Kant's Philosophy of Mathematics Synthese Library

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kant's Philosophy of Mathematics Synthese Library KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHll.OSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: JAAKKO lßNTIKKA, Boston University Editors: DONALD DAVIDSON, University 0/ California. Berkeley GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University 0/ Leyden WESLEY C. SALMON, University 0/ Pittsburgh VOLUME219 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS MODERN ESSAYS Edited by CARLJ. POSY Duke University, North Carolina, U.s.A. SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Kant's phllosophy of mathematlcs : modern essays I edlted by Carl ~. Posy. p. cm. -- <Synthese 11brary : v. 219) ISBN 978-90-481-4105-0 ISBN 978-94-015-8046-5 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-8046-5 1. Mathematlcs--Phllosophy. 2. Kant, Immanuel, 1724-1804. I. Posy, Carl~. 11. Serles. QA8.4.K36 1992 501--dc20 91-36207 ISBN 978-90-481-4105-0 Printed on acidlree paper All Rights Reserved © 1992 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1992 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1992 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE vii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ix CARL J. POSY - Introduction: Mathematics in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason I. CLASSIC PAPERS OF THE 1960'S AND 1970'S JAAKKO HINTIKKA - Kant on the Mathematical Method 21 CHARLES PARSONS - Kant's Philosophy of Arithmetic 43 - Postscript 69 MANLEY THOMPSON - Singular Tenns and Intuitions in Kant's Epistemology 81 - Postscript 102 PHILIP KITCHER - Kant and the Foundations of Mathematics 109 11. RECENT WORK CHARLES PARSONS - Arithmetic and the Categories 135 J. MICHAEL YOUNG - Construction, Schematism and Imagination 159 MICHAEL FRIEDMAN - Kant 's Theory of Geometry 177 STEPHEN BARKER - Kant's View of Geometry: a Partial Defense 221 ARTHUR MELNICK - The Geometry of a Fonn of Intuition 245 WILLIAM HARPER - Kant on Space, Empirical Realism, and the Foundations of Geometry 257 CARL J. POSY - Kant's Mathematical Realism 293 GORDON G. BRITTAN, JR. - Algebra and Intuition 315 JAAKKO HINTIKKA - Kant's Transcendental Method and His Theory of Mathematics 341 v vi TABLE OF CONTENTS CONTRIBUTORS 361 INDEX 363 PREFACE For the bulk of the twentieth century, Kant's philosophy of mathematics fell into low disrepute. His views suffered partly from the nineteenth and twenti­ eth century challenges to the hegemony of Euclidean geometry. And their reputation declined partly because the great thinkers - RusselI, Hilbert, Brouwer and others - who shaped the twentieth century's philosophical approach to mathematics each took aim in his own way at central Kantian doctrines. To be sure, the early years of the twentieth century saw lively debates about Kant's mathematical views. (The famous interchanges between Russell and Couterat are but one instance of this.) But the generally negative assessment of Kant's philosophy of mathematics led naturally to general neglect. So, with scant exception, the middle of the century saw little creative work on this topic. The one main exception is the late Gottfried Martin's work. Martin's Arithmetik und Kombinatoric bei Kant appeared in 1938. Though the book's positive thesis - that Kant viewed arithmetic as a formal axiomatic science - is still highly controversial, its scholarship and its treasure trove of insights about Kant's way of thinking remain unsurpassed. It is indeed still the best starting place for anyone who wishes to do scholarly work on reactions to Kant's philosophy of mathematics. But for a long time Martin's work had sadly small impact on the wider philosophical community, and exploration of Kant's views about mathematics remained a philosophical backwater. All of that changed in the mid-1960's with the publication of a Iively debate about issues in Kantian mathematics between Charles Parsons and Jaakko Hintikka. The debate, which was fascinating in its own right, - each of these authors is an accomplished logician and asolid Kantian scholar - had the added effect of reigniting philosophical interest in Kant's thoughts about mathematics. A trickle of fascinating studies - inspired by the issues that Parsons and Hintikka raised - followed in the 1970's. Then in the next decade the movement grew into a full-fledged renaissance of interest in Kant's philosophy of mathematics. This was further sparked by a 1983 con­ ference on the topic at Duke University. vii Carl J. Posy (ed.), Kant's Philosophy 0/ Mathematics. vii- viii. © 1992 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Vlll PREFACE The present anthology is designed first of all to chronicle and publicize this renaissance. But hopefully it will also show the importance of Kantian think­ ing for general issues in the philosophy of mathematics. Part I includes a pair of the seminal papers by Hintikka and Parsons. It also includes inftuential papers by Manley