braun In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. The theory is Russellianism, sometimes also called `neo-Russellianism', `Millianism', `the direct reference theory', `the "Fido"-Fido theory', or `the naive theory'. The objection concerns substitution of co-referring names in belief sentences. Russellianism implies that any two belief sentences, that differ only in containing distinct co-referring names, express the same proposition (in any given context). Since `Hesperus' and `Phosphorus' both refer to the planet Venus, this view implies that all utterances of (1) and (2) express the same proposition and have the same truth value.1 (1) Hammurabi believes that Hesperus is visible in the evening. (2) Hammurabi believes that Phosphorus is visible in the evening. The Substitution Objection is basically this: utterances of (1) and (2) can differ in truth value. More cautiously: a competent speaker could rationally think that they differ in truth value, and that is very strong evidence that they can. Two of the best-known proponents of Russellianism, Nathan Salmon and Scott Soames, have formulated a (by now familiar) reply to the Substitution Objection.2 They say that speakers who think that utterances of (1) and (2) differ in truth value are failing to distinguish correctly between what the utterances semantically express and what they pragmatically convey. Utterances of these sentences can pragmatically convey propositions that differ in truth value, 1 and so speakers who do not correctly distinguish between what they pragmatically convey and what they semantically express may wrongly judge that the utterances themselves differ in truth value.
    [Show full text]
  • INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS
    INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS Volume 173 Robert Ginsberg Founding Editor Peter A. Redpath Executive Editor Associate Editors G. John M. Abbarno Matti Häyry Mary-Rose Barral Steven V. Hicks Gerhold K. Becker Richard T. Hull Raymond Angelo Belliotti Mark Letteri Kenneth A. Bryson Vincent L. Luizzi C. Stephen Byrum Alan Milchman H. G. Callaway George David Miller Robert A. Delfino Alan Rosenberg Rem B. Edwards Arleen L. F. Salles Andrew Fitz-Gibbon John R. Shook Francesc Forn i Argimon Eddy Souffrant William Gay Tuija Takala Dane R. Gordon Anne Waters J. Everet Green John R. Welch Heta Aleksandra Gylling Thomas F. Woods a volume in Cognitive Science CS Francesc Forn i Argimon, Editor INTENTIONALITY Past and Future Edited by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Cover Design: Studio Pollmann The paper on which this book is printed meets the requirements of “ISO 9706:1994, Information and documentation - Paper for documents - Requirements for permanence”. ISBN: 90-420-1817-8 ©Editions Rodopi B.V., Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Printed in the Netherlands CONTENTS Preface vii List of Abbreviations ix ONE The Necessity and Nature of Mental Content 1 LAIRD ADDIS TWO Reading Brentano on the Intentionality of the Mental 15 PHILIP J. BARTOK THREE Emotions, Moods, and Intentionality 25 WILLIAM FISH FOUR Lockean Ideas as Intentional Contents 37 GÁBOR FORRAI FIVE Normativity and Mental Content 51 JUSSI HAUKIOJA SIX The Ontological and Intentional Status of Fregean Senses: An Early Account of External Content 63 GREG JESSON
    [Show full text]
  • Direct Reference and Vague Identity
    1 This article appeared in Philosophical Topics 28/1 (Spring 200): 177-192. DIRECT REFERENCE AND VAGUE IDENTITY In 1957, reporters asked maverick producer Mike Todd why he bought a huge 29-carat engagement ring for Elizabeth Taylor. Todd answered “Thirty carats would have been vulgar.” Todd’s quip absurdly implies he knew that 30 carats is the threshold for vulgarity. But most philosophers think stopping here misses the root of the joke. They think there is a more fundamental absurdity; that it is even possible for a single carat to make the difference between a vulgar ring and a non-vulgar ring. We epistemicists defend the possibility. The law of bivalence implies that discriminative terms (ones that apply to some but not all things) have sharp boundaries. Consequently, classical logic permits few degrees of freedom when solving the sorites paradox. One can follow the incoherentists (Wheeler 1967, Unger 1979) and conclude that nothing is vulgar. One can blaze a new path and conclude everything is vulgar. Or one could follow the epistemicists and say that there are some vulgar things, some non-vulgar things, and nothing lies between the Vulgar and the Non-vulgar. Epistemicism goes beyond conservatism about logic. Ordinary vocabulary must also be preserved. We epistemicists think that ordinary words apply to pretty much what ordinary folks assume they apply to. Thus our double conservatism obeys the time-honored dictum Loquendum enim est ut plures, sentiendum ut pauci (Augustine Niphus Comm. In Aristotelem de 1 Gen. Et. Corr., Bk. I, folio 29). “Think with the learned and speak with the vulgar.” Do epistemicists have a passion for precision? Consider the Victorian British bachelor, Phileas Fogg, protagonist of Mike Todd’s 1956 academy award winning film Around the World in 80 Days (based on the Jules Verne story).
