Volume XLIV September Number 4 Luther and the Late Medieval Augustinians: Another, Look David C

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Volume XLIV September Number 4 Luther and the Late Medieval Augustinians: Another, Look David C OCT 1 1973 ARCHIVES Volume XLIV September Number 4 Luther and the Late Medieval Augustinians: Another, Look David C. Steinmetz The author is professor of history at Duke University, Durham, N. C. On July 17, 1505, Martin Luther, the writings of St. Augustine.3 And M. A., of the University of Erfurt, there is probably, among the late applied for admission to the Reformed medieval scholastics, no doctor whose Congregation of the Order of the mastery of the theology of St. Augus­ Hermits of St. Augustine. When, later tine is more impressive 4 or whose that year in September, he received ability to interpret the ideas of St. the tonsure and black habit of the Augustine in the categories of his own Austin Friars in the monastery church time is more successful 5 than the of the Augustinian cloister near Leh­ famous general of the Augustinian mann's bridge in the northeastern Order, Gregory of Rimini. part of Erfurt, he entered an order The question of the relationship dedicated to theological study, espe­ of Martin Luther to the theological cially to the study of the writings of traditions of his own order, to ,hie St. Augustine. At Oxford, Cambridge, he was exposed in a lesser or greater Paris, and other centers of medieval degree, has remained one of the inter­ learning - but especially at Paris 1 esting, if unsolved problems of Luther -doctors of the Augustinian Order research. Was there a revival of Augus- had distinguished themselves for the breadth and profundity of their learn­ 3 "Without wishing to make of this connec­ ing. Thomas Aquinas had no more tion more than the evidence can sustain, it does famous pupil than Giles of Rome, not seem likely that Petrarch could have been whose independence of his teacher unaware of the Augustinians' theological views, especially since he was introduced to the study was so marked that he was even re­ of St. Augustine by the Augustinian Hermit, garded by some Thomists as a rival of Dionigi of Borgo San Sepolcro," Charles Aquinas.2 Petrareh found in the Augus­ Trinkhaus, In Our Image and Likeness: Humanity tine scholarship of the Italian Augus­ and Divinity in Italian Humanist Thought, Volume 1 (London: Constable, 1970), p.61. tinians an aid for his own studies in See A. Zumkeller, "Augustinerschule," pp. 1 Of the Augustinians whose commentaries 206-207. on the Sentences have survived, 42 Out of 75 4 "What is so new in Gregory is the fact that lectured on the Sentences at Paris, including such he is the best Augustine scholar of the Middle famous doctors as Giles of Rome, James of Ages from the milieu which created the Mil­ Viterbo, Alexander of San Eipidio, Henry of leloquium," Damasus Trapp, "Augustinian Friemar, Augustinus of Ancona, William of Theology of the 14th Century: Notes on Edi­ Cremona, Henry of Friemar the Younger, tions, Marginalia, Opinions, and Book-Lore," Hermann of Schild esche, Thomas of Strassburg, Augustiniana 6 (1956), p. 181. Gregory of Rimini, Alfons Vargas of Toledo, 5 Gordon Leff, Gregory of Rimini, Tradition Hugolino of Orvieto, Dionysius of Montina, and Innovation in Fourteenth Century Thought to name only a few. See the table found on (Manchester: The University Press, 1961), pages 174-176 of Adolar Zumkeller, "Die pp.241-242: " ... what the Augustinians did for Augustinerschule des Mittelalters: Vertreter tradition in the thirteenth century he achieved und philosophisch-theologische Lehre," Analecta in the fourteenth. He recast it and adapted it; August-iniana 27 (1964), 167-262. and thereby preserved it. When the full history 2 "Dafuer spricht auch der Umstand, dass of fourteenth-century thought comes finally to manche Thomasschueler seiner Zeit in ihm be written, Gregory may well prove to have [Giles of Rome] einen ausgesprochenen Gegner been its St. Bonaventure: the very divergence des Aquinaten sehen wollen," A. Zumkeller, between them is the measure of his achieve­ "Augustinerschule," p. 180. ment." 246 LUTHER AND THE AUGUSTINIANS tlO1anism in the Augustinian Order, If he rejects the Augustinian teaching which played an important role in the concerning predestination, he may theological development of Martin affirm with real gusto Augustinian Luther? As straightforward and simple ecclesiology. No Donatist rides againSt as this question appears, it has proven the enemy with the banner of a dis­ unbelievably complex and difficult to credited heretic flying overhead. The answer. This paper will try, in as brief teaching of St. Augustine's opponents a manner as possible, to point out the is far more likely to be introduced difficulties which confront the his­ under the aegis of an Augustine, now torian when he attempts to address at last authentically understood. And this question, to survey the history of one can always appeal to the moderate the answers which have thus far been Augustine against the Augustine