Thompson and Philip Kitcher which followed up on this initial work and which appeared in the ensuing decade. Parsons and Thompson have added more recent postscripts to their papers. Part 11 contains a selection of papers that represent the ftowering of interest in Kant's philosophy of mathematics during the 1980's and the beginning of the 1990's. It includes new work by both Hintikka and Parsons. I hope that the essays in this volume will demonstrate that Kant's views about mathematics are interesting, that they are defensible (or at least respectable in the light of our current knowledge) and that they are insepara­ ble from his overall philosophical system. Indeed, a leisurely thumb through the volume will readily testify to the fascination that many modern Kant scholars and philosophers of mathematics have for Kant's mathematical views. As for defensibility, you will find in the pages that follow quite a few attempts to vindicate or reconstruct Kantian doctrines and arguments from a modern perspective. In fact, far from viewing Kant's work on mathematics as dead, the volume contains several attempts to connect his views with quite recent findings in physical science, cognitive science and mathematical logic. Finally, you will find the volume rich and diverse with suggestions connect­ ing Kant's mathematical views with his overall philosophy. This collection contains a mixture of scholarship and speculation, recon­ struction and close textual analysis. It represents a fair sampie of the current state of thinking on Kant's philosophy of mathematics. To be sure, you will find no unanimity on any single point; and it is hard to tell which, if any, of the perspectives and interpretations presented here will prevail. This very diversity and vigorous debate, however, are themselves the signs of a vibrant field of study. Durham, 1991 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Part of the editorial and clerical costs for this anthology were underwritten by a generous grant from the Duke University Research Council. The editor is also indebted to Tod Davis and Marianne Grochowski for editorial assistance. The editor gratefully acknowledges the permission given by the authors, editors and copyright holders of the following publications to reproduce them in original or revised form in this anthology: "Kant on the Mathematical Method" was first published in The Monist, volume 51, 1967, pages 352-375. It is copyright © 1967 The Monist, and is reproduced here by kind permission of Jaakko Hintikka and the publishers of The Monist, La Salle, Illinois, 61301. "Kant's Philosophy of Arithmetic" was first published in Sidney Morgenbesser, Patrick Suppes, and Morton White, eds., Philosophy, Science and Method: Essays in Honor 0/ Ernest Nagel, 1969, St. Martin's Press. It is reproduced here by kind permission of Charles Parsons and the editors. The Postscript to "Kant's Philosophy of Arithmetic" was first published in Charles Parsons, Mathematics in Philosophy: Selected Essays, copyright 1983, Cornell University Press. It is reproduced here by kind permission of Charles Parsons and Cornell University Press. "Singular Terms and Intuitions in Kant's Epistemology" was originally pub­ lished in the Review 0/ Metaphysics, Volume 26, copyright 1972, it .is repnnted here by kind permission of Manley Thompson and the Review 0/ Metaphysics. "Kant and the Foundations of Mathematics" was first published in The Philosophical Review, Volume 84, copyright 1975. It is reprinted here by kind permission of Philip Kitcher and The Philosophical Review. ix earl J. Posy (ed.), Kant's Philosophy 01 Mathematics. ix-x. © 1992 Kluwer Academic Publishers. x ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS "Arithmetic and the Categories" was first published in Topoi volume 3, copy­ right 1984. It is reprinted here by kind permission of Charles Parsons and of Topoi. "Construction, Schematism, and Imagination" was first published in Topoi volume 3, copyright 1984. It is reprinted here by kind permission of J. Michael Young and of Topoi. "Kant's Theory of Geometry," was first published in The Philosophical Review, Volume 94, copyright 1985. It is reproduced here by kind permission of Michael Friedman and of The Philosophical Review. "The Geometry of a Form of Intuition" was first published in Topoi volume 3, copyright 1984. It is reprinted here by kind permission of Arthur Melnick and ofTopoi. "Kant on Space, Empirical Realism and the Foundations of Geometry" was first published in Topoi volume 3, copyright 1984. It is reprinted here by kind permission of William Harper and of Topoi. "Kant's Mathematical Realism," was first published in The Monist, volume 67, pages 115-134. It is copyright © 1984 The Monist, and is reproduced here by kind permission of the publishers of The Monist, La SaUe, Illinois, 61301. "Kant's Transcendental Method and His Theory of Mathematics," was first published in Topoi volume 3, copyright 1984. It is reprinted here by kind per­ mission of Jaakko Hintikka and of Topoi.