    [Show full text]
  • What Does It Mean to Say That Logic Is Formal?
    WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO SAY THAT LOGIC IS FORMAL? by John Gordon MacFarlane A.B., Philosophy, Harvard College, 1991 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 1994 M.A., Classics, University of Pittsburgh, 1997 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2000 i Robert Brandom, Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy (Director) Nuel Belnap, Alan Ross Anderson Distinguished Professor of Philosophy (Second Reader) Joseph Camp, Professor of Philosophy Danielle Macbeth, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Haverford College (Outside Reader) Kenneth Manders, Associate Professor of Philosophy Gerald Massey, Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy ii WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO SAY THAT LOGIC IS FORMAL? John Gordon MacFarlane, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2000 Much philosophy of logic is shaped, explicitly or implicitly, by the thought that logic is distinctively formal and abstracts from material content. The distinction between formal and material does not appear to coincide with the more familiar contrasts between a pri- ori and empirical, necessary and contingent, analytic and synthetic—indeed, it is often invoked to explain these. Nor, it turns out, can it be explained by appeal to schematic inference patterns, syntactic rules, or grammar. What does it mean, then, to say that logic is distinctively formal? Three things: logic is said to be formal (or “topic-neutral”) (1) in the sense that it provides constitutive norms for thought as such, (2) in the sense that it is indifferent to the particular identities of objects, and (3) in the sense that it abstracts entirely from the semantic content of thought.
    [Show full text]
  • CRITICAL STUI)Y the Philosophy of KARL POPPER Tile
    Philosophia Vol. 6 Nos. 3-4 Ps'. 463.4o Septem rDecemt'er tum / CRITICAL STUI)Y THE PhIlOSOPhY OF KARL POPPER PART!: BIOLOGY & EVOLUTIONARY EPISTEMOLOGY W.W. hARTLEY, Ill TilE PhILOSOPHY OP KARL POPPER edited by Paul A. Schilpp, Two volumes, Open Court, Library of Living Philosophers, La Salle, 1974, 1323 pp., $30.00. The philosophical perspective celebrated in the latest member of the distinguished Schilpp series is the most radical yet presented in The Library of Living Philosophers. Radical for this simple reason: Sir Karl Popper is not really a participant in the contemporary professional philosophical dialogue; quite the contrary, he has ruined that dialogue. If he is on the right track, then the majority of professional philosophers tlte world over have wasted or are wasting their intellectual careers. The gulf between Popper's way of doing philosophy and that of the bulk of contemporary professional philosophers is as great as that between astronomy and astrology.* I believe that Karl Popper is on the right track. I ant a bit reluctant to admit this. For although I spent the first ten years of lny professional life in close collaboration with Popper and his ideas, I snt the second decade o( my career, only recently • elapsed, trying to avoid both. From 1 955 to 1958 I studied Popper's work intensively at llarvard despite the warnings of my teachers • there about this "difficult man". In 1958 I went to London as a kind of pilgrim to become first Popper's student and then for four I express my thanks to the following persons, who have been kind enosigh to rcad aod conitneist on all or part of this first instullrn ml, and who have sometimes protested my views: Joseph Agassi, t)onald T.
    [Show full text]
  • Paradoxes of Intensionality Version Of: March 1, 2007 Dustin Tucker and Richmond H
    Paradoxes of Intensionality Version of: March 1, 2007 Dustin Tucker and Richmond H. Thomason Philosophy Department, University of Michigan Abstract We identify a class of paradoxes that are neither set-theoretical or semantical, but that seem to depend on intensionality. In particular, these paradoxes arise out of plausible properties of propositional attitudes and their objects. We try to explain why logicians have neglected these paradoxes, and to show that, like the Russell Paradox and the direct discourse Liar Paradox, these intensional paradoxes are recalcitrant and challenge logical analysis. Indeed, when we take these paradoxes seriously, we may need to rethink the commonly accepted methods for dealing with the logical paradoxes. 1. Introduction Contemporary work on the paradoxes of logic and set theory is framed by ideas that go back to the 1920s and 1930s. In 1925, Frank Ramsey divided the paradoxes into those (like the Russell Paradox) that arise within mathematics, and those (like the Liar Paradox) that do not. Having made his division of the paradoxes, Ramsey took the Liar and related paradoxes to be extralogical, involving an “empirical” linguistic element. But later, in work published in 1936, Alfred Tarski showed that the Liar Paradox does arise even in rigorously presented semantic theories of formalized languages, making a compelling case that the enterprise of producing these theories belongs to logic. At the same time, he demonstrated how the para- dox could be avoided by relativizing truth to a language and invoking a linguistic hierarchy in which no language could serve as its own semantic metalanguage. These ideas were congenial to the spirit of the times.