who suggested, to indicate some of the spoke excessively. more obvious deficiencies in those It seems to me a serious mistake to answers, and to recommend some regard as nothing more than theolog­ directions which further historical ical posturing this universal respect research might profitably pursue. for the teaching of St. Augustine, even when that teaching is misunderstood or abandoned. Men can venerate St. 1. INITIAL DIFFICULTIES Paul and come to very different con­ Some difficulties only become ap­ clusions about the import of his teach­ parent when one has immersed oneself ing. A medieval theologian may be in the primary sources; but other genuine in his commitment to Augus­ difficulties dog the historian's footsteps tinianism and yet, for a variety of from the very outset. What, for ex­ historical reasons beyond his own taste ample, is meant by the term "Augus­ and preference, only be receptive to tinian"? There are, so far as I am able certain Augustinian motifs, while re­ to determine, five different senses in maining totally deaf to others. What which this term is used by historians is at stake is not his sincerity, but the who discuss the phenomenon of late theological climate of an epoch. When medieval Augustinianism. Apart from Thomas Aquinas meets St. Augustine, the sheer confusion which this plurality he changes him into an Aristotelian; of meanings introduces, there is the when Martin Luther meets him, he additional danger that an historian, transforms him into a modernus. It is who has demonstrated the Augus­ the strength of the Augustinian tra­ tinianism of a late medieval theologian dition that it can speak with many in sense three, will assume that he has tongues and is attractive even in a proven it in senses two, four, and five stunted and truncated form. as well; and, what is worse, will begin The term "Augustinian" may also to draw conclusions on the basis of be used to describe the theology of those unproven assumptions. the Augustinian Order. When it is The term "Augustinian" may be used in this sense, it is not used used simply to designate the theology evaluatively to mean agreement with of the Latin West in general. No Latin the teaching of St. Augustine, but theologian, however Pelagian his own descriptively to mean the actual teach­ theological instincts, is absolutely ings of members of the Augustinian unaffected by the teaching of St. Order, whether those teachings are Augustine. If he finds little that is faithful to St. Augustine or not. Adolar relevant for his own theological situ­ Zumkeller,6 and to some extent ation in the anti-Pelagian writings of St. Augustine, he nevertheless will 6 For Zumkeller, "Augustinerschule" and cite the early anti-Manichaean writings "Ordensschule" are interchangeable terms. See in support of his theological position. Zumkeller, "Augustinerschule," p. 169. LUTHER AND THE AUGUSTINIANS 247 Damasus Trapp as well, have used Ages without paying any attention "Augustinian" in this somewhat more whatever to the affiliation of that theologically neutral and descriptive right wing with any of the orders. If a sense. Are there any tendencies in the theologian is Augustinian in a more teaching of the Augustinian Order radical sense than, say, Thomas which characterize the order as a Aquinas, he qualifies to be regarded as whole and not simply a party within a late medieval Augustinian.9 Perhaps, the order? If so, those tendencies right wing is the wrong term to use, deserve to be called Augustinian, as since it carries the connotation of op­ similar tendencies within the other position to all theological currents of mendicant orders might be called one's own time. Thomas Bradwardine Franciscan or Dominican. could be said to be a right-wing "Augustinian" may also be used Augustinian who resisted the theolog­ evaluatively to describe a party within ical currents of the 14th century, but the Augustinian Order which agrees hardly Gregory of Rimini, who gave with St. Augustine on a wide range of Augustine a 14th-century voice. issues and at a depth which is more Augustinian in this fourth sense is the profound than the merely nominal designation for a sentiment in theology Augustinianism of all medieval which takes Augustine without ice or theologians. A. V. Mueiler is certainly water and translates him into the using Augustinian in this evaluative theological categories of a later age. and descriptive sense when he at­ In the later Middle Ages to be tempts to show the continuity between Augustinian in this sense generally the teaching of Hugolino of Orvieto, meant such things as a stress on Simon Fidati of Cassia, Augustinus predestination, on concupiscence as an Favaroni of Rome, Jacobus Perez of essential ingredient of original sin, on Valencia, and Martin Luther.7 To grace as the precondition of moral some extent, H . A. Oberman wishes virtue as well as of merit, and on the to use Augustinian in this sense,8 merits of the Christian as nothing though, since Oberman is a more more than merita de congruo or half­ subtle historian than Mueller, he uses merits.
