Impiety in Epigraphic Evidence*

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Impiety in Epigraphic Evidence* Kernos Revue internationale et pluridisciplinaire de religion grecque antique 24 | 2011 Varia Impiety in Epigraphic Evidence Aurian Delli Pizzi Édition électronique URL : http://journals.openedition.org/kernos/1934 DOI : 10.4000/kernos.1934 ISSN : 2034-7871 Éditeur Centre international d'étude de la religion grecque antique Édition imprimée Date de publication : 1 janvier 2011 Pagination : 59-76 ISSN : 0776-3824 Référence électronique Aurian Delli Pizzi, « Impiety in Epigraphic Evidence », Kernos [En ligne], 24 | 2011, mis en ligne le 01 février 2014, consulté le 20 avril 2019. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/kernos/1934 ; DOI : 10.4000/kernos.1934 Kernos Kernos 2A (2011), p. 59-75. Impiety i Epigraphic Evide ce∗ Abstract3 The aim of this paper is to highlight several features of the concept of impiety (iq•psk) and of its use in inscriptions. Two main types of epigraphic teNts mention impietyM 1. preventive laws, where formulations such as iqp ±qzw, iqppzw and ±|xmx ±qzw iqppÙ have a dou.le effect inasmuch as they categorize an offence as an impiety and, in addition, they give a culprit the status of impious and 2. reports of trials or of past wrongs. (eing regarded as impious entails other conse-uences on the relationship .etween the culprit and gods .ut also .etween the culprit and the human community – the main issue .eing that these conse-uences are seldom eNplicitly mentioned. Moreover, instead of a single law or teNt defining impiety or proceedings to take place in case of impiety, there is an array of teNts in which impiety appears, the sum of which forms what a community would legally recognize as an impiety. Résumé M 2et article vise L mettre en eNergue diff rentes particularit s du concept dIimpi t (iq•psk) et de son utilisation dans les inscriptions. DeuN types principauN de teNtes pigraphi-ues mentionnent lIimpi t M 1. des lois pr ventives, dans les-uelles des formulations telles -ue iqp ±qzw, iqppzw et ±|xmx ±qzw iqppÙ ont un dou.le effet dans la mesure oJ elles d finissent une infraction comme tant une impi t et, de surcroTt, elles conf;rent au coupa.le le statut dIimpie et 2. des rapports de proc;s ou de torts commis par le pass . Útre consid r impie entraTne dIautres cons -uences, dans la relation du coupa.le avec les dieuN mais galement avec la communaut humaine – le pro.l;me tant principalement -ue ces cons -uences sont rarement eNplicitement mentionn es. De plus, au lieu dIune loi uni-ue d finissant lIimpi t ou envisageant les proc dures L mettre en place en cas dIimpi t , il y a un ensem.le de teNtes dans les-uels apparaTt lIimpi t , dont la somme forme ce -uIune commu- naut reconnaTtrait l galement comme impi t . The concept of impiety (iq•psk) in ancient Greek religion is compleN. Firstly, definitions provided .y ancient authors themselves point out, as potential victims of an impious act, different actors whose connections with each other do not seem a priori o.vious to us, such as gods and parents.1 It was ∗ I am eNtremely grateful to Prof. Vinciane Pirenne-Delforge, Angelos 2haniotis andRo.ert Parker for theirhelpful criticisms on earlier drafts of thispaper.Many thanks to Dr. (eate Dignas and2harles 2rowther for their interest in my research andtheir support. Athina Mitropoulos and Justine Potts have kindly contri.utedto the improvement of my English. Any remaining error is mine. 1 See in particular ps.