    [Show full text]
  • Comments on Nathan Salmon “Are General Terms Rigid”*
    COMMENTS ON NATHAN SALMON “ARE GENERAL TERMS RIGID”* Robert May Princeton Semantics Workshop 17 May 2003 1. Nathan Salmon paper is entitled with a question: are general terms rigid? He asks this question in way of engaging the issue of the extension of the notion of rigidity beyond the domain of singular terms. While singular terms has been the province of most of the discussion of this rigidity since Naming and Necessity, it is well known that Kripke saw the notion extending to at least certain general terms such as terms for natural kinds. Scott Soames has recently weighed in on this issue in the latter chapters of his book Beyond Rigidity. His conclusion is that although there are significant overlaps in the properties of singular and general terms, there is no direct extension of rigidity to the general terms, and that rigid designation is properly applied only to singular terms. Salmon disagrees. His view, based in part of views dating back to his book Reference and Essence, is that there is an extension to be had, one which allows the application of the standard Kripkean characterization of rigidity to be applied to both sorts of terms. Central to his thesis is a claim about the status of certain definite descriptions. In these remarks, I will try to outline the issues to which NS is reacting, and the proposal he posits in response. I will then consider in a more critical light his claim about definite descriptions, bringing to bear considerations of their grammar. * Thanks to Richard Heck, Kent Johnson, Jeff King and Kai Wehmeier for helpful comments and discussion, and to Nathan Salmon and Scott Soames for discussion at the workshop.
    [Show full text]
  • Michael Anthony Eardley Dummett
    Michael Anthony Eardley Dummett 27 June 1925 – 27 December 2011 elected Fellow of the British Academy 1968 resigned 1984 re-elected Fellow of the British Academy 1995 by DANIEL ISAACSON IAN RUMFITT Fellow of the Academy Biographical Memoirs of Fellows of the British Academy, XVII, 191–228 Posted 21 November 2018. © British Academy 2018. MICHAEL DUMMETT Throughout the second half of the twentieth century, Michael Dummett was a powerful figure in British philosophy and in later years its most distinguished and authoritative practitioner, with tremendous international standing. His work spanned philosophy of mathematics, formal logic, philosophy of language, history of phil - os ophy, and metaphysics. He also played an important role in combatting racism in Britain, and when he was knighted, in the 1999 New Year’s Honours, it was ‘for services to Philosophy and to Racial Justice’. Biography Early life and education Michael Dummett was born at 56 York Terrace, London, his parents’ home, on 27 June 1925, and died on 27 December 2011 at 54 Park Town, Oxford, the home where he and his wife Ann had lived since 1957 and brought up their children. He was the only child of his parents George Herbert Dummett (1880–1970), a silk merchant, who also later dealt in rayon, and Mabel Iris née Eardley-Wilmot (1893–1980), whose father, Sir Sainthill Eardley-Wilmot, had been Inspector-General of Indian Forests, and after whom Michael Dummett was given Eardley as his middle name. Dummett’s father had two sons and a daughter by a previous marriage. At the age of ten Dummett was sent as a boarder to a preparatory school, Sandroyd, in Cobham, Surrey.
    [Show full text]
  • Kripke on Epistemic and Metaphysical Possibility: Two Routes to the Necessary Aposteriori
    May 2005 May 2005 Kripke on Epistemic and Metaphysical Possibility: Two Routes to the Necessary Aposteriori by Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC To Appear in Saul Kripke Edited by Alan Berger Cambridge University Press 1 Saul Kripke’s discussion of the necessary aposteriori in Naming and Necessity and “Identity and Necessity” -- in which he lays the foundation for distinguishing epistemic from metaphysical possibility, and explaining the relationship between the two – is, in my opinion, one of the outstanding achievements of twentieth century philosophy.1 My aim in this essay is to extract the enduring lessons of his discussion, and disentangle them from certain difficulties which, alas, can also be found there. I will argue that there are, in fact, two Kripkean routes to the necessary aposteriori – one correct and philosophically far-reaching, the other incorrect and philosophically misleading.2 Propositions Although Kripke avoids the word ‘proposition’ in Naming and Necessity, and tries to keep his theoretical commitments to a minimum, he speaks repeatedly of the necessary or contingent “statements,” and “truths” knowable apriori or aposteriori, that sentences express. Evidently, then, he thinks that there are things expressed by sentences that are that are both bearers of truth value and objects of attitudes like knowledge. Since this is what propositions are supposed to be, his discussion can be understood as implicitly involving propositions, while avoiding, as far as possible, substantive theoretical commitments about what they are. Thus, it should be safe to introduce the word into our discussion, so long as we limit our assumptions about propositions to those that are least objectionable, and most in tune with Kripke’s implicit presuppositions.
    [Show full text]