Recommended publications
  • FAITH and REASON in the THOUGHT of GREGORY of RIMINI (C
    FAITH AND REASON IN THE THOUGHT OF GREGORY OF RIMINI (c. 1300-1358) BY GORDON LEFF, B.A., PH.D. LECTURER IN HISTORY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF MANCHESTER F any one trait may be said to characterize fourteenth- I century thought it is the progressive withdrawal of faith from the arena of philosophy and rational knowledge. Perhaps the greatest driving force in the development of medieval thought during the twelfth and thirteenth centuries had been the confidence that the truths of faith were accessible to human understanding and rational demonstration. It had nurtured a diversity of summae and systems, designed to incorporate the conclusions derived from the accumulating wealth of natural, mainly Aristotelian, knowledge into a Christian framework; it also led to some of the greatest works of Christian apologetics, including St. Thomas Aquinas's Summa contra gentiles, with the purpose of convincing the unbeliever and the infidel. With Henry of Ghent, Duns Scotus, and, even more with William of Ockham, however, the growing doubts over such a union were given full and lasting expression. Although not the first to do so, they reverted to a conception of theology as an indepen­ dent pursuit which was marked off from natural knowledge in the strict sense. Theology, they held, was a self-contained corpus with its own tenets and principles. It could not be regarded as just one more science governed by laws which were applicable to all knowledge, for, as founded on revealed truth, it was dependent on faith, not natural experience. These thinkers, moreover, were so obsessed by the contingent nature of all creation that they refused to countenance the possibility of arriving at a knowledge of God through creation.
    [Show full text]
  • © in This Web Service Cambridge University
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-89754-9 - An Introduction to Medieval Theology Rik Van Nieuwenhove Index More information Index Abelard, Peter, 82, 84, 99–111, 116, 120 beatific vision, 41, 62, 191 Alain of Lille, 71 beatitude, 172, 195–96 Albert the Great, 171, 264 Beatrijs van Nazareth, 170 Alexander of Hales, 147, 211, 227 beguine movement, 170 allegory, 15, 43, 45, 47, 177 Benedict XII, Pope, 265 Amaury of Bène, 71 Benedict, St., 28–29, 42 Ambrose, 7, 10, 149 Berengar of Tours, 60, 83, 129, 160, see also amor ipse notitia est 51, 117, see love and knowledge Eucharist anagogy, 47 Bernard of Clairvaux, 79, 82, 100, 104, 110, 112–15, analogy, see univocity 147, 251 analogy in Aquinas, 182–85, 234, 235 critique of Abelard, 110–11 Anselm of Canterbury, 16, 30, 71, 78, 81, 83–98, on loving God, 112–14 204, 236 Boccaccio, Giovanni, 251 Anselm of Laon, 72, 99 Boethius, 29–33, 125, 137 Anthony, St., 27 Bonaventure, 34, 47, 123, 141, 146, 148, 170, 173, apophaticism, 8, 34, 271 176, 179, 211–24, 227, 228, 230, 232, 242, 243, Aquinas, 182–83 245, 254 Aquinas, 22, 24, 34, 47, 51, 72, 87, 89, 90, 133, 146, Boniface, Pope, 249 148, 151, 154, 164, 169, 171–210, 214, 225, 227, 230, 235, 236, 237, 238, 240, 241, 244, 246, Calvin, 14 254, 255, 257, 266 Carabine, Deirdre, 65 Arianism, 20, 21 Carthusians, 79 Aristotle, 9, 20, 29, 78, 84, 179, 181, 192, 195, 212, Cassian, John, 27–29, 47 213, 216, 223, 225, 226, 227, 229, 237, 254, Cassidorius, 124 267, 268 cathedral schools, 82, 169 Arts, 124, 222 Catherine of Siena, 251 and pedagogy (Hugh), 124–28
    [Show full text]
  • The Patristic Legacy in the Middle Ages (II) 16:00 - 18:30 Wednesday, 21St August, 2019 Room 8 Presentation Type Workshop
    Politics and Society: The Patristic Legacy in the Middle Ages (II) 16:00 - 18:30 Wednesday, 21st August, 2019 Room 8 Presentation type Workshop 499 Side by Side: Augustine's supporting role in William of St. Thierry's attacks on Peter Abaelard Delphine Conzelmann University of Basel, Basel, Switzerland Abstract How far can a theologian go? What can, and more importantly, what can't he say? It was not merely a personal rivalry, but this very question, that drove William of St. Thierry (1080-1148) to consider the theology of Peter Abaelard (1079-1142) as a problem that needed to be dealt with. For him, the limits of the theological task as such were at