Recommended publications
  • 472 Philip Kitcher Preludes to Pragmatism
    Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 6 Philip Kitcher Preludes to Pragmatism: Toward a Reconstruction of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012. 464 pages $45.00 (cloth ISBN 978–0–19–989955–5) This book collects seventeen of Philip Kitcher’s essays from the past two decades. All but two have been published elsewhere, and several are quite well-known. ‘The Naturalists Return’, for example, appeared in Philosophical Review’s 1992 centennial issue, and is a staple of reading lists in epistemology and the philosophy of science. But the book frames these essays in a valuable new way. In the period from which these essays are drawn, Kitcher moved steadily toward an embrace of pragmatism, and the book presents them as milestones in this development: tentative applications of pragmatist ideas to a range of topics. Hence the word ‘prelude’. Kitcher says that he is not yet ready to present a ‘fully developed pragmatic naturalist position’ and that he is merely giving ‘pointers’ toward such a position (xvi-xvii). But this modesty does not do justice to the sophistication of his pragmatism. Preludes to Pragmatism is a rich and rewarding book that will interest philosophers of many different stripes. It may also prove to be an important contribution to the history of pragmatism. The book’s lengthy introduction puts the essays in context. Kitcher seems surprised to have wound up a pragmatist. ‘Two decades ago’, he writes, ‘I would have seen the three canonical pragmatists—Peirce, James, and Dewey—as well-intentioned but benighted, laboring with crude tools to develop ideas that were far more rigorously and exactly shaped by… what is (unfortunately) known as “analytic” philosophy’ (xi).
    [Show full text]
  • Kitcher's Modest Realism: the Reconceptualization of Scientific
    1 KITCHER’S MODEST REALISM: THE RECONCEPTUALIZATION OF SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY Antonio Diéguez Forthcoming in W. J. González (ed.), Scientific Realism and Democratic Society: The Philosophy of Philip Kitcher , “Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities”, Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2010. Abstract In Science, Truth and Democracy , Kitcher moderates the strongest ontological realist thesis he defended in The Advancement of Science , with the aim of making compatible the correspondence theory of truth with conceptual relativity. However, it is not clear that both things could be harmonized. If our knowledge of the world is mediated by our categories and concepts; if the selection of these categories and concepts may vary according to our interests, and they are not the consequence of the existence of certain supposed natural kinds or some intrinsic structure of the world, it is very problematic to establish what our true statements correspond to. This paper analyzes the transformation in Kitcher’s realism and expounds the main difficulties in this project. Finally, a modality of moderate ontological realism will be proposed that, despite of keeping the sprit of the conceptual relativity, is strong enough to support the correspondence theory of truth. KEY WORDS MODEST REALISM, CONCEPTUAL RELATIVITY, CORRESPONDENCE THEORY OF TRUTH The last two decades have been a period of deep changes in the realm of the philosophy of science. Not only its hegemony among meta-scientific disciplines has been challenged by the sociology of science and, in general, by the social studies of science, but the objective that guided it from the beginning of its academic institutionalization with the Vienna Circle in the 1930’s —i.