-Aristotle, 4irtues and vices, 1251aM “There are three types of offence (isk)M impiety, greediness(j~px|pk)andoutrage (Ûls).Impietyisafault(j~•~psk)regarding gods, daemons or deceased persons, parents or homeland_, and Poly.ius, XXXVI, 9M “Impiety means committing a wrong (·klzo|ps|) in respect of what is related to gods, parents and deceased persons_. A common point .etween these elements is that normally they should all .e granted a certain amount of honour (zsn). }q•psk can thus .e seen as a lack of zsn. 50 A. DELLI PI&&I similarly pro.lematic for ancient authors to define piety as well as impiety, as is o.vious in PlatoIs Euthyphro.2 Moreover, modern scholarship has mostly fo- cused on the legal treatment of impiety and on Athenian case studies, such as Socrates and other philosophersI alleged trials for impiety.3 This focus has led to two assumptionsM .eing impious could only .ring an individual to .e prosecuted in a court and, since most of the impious individuals studied .y scholars would .e philosophers, impiety was intrinsically linked to atheism or, at least, to a pro.lem of |xºps| zx¹ rpx”.A I am convinced that several essential aspects of impiety have .een neglected through these approaches.5 This paper cannot claim comprehensiveness, .ut I would like to focus on a specific issueM the use of impiety in epigraphic docu- mentary evidence. Impiety is an offence, an isk – i.e., to put it crudely, a wrong that you might do and that is likely to .e punished in some way.5 Imperative formulations used in preventive laws, such as iqp ±qzw, iqppzw and ±|xmx ±qzw iqppÙ, categorize a given isk as an impiety, .ut also imply that from now on the culprit will .e regarded as impious, and this status will 2 On this dialogue, see L. (R)IT &AIDMAN, .e commerce des dieux: euse.eia, essai sur la pi5t5 en GrQce ancienne, Paris, 2001, p.15A-157. One couldo.Pect to my statement that not much could easilybedefinedwithaninterlocutorsuchasSocrates. 3 It is however not certain that these trials took place, andscholars have different positions on the matter. E. DERENNE, .es procQs d2impi5té intentés auxphilosophes 8 AthQnes au 4me etau I4me siQcles avant c.7C., Li;ge/Paris, 1930, provides a -uite o.solete though inescapa.le overview of these trials. More recently, on Protagoras, see D. LENFANT, “Protagoras et son proc;s d’impi t M peut-on soutenir une th;se et son contraire?_, Ktema 27 (2002), p.135-15A, which rightly casts dou.t on the historicity of this trial and criticizes anachronistic concepts, such as “intellectual freedom_ or “tolerance_X on Nino, Phryne andNeaira, see e.g. 1. TRAMPEDA2,, “Gefhhrliche Frauen. &u athenischen Ase.ie-Prozessen im A. Jh. v. 2hr._, in R. VON DEN ,OFF, St. S2,MIDT (eds.), Konstruktionen von Wirklichkeit. Lilder im Griechenland des l. und a. cahrhunderts v. Chr., Stuttgart, 2001, p. 137-155X R. PAR1ER, 1olytheism and Society at Athens, ONford, 2005, p. 133-135X E. EIDINO , 3racles, Curses and Risk among the Ancient Greeks, ONford, 2007, p.29 and 153X on Aristotle, see R.BODE)S, “LIimpi t d’Aristote_, Kernos 15 (2002), p. 51-55 andM.-F. (ASLE&, .es pers5cutions dans l2Antiquité: victimes, h5ros, martyrs, Paris, 2007, p.35-39. For an overview of the trials for impiety in Athens in the fourth century (2, see L.-L. S)LLIVAN, “Athenian Impiety Trials in the Late Fourth 2entury (2_, C6 A7 (1997), p.135-152. For cautious remarks a.out the historicity of all these trials, see S. 1RA)TER, Lmrgerrecht und Kultteilnahme. 1olitische und kultische Rechte und 1flichtenin griechischen 1oleis,Romundantikem cudentum,Berlin,200A, p.231-2A9. A On the -uestion of “un.elief_ and |xºps| zx¹ rpx”, see . FA,R, "IE JIHD "&J. :um 1roblem der Anfnge des Atheismus bei den Griechen, ,ildesheim, 1959, p. 150-152 et passimX R. PAR1ER, Athenian Religion: A 0istory, ONford, 1995, chap. IXX M. GIORDANO-&A2,ARDA, “As Socrates Shows, the Athenians Did Not (elieve in Gods_, Numen 52 (2005), p. 325-355X ,. 