stake. In William's eyes, Abaelard approached the Bible in a way too speculative and philosophical manner. In contrast, he understood his own theology as Biblical and true to the opinions of the Fathers, a sentiment he strongly expressed in his Expositio super Epistolam ad Romanos. In this paper I am going to discuss William's reception of Augustine, in order to present his own reading of Romans as firmly grounded in ecclesial tradition. Not only does he take up Augustine's thought, but he uses Augustine's biographical background – mainly his anti-Pelagian fervor – to support his own fight against heretical ideas, such as Peter Abaelard's or William of Conches'. This paper will explore how William introduced Augustine as a third player into his rising conflict with the school of Abaelard, both as authority in matters of theological content and methodology, and as a role model for his concrete political actions in the matter.
    [Show full text]
  • Good Positive Reasons" for an Ethics of Divine Commands: a Catalogue of Arguments
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 6 Issue 1 Article 4 1-1-1989 In Search of "Good Positive Reasons" for an Ethics of Divine Commands: A Catalogue of Arguments Janine Marie Idziak Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Idziak, Janine Marie (1989) "In Search of "Good Positive Reasons" for an Ethics of Divine Commands: A Catalogue of Arguments," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 6 : Iss. 1 , Article 4. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol6/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. IN SEARCH OF "GOOD POSITIVE REASONS" FOR AN ETHICS OF DIVINE COMMANDS: A CATALOGUE OF ARGUMENTS J anine Marie Idziak Recent proponents of a divine command ethics have chiefly defended the theory by refuting objections rather than by offering "positive reasons" to support it. We here offer a cata­ logue of such positive arguments drawn from historical discussions of the theory. We pre­ sent arguments which focus on various properties of the divine nature and on the unique status of God, as well as arguments which are analogical in character. Finally, we describe a particularform of the theory to which these arguments point, and indicate how they counter­ act a standard criticism of it.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustinianism.Pdf
    Augustinianism. This term is used to characterize philosophical, theological and political political ideas which were more or less close to those of S. Augustine of Hippo. The term came into use relatively recently, and can cover a spectrum of views: Augustinianism has never been a homogeneous movement. In particular, it is necessary to distinguish between a broad and a strict sense of the word, In the broad sense, the whole of Latin theology of the medieval and early modern period was strongly influenced by Augustine, as emerges very clearly from the Summae of the twelfth century and above all from Hugh of St Victor and from the authoritative Book of Sentences of Peter Lombard. The early generations of theologians of the mendicant orders – Hugh of St Cher, Alexander of Hales, Bonaventura of Bagnoregio – developed a close bond with Augustine, but they interpreted him in the light of neoplatonic or Aristotelian theories (for example, divine illumination of the intellect, the ‘agent intellect’, matter, rationes seminales [seminal principles]. In the strict sense one must distinguish between the following. #1. Augustinianism from the end of the thirteenth and the beginning of the fourteenth century emerged - especially in the Franciscan School (William de la Mare) and among Augustinian Hermits (“the old Augustinian School according to Giles of Rome) - as a reaction to the widespread reception of Aristotle in the work of Thomas Aquinas, after the condemnations of 1277 at Paris and 1284 at Oxford. Consciously drawing on Augustinian on Augustinian ideas (illumination, the form of created things in the mind of God), Henry of Ghent [a member of the secular clergy] created a coherent new system of speculative theology which would provide a a basis for acute critical analysis and the new order introduced by John Duns Scotus, who substituted for illumination the idea of an intuitive grasp of the essence of things.