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.Kitcher on Well-Ordered Science: Should Science Be
    THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia ISSN: 0495-4548 [email protected] Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea España KEREN, ARNON Kitcher on Well-Ordered Science: Should Science Be Measured against the Outcomes of Ideal Democratic Deliberation? THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, vol. 28, núm. 2, 2013, pp. 233- 244 Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea Donostia-San Sebastián, España Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=339730822003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative Kitcher on Well-Ordered Science: Should Science Be Measured against the Outcomes of Ideal Democratic Deliberation? * Arnon KEREN Received: 02.10.2012 Final version: 25.02.2013 BIBLID [0495-4548 (2013) 28: 77; pp. 233-244] ABSTRACT: What should the goals of scientific inquiry be? What questions should scientists investigate, and how should our resources be distributed between different lines of investigation? Philip Kitcher has suggested that we should answer these questions by appealing to an ideal based on the consideration of hypothetical democratic deliberations under ideal circumstances. This paper examines possible arguments that might support acceptance of this ideal for science, and argues that neither the arguments
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy Upside Down?
    Philosophy Upside Down? Peter Baumann published in: Metaphilosophy 44, no. 5 (October 2013): 579-588. The definitive version is available at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/meta.12046/abstract Abstract Philip Kitcher recently argued for a reconstruction in philosophy. According to him, the contemporary mainstream of philosophy (in the English speaking world, at least) has deteriorated into something which is of relevance only to a few specialists who communicate with each other in a language nobody else understands. Kitcher proposes to reconstruct philosophy along two axes: a knowledge axis (with a focus on the sciences) and a value axis. I discuss Kitcher’s diagnosis as well as his proposal of a therapy. I argue that there are problems with both. I end with an alternative view of what some core problems of the profession currently are. KEYWORDS: applied philosophy; Philip Kitcher; pragmatism; reconstruction in philosophy; scholasticism. In a recent contribution to Metaphilosophy Philip Kitcher argues that there is something deeply wrong with contemporary mainstream anglophone philosophy and that we should “reconstruct” philosophy “inside out” (see Kitcher 2011).1 Kitcher expresses some caution with respect to both his diagnosis and the proposed therapy (see 249); he is happy to admit the vagueness of some of his remarks (see 254; see, e.g., some passages on 252 and 254) and even remarks that much “of what I have said is probably crude, simplistic, and wrong” (258). He continues: “Yet I don’t think that the errors and the need for refinement matter to my plea for philosophical redirection.” (258). I think we should follow Kitcher’s lead here and not worry too much about the details (it is not clear anyway which of the more detailed claims Kitcher is more committed to and which less).
    [Show full text]
  • Well-Ordered Science and Indian Epistemic Cultures
    Well-Ordered Science and Indian Epistemic Cultures Toward a Polycentered History of Science By Jonardon Ganeri* ABSTRACT This essay defends the view that “modern science,” as with modernity in general, is a polycentered phenomenon, something that appears in different forms at different times and places. It begins with two ideas about the nature of rational scientific inquiry: Karin Knorr Cetina’s idea of “epistemic cultures,” and Philip Kitcher’s idea of science as “a system of public knowledge,” such knowledge as would be deemed worthwhile by an ideal conversation among the whole public under conditions of mutual engagement. This account of the nature of scientific practice provides us with a new perspective from which to understand key elements in the philosophical project of Jaina logicians in the seventh, eighth, and ninth centuries C.E. Jaina theory seems exceptionally well targeted onto two of the key constituents in the ideal conversation—the classification of all human points of view and the representation of end states of the deliberative process. The Buddhist theory of the Katha៮vatthu contributes to Indian epistemic culture in a different way: by supplying a detailed theory of how human dialogical standpoints can be revised in the ideal conversation, an account of the phenomenon Kitcher labels “tutoring.” Thus science in India has its own history, one that should be studied in comparison and contrast with the history of science in Europe. In answer to Joseph Needham, it was not ‘modern science’ which failed to develop in India or China but rather non-well-ordered science, science as unconstrained by social value and democratic consent.