2AN2I1- LINDEMAIER, “Gottlosigkeit im Altertum. Materialismus – Pantheismus – Religionskritik – Atheismus_, in R. FA(ER,S. LAN ERD (eds.), Atheismus: Ideologie, 1hilosophie oder Mentalitt9, ürz.urg, 2005, p. 15-3A. 5 Impiety will .e the topic of my doctoral research, entitled “Transgression of Norm in AncientGreekReligioninClassical,HellenisticandRomanPeriodsMtheCaseofImpiety._ 5 The link .etween iq•psk andisk is o.vious in some statements, though clearly on a rhetorical level. See e.g. the parallel in Andocides, 3n the mysteries, 31M Õ|k zswlnqzp | zx¹ iqpx|zk,σ»ºzpδτx¹ †| isx|zkX ibid.,132Mν|δ iqp{κk is{εqs¿|ετ• ‘plo. Impiety in Epigraphic Evidence 51 legitimize the application of sanctions from other mem.ers of the community. In other words, iqp ±qzw, “let him .e impious_, should .e understood as a shorter version of “let him .e punished as one who is regarded as impious_.7 Far from .eing a simple linguistic twist, the connection .etween committing an iq•psk and .eing iqpn has not insignificant conse-uences for how we should understand impiety and its implications in Greek society, as well as the Greek legal system in general. O.viously elliptic formulations in “adPective + ±qzw_ in preventive laws are not restricted to impiety, and it is pro.a.ly wise to consider that what is said here a.out iq•psk cannot .e systematically applied to other concepts. For eNample we have several attestations of i|uqsx| ±qzw. In these cases, however, i|uqsx designates an o.Pect, not a person.8 Moreover, the term ™qsx is used a lot, especially in the eNpression z• ‘plo k z• ™qsk9, .ut surprisingly its antonym is -uite rare in epigraphic teNts. This suggests that the difference .etween i|uqsx and iqpn is more important than usually thought or at least shown in translations.10 Moreover, there are also many eNamples of ‘pluq~x ±qzw, to which I will return .elow, and zwl”mx ±qzw, in epitaphs from Asia Minor, which I will pass over in the present paper. Studying the way ancient Greeks delimited the concept of impiety is of first importance, as it may help us avoid .eing trapped in a pro.lem of inaccuracy -uite common in modern scholarshipM impiety has often .een discussed even in cases where ancient authors did not mention it.
Recommended publications
  • A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion
    ABSTRACT Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A., M.A. Mentor: T. Michael Parrish, Ph.D. The trouble with “definitions” is they leave no room for evolution. When a word is concretely defined, it is done so in a particular time and place. Contextual interpretations permit a better understanding of certain heavy words; Atheism as a prime example. In the post-modern world Atheism has become more accepted and popular, especially as a reaction to global terrorism. However, the current definition of Atheism is terribly inaccurate. It cannot be stated properly that pagan Atheism is the same as New Atheism. By interpreting the Atheisms from four stages in the term‟s history a clearer picture of its meaning will come out, hopefully alleviating the stereotypical biases weighed upon it. In the interpretation of the Atheisms from Pagan Antiquity, the Enlightenment, the New Atheist Movement, and the American Judicial and Civil Religious system, a defense of the theory of elastic contextual interpretations, rather than concrete definitions, shall be made. Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion by Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A. A Thesis Approved by the J.M. Dawson Institute of Church-State Studies ___________________________________ Robyn L. Driskell, Ph.D., Interim Chairperson Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Baylor University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Approved by the Thesis Committee ___________________________________ T.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates and Democratic Athens: the Story of the Trial in Its Historical and Legal Contexts
    Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. Version 1.0 July 2006 Josiah Ober Princeton University Abstract: Socrates was both a loyal citizen (by his own lights) and a critic of the democratic community’s way of doing things. This led to a crisis in 339 B.C. In order to understand Socrates’ and the Athenian community’s actions (as reported by Plato and Xenophon) it is necessary to understand the historical and legal contexts, the democratic state’s commitment to the notion that citizens are resonsible for the effects of their actions, and Socrates’ reasons for preferring to live in Athens rather than in states that might (by his lights) have had substantively better legal systems. Written for the Cambridge Companion to Socrates. © Josiah Ober. [email protected] Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. (for Cambridge Companion to Socrates) Josiah Ober, Princeton University Draft of August 2004 In 399 B.C. the Athenian citizen Socrates, son of Sophroniscus of the deme (township) Alopece, was tried by an Athenian court on the charge of impiety (asebeia). He was found guilty by a narrow majority of the empanelled judges and executed in the public prison a few days later. The trial and execution constitute the best documented events in Socrates’ life and a defining moment in the relationship between Greek philosophy and Athenian democracy. Ever since, philosophers and historians have sought to
    [Show full text]
  • Pagan and Christian Demonology of the Ante-Nicene Period
    o ujHOUSTON. r" > &O • vjyTEXAS / j v * RICE UNIVERSITY Pagan and Christian Demonology of the Ante-Nicene Period ty' Diana Lynn Walzel A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OP THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OP Master of Arts Thesis Director*s signature: Houston, Texas May, 1972 Abstract Pagan and Christian Demonology of the Ante-Nicene Period ty Diana Lynn Walzel' The idea of progress has become one of the central concepts of western civilization; but in the ante-Nicene period, this idea, with its inherent optimism, was little known. The universe was controlled by supernatural forces which were often working against man. Fate and the stars controlled the lives of men, but controlling the stars were demons. These pages review pagan and Christian demonology from Plato to Xamblichus, During these centuries, there were variations among the pagans in the concept of the function and nature of demons*, but the answers to the three main philosophic questions implicit ;.in demonology — the problem of evil, the problem of unity and diversity, and the relationship of the soul to a higher sphere - remained remarkably the same, Christianity, because of a different view of the universe, answered these questions in a different way. The early Christians, from Paul to Lactantlus, proclaimed victory over the demonic forces which held the pagan world in fear. By the cross of Jesus Christ, the power of the demonic forces which had enslaved men was broken. The major battle against the forces of evil had been won-, and the cross was a positive token that ultimately a kingdom would be established in which demons had no power.
    [Show full text]
  • The Derveni Papyrus ("Diagoras of Melos, Apopyrgizontes Logoi?"): a New Translation Author(S): Richard Janko Reviewed Work(S): Source: Classical Philology, Vol
    The Derveni Papyrus ("Diagoras of Melos, Apopyrgizontes Logoi?"): A New Translation Author(s): Richard Janko Reviewed work(s): Source: Classical Philology, Vol. 96, No. 1 (Jan., 2001), pp. 1-32 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1215469 . Accessed: 15/05/2012 18:47 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Classical Philology. http://www.jstor.org THE DERVENI PAPYRUS (DIAGORAS OF MELOS, APOPYRGIZONTESLOGOI?): A NEW TRANSLATION RICHARD JANKO I. THE AIM AND OUTLOOK OF THE DERVENI AUTHOR HE DERVENI PAPYRUS, our oldest surviving Greek manuscript, was discovered in the remains of a funeral pyre1almost forty years ago, in January 1962. Along with other bizarre and astounding material, it offers an allegorical interpretationof a cosmogonic poem ascribed to Or- pheus. It is a text of capital importance for understandingthe religious and philosophical crisis of the late fifth century B.C.E.,when polytheism was challenged by monotheism and pantheism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Eleusinian Mysteries & Rites