    [Show full text]
  • 178 Petrus Martyr Vermigli This Volume Is a Fine Critical Edition of Pietro Martire Vermigli's
    178 Book Reviews Petrus Martyr Vermigli Kommentar zur Nikomachischen Ethik des Aristoteles, ed. Luca Baschera and Christian Moser (Studies in Medieval and Reformation Traditions, vol. 158). Leiden/Boston: Brill, 2011. viii, 689 pp. ISBN 9789004218734. This volume is a fine critical edition of Pietro Martire Vermigli’s (1499-1562) relatively unexplored but rich commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. When Vermigli lectured on the Nicomachean Ethics during his second profes- sorship at Strasbourg 1553-1556, he most likely continued the practice he had learnt at the University of Padua, which in the first half of the sixteenth cen- tury had distinguished itself by installing an ordinary professorship in moral philosophy devoted to the exposition of the Nicomachean Ethics. Vermigli comments on his own Latin translation of (most likely) Erasmus’s Greek edi- tion. He follows the mediaeval tradition of both literal comments and topical digressions, but his analysis of Greek terminology and grammar as well as the generous use of classical and patristic sources shows his debt to his Renaissance context. The style of his Latin is classical, fused with mediaeval philosophical terminology. On the surface the commentary of Eustratios appears to be more important than those of Albert the Great, Thomas Aquinas and Jacques-Louis d’Estrebay. Each section usually begins with a statement of the subject or even a summarizing syllogism and Vermigli then argues for the major and minor premises in the commentary. Many of the subsections end with digressions on difficulties and problems. Although Vermigli does not con- form to the fixed scholastic genres of quaestio, dubia and solutio, he uses them informally.
    [Show full text]
  • MOLINA and JOHN DUNS SCOTUS Jean-Pascal Anfray the Influence of John Duns Scotus
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers MOLINA AND JOHN DUNS SCOTUS Jean-Pascal Anfray The influence of John Duns Scotus (1265/6–1308) on late medieval and early modern philosophy and theology can hardly be overlooked. The Subtle Doctor’s concepts and doctrines set the shape of much of the discussions of the time, on the nature and subject of metaphysics, on the freedom of the will, and on the principles of morality. More pre- cisely, Scotus’s definition of being qua being as that to which being is not repugnant (cui non repugnat esse),1 and as a possible being, left a twofold legacy to later philosophy: on the one hand, his conception of metaphys- ics as a transcendental science of the univocal concept of being, and on the other hand the centrality of the notion of freedom, whose first mani- festation is the contingency of the world order. During the Renaissance and early modern period, those who would qualify as Scotists were so many that the Cistercian Juán Caramuel Lobkowitz could claim that Scoti schola numerosior est aliis simul sumptis (the school of Scotus counts more than all the other schools taken together).2 Not only was the institutional authority of Scotus uncontroversial but his thought also exercised a more diffused influence. Jesuit philosophy and theology was undoubtedly the main channel of diffusion for Scotus’s thought in the early modern era, and this, despite the fact that the ratio studiorum of the order (1586–99) made the study of Thomas Aquinas’s doctrine the basis of their theo- logical teaching.3 Especially well known is the importance of the Scotist 1 See John Duns Scotus, Quodl.