    [Show full text]
  • Philip Kitcher's Philosophical Pendu
    From Philosophy of Science to Philosophy of Literature (and Back) via Philosophy of Mind: Philip Kitcher’s Philosophical Pendulum * Bence NANAY Received: 24.09.2012 Final version: 25.02.2013 BIBLID [0495-4548 (2013) 28: 77; pp. 257-264] ABSTRACT: A recent focus of Philip Kitcher’s research has been, somewhat surprisingly in the light of his earlier work, the philosophical analyses of literary works and operas. Some may see a discontinuity in Kitcher’s oeuvre in this respect—it may be difficult to see how his earlier contributions to philosophy of science rela- te to this much less mainstream approach to philosophy. The aim of this paper is to show that there is no such discontinuity: Kitcher’s contributions to the philosophy of science and his more recent endeavors into the philosophy of literature and of music are grounded in the same big picture attitude towards the human mind—an attitude that he would undoubtedly call ‘pragmatic’: one that emphasizes the importance of tho- se mental processes that are not (or not entirely) rational. Keywords: Philip Kitcher; Philosophy of Literature; Philosophy of Science; Emotions. RESUMEN: El análisis filosófico de obras literarias y óperas se ha convertido en un objeto de estudio reciente para Philip Kitcher, algo quizá sorprendente a la vista de su trabajo anterior. Hay quien puede percibir una dis- continuidad en la obra de Kitcher a este respecto: puede ser difícil apreciar cómo sus anteriores contribu- ciones a la filosofía de la ciencia se relacionan con este otro tipo menos mayoritario de filosofía. El propósi- to de este artículo es mostrar que no hay tal discontinuidad: las contribuciones de Kitcher a la filosofía de la ciencia y sus empresas más recientes en filosofía de la literatura y de la música se basan en la misma visión general del espíritu humano, una actitud que indudablemente él denominaría pragmática: enfatiza la impor- tancia de los procesos mentales que no son (o no completamente) racionales.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    CURRICULUM VITAE Philip Stuart Kitcher February 2018 Date of Birth: February 20 1947 Place of Birth: London, England Citizenship: British by origin, naturalized American citizen (May 1995). Home address: 454 Riverside Drive, Apt. 6B, New York, NY 10027 Home phone: (212)-662-5812 Office phone: (212)-854-4884, (212)-854-3196 (department) E-mail: [email protected] Higher Education Christ's College, Cambridge; 1966-1969, B.A. 1969, (M.A. 1996). (First class honours in Mathematics/History and Philosophy of Science) Princeton University; 1969-1973; Ph.D. 1974 (Department of Philosophy/Program in History and Philosophy of Science) Honorary Degree Doctor, honoris causa Erasmus University Rotterdam November 2013 (on the occasion of the University centennial; awarded for “outstanding contributions to philosophy of science”) Honors and Awards Henry Schuman Prize (awarded by the History of Science Society, for the best essay by a graduate student), 1971 University of Vermont Summer Research Grant, 1975 University of Vermont Summer Research Grant, 1979 NEH Summer Research Grant, 1979 ACLS Study Fellowship, 1981-82 University of Vermont Distinguished Scholar in Humanities and Social Sciences, 1983 NEH Fellowship for College Teachers, 1983-84 NEH Grant for Institute to Investigate a Possible New Consensus in Philosophy of Science (Joint Principal Investigator with C. Wade Savage) 1 Imre Lakatos Award (co-winner with Michael Friedman) 1986. Awarded for Vaulting Ambition. NEH Fellowship for University Teachers 1988-89 (declined) John Simon Guggenheim Fellowship 1988-89 Principal Investigator, five-year NSF Research and Training Grant for the development of a Science Studies Center at UCSD. (Awarded Fall 1990). Revelle College (UCSD) Distinguished Teaching Award, 1990.