    THE ELEUSINIAN MYSTERIES & RITES DUDLEY WRIGHT THE ELEUSINIAN MYSTERIES AND RITES THE ELEUSINIAN MYSTERIES ^ RITES BY DUDLEY WRIGHT INTRODUCTION BY THE REV. J. FORT NEWTON, D.Litt., D.D. Past Grand Chaplain of the Grand Lodge of lowa^ U.S.tA. THE THEOSOPHICAL PUBLISHING HOUSE I UPPER WOBURN PLACE LONDON, W.C.I "THE SQUARE & COMPASS," 4, 412, Beach Court, Denver, Colo. U.S.A. n CO 5 U ^ PREFACE AT one time the Mysteries of the various nations were the only vehicle of religion throughout the world, and it is not impossible that the very name of religion might have become obsolete but for the support of the periodical celebrations which preserved all the forms and ceremonials, rites and practices of sacred worship. With regard to the connection, supposed or real, between Freemasonry and the Mysteries, it is a remarkable coincidence that there is scarcely a single ceremony in the former that has not its corresponding rite in one or other of the Ancient Mysteries. The question as to which is the original is an important one to the student. The Masonic antiquarian maintains that Freemasonry is not a scion snatched with a violent hand from the Mysteries—whether Pythagorean, Hermetic, Samothracian, Eleusinian, Drusian, Druidical, or the Uke—but is the original institution, from which all the Mysteries were derived. 8 ELEUSINIAN MYSTERIES AND RITES In the opinion of the renowned Dr. George Ohver : *' There is ample testimony to estabhsh the fact that the Mysteries of all nations were originally the same, and diversified only by the accidental circumstances of local situation and pohtical economy." The original foundation of the Mysteries has, however, never been established.
    [Show full text]
  • The Atheism of Epicurus , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 30:2 (1989) P.187
    OBBINK, DIRK, The Atheism of Epicurus , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 30:2 (1989) p.187 The Atheism of Epicurus Dirk Obbink PICURUS, who defines himself in opposition to notorious E atheists of the classical period, argues emphatically in extant works for the existence of a supremely blessed, living, and imperishable form of divinity ('tov 9£ov ~cpov acp9ap'tov Kat J.1a­ KUptoV). Yet there was a tradition current in many circles in antiquity that Epicurus was himself an atheist;! and in modern times his hedonism and his opposition to teleology have often been equated with a general godlessness and contempt for traditional religion.2 Scholars have long puzzled over just how this discrepancy 1 E.g. Cic. Nat.D. 1.123 citing Posidonius (fr.22a Edelstein-Kidd=346 Theiler, quoted 208 infra); 1.85 (Cotta). Cf Sext. Emp. Math. 9.58 (209 infra); Pluto Mor. 1102B, 1112D, 1119D-E, 1123E; Lact. De ira Dei 4.7 (Posidonius fr.22b E.-K.=346 Th.); Inst.Epit. 31.3. A more complete list in M. Winiarczyk, "Wer galtimAltertum als Atheist?" Philologus 128 (1984) 157-83 at 168-70. 2 A common sentiment is Clem. Alex. Protr. 5.66.5 (CCS 52 [15] p.51.6-9 Stahlin­ Treu): 'E1ttKOUPOU ~EV yap ~6vou Kal. EKrov tKh:rlO"O~at, 0<; OUOEv ~tAEtV OtE'tat 't ii> SEep, btu 1t<lv'tcov ao"E~rov. In modern times such representation is commonplace (e.g. E. Zeller, Die Philosophie der Criechen IILls [Leipzig 1923] 429f, 437 n.2), including a long line of German idealists, from Hegel through Marx to Sartre.