    [Show full text]
  • Theological Knowledge" in Gregory of Rimini and His Fourteenth-Century Context
    Between Faith and Knowledge: "Theological Knowledge" in Gregory of Rimini and his Fourteenth-Century Context Author: Jeffrey Charles Witt Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/2622 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2012 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy BETWEEN FAITH AND KNOWLEDGE: “THEOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE” IN GREGORY OF RIMINI AND HIS FOURTEENTH-CENTURY CONTEXT a dissertation by JEFFREY C. WITT submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May, 2012 © copyright by JEFFREY CHARLES WITT 2012 Abstract BETWEEN FAITH AND SCIENCE: GREGORY OF RIMINI ON THEOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE IN HIS FOURTEENTH-CENTURY CONTEXT By Jeffrey C. Witt Directed by Jean-Luc Solère The professional theologian attempts to distinguish herself by claiming some kind of “epistemic advance” over the person of mere belief. This claim to knowledge—and the relation of this knowledge to the other sciences—can therefore be subject to philosophical analysis. What is the subject matter of this discipline? What is the method by which it secures its results? And how does its practitioner “know” when she has passed beyond mere belief? The theologians of the high and late Middle Ages faced a unique historical challenge. At this time, “theology” first emerged as a distinct academic discipline, and the theological doctors were perpetually engaged in a debate about the exact nature of theology. On the one hand, they were eager to assert that theology made a real epistemic contribution that should be respected by the other sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • A Jesuit Debate About the Modes of Union Francisco Suárez Vs. Pedro Hurtado De Mendoza Jean-Pascal Anfray
    A Jesuit Debate about the Modes of Union Francisco Suárez vs. Pedro Hurtado de Mendoza Jean-Pascal Anfray To cite this version: Jean-Pascal Anfray. A Jesuit Debate about the Modes of Union Francisco Suárez vs. Pedro Hurtado de Mendoza. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Philosophy Documentation Center, 2019, 93 (2), pp.309-334. 10.5840/acpq201931173. halshs-03183721 HAL Id: halshs-03183721 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-03183721 Submitted on 28 Mar 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. A Jesuit Debate about the Modes of Union: Francisco Suárez vs. Pedro Hurtado de Mendoza Jean-Pascal Anfray Abstract. In this paper, I examine a neglected debate between Francisco Suárez and Pedro Hurtado de Mendoza about the unity of composite substances (i.e., hylomorphic compounds of matter and form). There was a consensus among the Jesuits on the fact that the per se unity of composite substances requires something in addition to matter and form. Like most Jesuits, Suárez and Hurtado further agree on the fact that this additional ingredient is not a full-blown thing, but a “mode of union.” However, while Suárez claims that the union is achieved through a single mode, Hurtado maintains that it is necessary to postulate two distinct modes of union, one modifying form and another modifying matter.
    [Show full text]
  • Medieval Theologians: an Introduction to Theology in the Medieval Period
    Mystics, Masters, and Martyrs: Theology and Theologians in Medieval Europe January 2017 9-11:30am, Gardencourt 206 Instructor: Christopher Elwood Course Description: This course will explore the lives, thought, and context of significant Christian figures of the Middle Ages in Europe: Anselm of Canterbury (1033-1109), Marguerite Porete (d. 1310), and Gregory Palamas (1296- 1359). We will focus on themes of revelation and knowledge of God, attending to how these theologians and spiritual authors integrated practice and belief, spirituality, and theology. In addition, students will have the opportunity to research another medieval theologian of their choice. Goals and Objectives: The goal of the course is to help students develop their capacity for faithful and coherent theological expression in pastoral practice. Students will • gain a basic understanding of the different forms of theology and spirituality developed and practiced in Europe in the Middle Ages, • sharpen their skills of theological interpretation through the close reading and discussion of primary sources, orally and in writing, • develop their ability to make responsible and relevant use of historic theological writing, • reflect on various models for integrating the analytical, devotional and practical components of theology and spiritual writing, • and clarify their own theological and ethical positions. Required Books: Anselm of Canterbury: The Major Works. Eds. Brian Davis and G.R. Evans. Oxford World’s Classics. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1998. (Referred to in the syllabus as AoC) Marguerite Porete: The Mirror of Simple Souls. Ed. Ellen L. Babinsky. The Classics of Western Spirituality. New York: Paulist Press, 1993. Gregory Palamas: The Triads. Eds.