    [Show full text]
  • In the Long Cool Hour: Pragmatic Naturalism
    In the Long Cool Hour Amia Srinivasan The Ethical Project by Philip Kitcher. Harvard, 422 pp., £36.95, November 2011, 978 0 674 06144 6 hese English psychologists,’ ultimate explanation of morality – not to Nietzsche wrote in 1887, ‘just what mention love, sex, religion and art – in brain ‘Tdo they want?’ scans and evolutionary just-so stories. ‘It is increasingly evident that moral stand ards, You always find them at the same task, whether practices and policies reside in our neuro- they want to or not, pushing the partie honteuse biology,’ the ‘neurophilosopher’ Patricia of our inner world to the foreground, and looking for what is really effective, guiding Churchland claims. ‘Our moral nature is and decisive for our development where what it is because our brains are as they man’s intellectual pride would least wish to are.’ Steven Pinker writes that the ‘human find it (for example, in the vis inertiae of habit, moral sense turns out to be an organ . with or in forgetfulness, or in a blind and random quirks that reflect its evolutionary history coupling and mechanism of ideas, or in and its neurobiological foundations.’ Thus something purely passive, automatic, reflex- Daniel Dennett feels able to claim that Dar- ive, molecular and thoroughly stupid) – what is it that actually drives these psychologists in winism is a ‘universal acid’ that ‘eats through precisely this direction all the time? just about every concept, and leaves in its wake a revolutionised worldview’. Some Nietzsche’s complaint is not that morality neuro-evo evangelists, especially those writ- should be protected from explanation – this ing for a mass audience, take themselves passage opens On the Genealogy of Morality – not only to be explaining morality, but to be but rather that the ‘English psycholog ists’ explaining it away.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Philosophy of the Unconscious
    Kant’s Philosophy of the Unconscious Kant’s Philosophy of the Unconscious Edited by Piero Giordanetti · Riccardo Pozzo · Marco Sgarbi De Gruyter An electronic version of this book is freely available, thanks to the support of libra- ries working with Knowledge Unlatched. KU is a collaborative initiative designed to make high quality books Open Access. More information about the initiative can be found at www.knowledgeunlatched.org An electronic version of this book is freely available, thanks to the support of libra- ries working with Knowledge Unlatched. KU is a collaborative initiative designed to make high quality books Open Access. More information about the initiative can be found at www.knowledgeunlatched.org ISBN 978-3-11-021808-4 e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-021809-1 e-ISBN (EPUB) 978-3-11-021806-2 ISSN 0179-0986 e-ISSN 0179-3256 This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 3.0 License, as of February 23, 2017. For details go to http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliogra- fie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.dnb.de abrufbar. ©ISBN 2016 978-3-11-021808-4 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston Drucke-ISBN und (PDF) Bindung: 978-3-11-021809-1 Duck & Co., Ortsname ♾e-ISBN Gedruckt (EPUB) auf 978-3-11-021806-2 säurefreiem Papier PrintedISSN 0179-0986 in Germany e-ISSN 0179-3256 ISBN 978-3-11-020403-2 www.degruyter.com e-ISBN 978-3-11-026540-8 This work is licensedLibrary under the of CongressCreative Commons Cataloging-in-Publication Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs Data 3.0 License, asA of CIP February catalog 23, record2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Millian Arguments: Using Helen Longino's Approach to Solve The
    Two Millian Arguments: Using Helen Longino’s Approach to Solve the Problems Philip Kitcher Targeted with His Argument on Freedom of Inquiry Jaana Eigi Department of Philosophy, University of Tartu Philip Kitcher argued that the freedom to pursue one’s version of the good life is the main aim of Mill’s argument for freedom of expression. According to Kitcher, in certain scientic elds, political and epistemological asymmetries bias research toward conclusions that threaten this most important freedom of underprivileged groups. Accordingly, Kitcher claimed that there are Millian grounds for limiting freedom of inquiry in these elds to protect the freedom of the underprivileged. I explore Kitcher’s argument in light of the interpretation Helen Longino gave to Mill’s argument. She argued that free critical dialogue in the community allows bias to be overcome, through intersubjective criticism of hypotheses and the back- ground assumptions that frame them. I suggest that Longino’s approach allows for the identication of the fundamental problems of the research programs Kitcher targeted, and for the rejection of their claims to knowledge. us it is possible to address Kitcher’s problem without limiting freedom of speech. Keywords: freedom of speech, J.S. Mill, P. Kitcher, H. Longino, social consequences of research Õ. Introduction In this paper, I focus on Philip Kitcher’s argument concerning freedom of scientic inquiry that Kitcher based on his interpretation of John Stuart Mill’s argument for freedom of expression.Õ e argument, rst presented Corresponding author’s address: Jaana Eigi, Department of Philosophy, Institute of Phi- losophy and Semiotics, University of Tartu, Jakobi ó, Tartu, ¢Õþþì, Estonia.