    [Show full text]
  • St. Augustine As a Historian of Philosophy
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1934 St. Augustine as a Historian of Philosophy James Patrick Brogan Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Brogan, James Patrick, "St. Augustine as a Historian of Philosophy" (1934). Master's Theses. 73. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/73 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1934 James Patrick Brogan 37 A. M. D. G. ST. AUGUSTINE AS A HISTORIAN OF EHILOSO?HY. A Thesis submitted to the Graduate .l!'aculty of ~oyola University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of AI"ts, Loyola University Chicago, Ill. 1934. JAMES ?ATRIC£ BROGAN. Vita. I was born July 2, 1911, in' the CLty of Toledo, Ohio. I attended the Immacul~te Conception grammox school. Upon completion of the eig'ht year course I enrolled at St. John's High School, from which I w~s gr~duated in 1~29. I Received the degree of Bachelor of Arts fro~n St. John's Uni­ versity in June, 1933. TaB1E OF CONTENTS. ?age. Vita. Introduction 1. Thales 7. Anwcimunder 8 A.naximenes 9 Pythagoras 11 Heraclitus 12 AO.axagorus 1;, Archelaus 15 Diogenes 16 Democritus 16 Sophists 19 Socrb.tes 20 A.ntisthenes 22 A.ristippus 23 Plato 24 Successors of Elatp 34 Aristotle 35 Stoics 37 Epicureans 42 Plotiuus 45 Porp.b.ry 47 Conclusion 50.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates' Understanding of His Trial: the Political Presentation of Philosophy
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by eScholarship@BC Socrates' Understanding of his Trial: The Political Presentation of Philosophy Author: Kazutaka Kondo Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3926 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2011 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Political Science SOCRATES’ UNDERSTANDING OF HIS TRIAL: THE POLITICAL PRESENTATION OF PHILOSOPHY a dissertation by KAZUTAKA KONDO submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 2011 © copyright by KAZUTAKA KONDO 2011 Abstract Socrates’ Understanding of his Trial: The Political Presentation of Philosophy Kazutaka Kondo Dissertation Advisor: Robert C. Bartlett This dissertation investigates how Socrates understands his trial. It is a well-known fact that Socrates is accused of impiety and corruption of the young and is subsequently executed. Unlike an ordinary defendant who is supposed to make every effort to be acquitted, Socrates, behaving provocatively, seems even to induce the death penalty. By reading Plato’s and Xenophon’s works, this dissertation clarifies his thoughts on the trial that must be the basis of his conduct and explains how he achieves his aim. To deal with Socrates’ view of the trial as a whole, this study examines three questions. First, does he believe in his own innocence? I argue that before and even at the trial, Socrates does not intend to prove his innocence effectively.
    [Show full text]
  • Saving Socrates: a New Socratic Portrait Anthony Lobrace Union College - Schenectady, NY
    Union College Union | Digital Works Honors Theses Student Work 6-2016 Saving Socrates: A New Socratic Portrait Anthony LoBrace Union College - Schenectady, NY Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalworks.union.edu/theses Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, and the Legal Commons Recommended Citation LoBrace, Anthony, "Saving Socrates: A New Socratic Portrait" (2016). Honors Theses. 176. https://digitalworks.union.edu/theses/176 This Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Work at Union | Digital Works. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Union | Digital Works. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LoBrace i Saving Socrates: A New Socratic Portrait By Anthony LoBrace ******************** Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for Honors in the Departments of Philosophy and Classics UNION COLLEGE June, 2016 LoBrace ii ABSTRACT LOBRACE, ANTHONY Saving Socrates: A New Socratic Portrait. Departments of Philosophy and Classics, June 2016 ADVISORS: Professor Robert Baker and Professor Tommaso Gazzarri In 399 B.C. Socrates was indicted on charges of asebeia, or impiety and corrupting the youth. He was brought before a jury of some 500 Athenians in a type of trial known as agon timetos, or “trial of assessment”. Casting their votes, the vast majority of the jurors found Socrates guilty of the offenses he was accused of. A week later he drank a cup of hemlock and died in his prison cell. In what follows I will draw a new portrait of Socrates.