    [Show full text]
  • Late Medieval Scholasticism John Dun Scotus, William of Ockham and Gabriel Biel
    HA/HL 112 Church History Reformation History Outline Late Medieval Scholasticism John Dun Scotus, William of Ockham and Gabriel Biel I. Introduction to Scholasticism A. Named after the “schools” that were set up around the cathedrals for Christian Education purposes • Progressed from a “theologian in residence” to groups of monks meeting in a motherhouse to colleges or universities • These gathered groups became known as the “schoolmen” – thus, “scholastics” II. Scholasticism as a Method for doing theology. A. Scholasticism is a particular way, or method, that theology was done in the medieval period. 1. Anselm of Canterbury. Came up with phrase, “faith seeking understanding” (fides querens intellectum). He insisted that faith and reason do not contradict each other. a) He emphasized the “ransom theory” of atonement 2. Abelard of Paris. Introduced the “Christ as example” theory of atonement a) In Abelard’s “Sic et Non” (1122 CE), was a book the dealt with a “scholastic method” to resolve apparent theological contradictions. This method was further developed in Peter Lombard’s Four Books on the Sentences. The method followed the following pattern: i) A question for discussion would be posed (questo) ii) An answer in the affirmative (videtur quod) iii) An answer in the negative (sed contra) iv) A resolution to the apparent contradictions between points 2 and 3 would be given (responsio). B. Salvation in Scholasticism • Thomas Aquinas saw salvation as a process • III. The development of schools of thought in Medieval Theology A. Early Medieval Scholasticism 1. The two scholastic schools of thought: a) The Dominicans, of whom Thomas Aquinas was the leading proponent b) The Franciscans, led by people such as Duns Scotus and William of Ockham 2.
    [Show full text]
  • This Is an Accepted Manuscript of a Book Chapter Published by Routledge in the Routledge Companion to Sixteenth Century Philosop
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto This is an Accepted Manuscript of a book chapter published by Routledge in The Routledge Companion to Sixteenth Century Philosophy on January 2017, available online: https://www.routledge.com/Routledge-Companion-to-Sixteenth-Century- Philosophy/Lagerlund-Hill/p/book/9780415658607 Philosophy Among and in the Wake of the Reformers: Luther, Melanchthon, Zwingli, and Calvin Pekka Kärkkäinen (Helsinki) Introduction The most influential figures of the Protestant Reformation were not only spiritual leaders but also academically educated theologians. Martin Luther (1483-1546), Ulrich Zwingli (1484-1531), Philip Melanchthon (1497-1560), and John Calvin (1509-64) were raised in the late medieval world and studied according to the medieval curriculum, which was based on Aristotelian philosophy. Although during the Reformation their main interests were in theological issues, all of them commented in various ways on philosophy in general and philosophical doctrines in particular. They also adopted philosophical theories that served their theological thinking. Also, Melanchthon was an active writer of philosophical treatises. Finally, their impact on the way philosophy was practiced in the Protestant countries was significant. One can approach a late medieval theologian's relationship to philosophy in terms of three important themes. These themes, rather than a separate discussion of individual Reformers, will serve in what follows as a guide through the complex nest of questions relating to the Reformers' relationship to philosophy. Firstly, there is the question of the theologian's relationship to his philosophical context. This includes questions about the continuity and discontinuity of the Reformers' thinking with their late medieval Aristotelian education.
    [Show full text]