    [Show full text]
  • Toward a Pragmatist Philosophy of Science *
    Toward a Pragmatist Philosophy of Science * Philip KITCHER Received: 05.12.2012 Final version: 12.12.2012 BIBLID [0495-4548 (2013) 28: 77; pp. 185-231] ABSTRACT: This three-part essay begins with a diagnosis of the career of general philosophy of science in the tradi- tion begun by Hempel’s reform of logical positivism. Since 1950, Anglophone philosophy of science has largely sought general accounts of confirmation, theory and explanation. It has not found them. Instead it has assembled some valuable tools for exploring problems in the natural and social sciences, and has put them to work in a range of useful studies. The second part of the essay pursues the question of whether there is a successor project to the general investigations that Hempel inspired. I argue that there are diffi- cult methodological questions about collective inquiry that have largely been neglected. Attempts to answer these questions should expand the resources for philosophical understanding of scientific knowledge. The third part focuses on the situation of the sciences within society. Can scientific research be divorced from the interests of a broader public? Can its conclusions be generated in neglect of the evidential standards ac- cepted by non-scientists? I argue for a development of the ideal of well-ordered science, and for the under- standing of science (singular!) as one institution among others. Conceiving matters in this way recovers im- portant themes from the neglected pragmatist tradition. Keywords: logical empiricism; pragmatism; social epistemology; science and society; well-ordered science; science and values. RESUMEN: Este ensayo en tres partes comienza con un diagnóstico de la trayectoria de la filosofía general de la cien- cia, tal como se cultiva en la tradición que se origina con la reforma hempeliana del positivismo lógico.
    [Show full text]
  • AN ALTERNATIVE to KITCHER's THEORY of CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS and HIS ACCOUNT of the CHANGE of the GENE CONCEPT Ingo Brigandt
    AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER’S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT Ingo Brigandt Department of History and Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh 1017 Cathedral of Learning Pittsburgh, PA 15260 USA E-mail: [email protected] Tel.: 412-624-5896 Fax: 412-624-6825 November 3, 2004 An Alternative to Kitcher’s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept Abstract The present paper discusses Kitcher’s framework for studying conceptual change and progress. Kitcher’s core notion of reference potential is hard to apply to concrete cases. In addition, an account of conceptual change as change in reference potential misses some important aspects of conceptual change and conceptual progress. I propose an alternative framework that focuses on the inferences and explanations supported by scientific concepts. The application of my approach to the history of the gene concept offers a better account of the conceptual progress that occurred in the transition from the Mendelian to the molecular gene than Kitcher’s theory. AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER’S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS 1 Philosophical accounts of the change of scientific terms often focus on the reference of terms. Philip Kitcher goes beyond the mere study of reference by using his notion of the ‘reference potential’ of a term, which allows for a more fine-grained study of conceptual change. In fact, Kitcher’s framework is probably the most sophisticated and interesting framework on conceptual change in the philosophy of science; and it includes an account of conceptual progress as well.
    [Show full text]