    [Show full text]
  • THE ELEUSINIAN MYSTERIES and POLITICAL TIMING in the LIFE of ALCIBIADES Del M F. Leão 1. Alcibiades and the Scandals of 415
    THE ELEUSINIAN MYSTERIES AND POLITICAL TIMING IN THE LIFE OF ALCIBIADES Del m F. Leão 1. Alcibiades and the Scandals of 415bc Among modern scholars and readers of Plato, Socrates’ trial is usually con- sidered to be the most important case of religious impiety (asebeia) and, according to the sources, it was also the most widely discussed, already in antiquity. Nevertheless, that perspective is mainly due to Plato’s inuence and to his success in presenting his master as a kind of martyr of philosoph- ical thinking. Conversely, for the average Athenian of the end of the fth century, the serious events that occurred in the days before the expedition against Sicily must have had a much greater impact, once they inspired a feeling of collective fear, which would be converted into an intense “witch hunt”, i.e. into a restless search for information which might lead to the presumptive authors of such provocative actions. The importance of these events, whose efects would be felt in Athenian society for years, is well known, wherefore this paper will not aim at analyzing the subject in detail once again, except for evoking the historical context that underlined the involvement of Alcibiades—the most emblematic politician of the time— in the scandals of that moment.1 The scandals comprised a double crime of asebeia: the mutilation of the Herms and the parody of the Eleusinian Mysteries. Nonetheless, only the rst was intended to have public visibil- ity, since the evidence points to the idea that the parody of the Mysteries was designed primarily to remain secret and in the private sphere.
    [Show full text]
  • The PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHERS (1) the Milesian School
    1 the PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHERS The appellation 'pre-Socratic' is a little misleading, since it refers to a number of philosophers who were contem- poraries of Socrates, and excludes both Protagoras and Socrates. It actually refers more to a brand of philosophy, dominated by an interest in the Natural world, mathematics, form, etc., and a quest to understand origins, mechanics, and to formulate hypotheses about the world. The ideas of Socrates, developed by Plato, instead allotted much more importance to social, political, and moral questions, and in doing so consciously reacted against the 'pre-Socratics'. Unfortunately most of what we know about the pre-Socratics comes from Plato and Aristotle, along with a number of other commentators (notably Theophrastus); we have almost none of the original writings of these philosophers. This is a great shame, but somewhat inevitable- as we shall see later, we are rather lucky to have any of the contributions of the Greeks available today. For our purposes the most important thing about the pre-Socratics is (i) the extent to which they anticipated both the later Greek ideas (indeed, some of the key ideas of Plato started from Heraclitus and Parmenides on the philosophical side, and from the earlier Pythagorean work in mathematics); and (ii) that their ideas in many ways represent the very beginnings of what we now call scientific enquiry. For this latter reason alone they deserve our attention- for although the beginnings of any really new area of human thought are always hard to understand, being inevitably somewhat disorganised, they are the crucial leaps that have brought us to where we are now.
    [Show full text]
  • Athenian Impiety Trials: a Reappraisal*
    JAKUB FILONIK ATHENIAN IMPIETY TRIALS: A REAPPRAISAL* Abstract This paper aims to critically analyse the testimonies concerning Athenian im- piety trials of the classical period. First, it reaffirms the arguments that some of them must have been an invention of Hellenistic and later authors. Second, it presents a likely political background behind the historical cases. Third, it discusses a number of legal issues, along with new arguments concerning the procedures employed. Finally, it examines some less well-known material from the fourth century BCE. Overall, it seeks to provide a possibly coherent and com- prehensive framework of Athenian impiety trials based on their shared charac- teristics. L’articolo intende condurre un’analisi critica delle testimonianze riguardanti i processi per empietà nell’Atene del periodo classico. Prima di tutto riafferma che alcuni di essi devono essere considerati invenzioni di autori ellenistici o an- che più tardi. In secondo luogo mira a ricostruire il probabile retroscena politico dei casi che si possono considerare storicamente dati. In terzo luogo approfon- disce un certo numero di problemi giuridici, presentando in particolare nuovi argomenti relativi alle procedure impiegate. Infine vengono esaminate alcune fonti meno note risalenti al IV sec. a.C. In generale si sforza di ricostruire un quadro il più possibile coerente ed esaustivo dei processi per empietà ateniesi, mettendone in luce le caratteristiche comuni. * An earlier version of this paper is scheduled to appear in two consecutive issues of Meander (in Polish). This revised study would not have been possible without the generous support of the Hardt Foundation and the exchange pro- gramme at Indiana University Bloomington for which I am very grateful.
    [Show full text]