Animal Signalling and Communication Purposes of Signals Signal Components Tactical Components

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Animal Signalling and Communication Purposes of Signals Signal Components Tactical Components 2. Sexual ritual or calling behavior between males Purposes of Signals and females Tungara Frogs Fireflies Animal Signalling and 1. recognition of species, individuals, neighbors, castes (social insects), kin, or demes 3. Establishing territories and/or social status Communication •Bird-song differences between species: are they Red deer, red-winged blackbirds adaptive? •Allopatric Speciation 4. Alarm calling •Hybridization zones Ground squirrels •If hybridization decreases fitness, we’d expect Outline: Great tits and other birds subject to raptor predation greater song differentiation in areas of closely- 1. Purposes and variety of Convergent evolution in “seet” calls related species overlap. signals •Gill and Murray (1972): Compared bird songs of 2. Signals in evolutionary context golden-winged and blue-winged warbler in areas of species 5. Information in groups of foragers Tactical components overlap and non-overlap Honey-bee example. The Sensory exploitation “Waggle Dance” Unintended receivers •Songs were less 3. Evolutionary thought on signalling varied in areas of Number of waggles gives •Strategic components overlap, perhaps info re: distance to food •Honest and deceptive signals because it was •Zahavi’s handicap principle adaptive to be more Direction of the straight- 4. Specific examples in territorial behavior specific. run gives info regarding •But this is a lone the direction toward a study amongst Golden-winged warbler food source. many that suggest bird song is not so important for species recognition. Tactical Components 6. Parental care: offspring/parent recognition Signal Components “Getting the message across” Studholme (1994): Example from Johnstone (1997): Anoline lizards Fiordland penguins Tactical Components: and the “assertion display” versus the “challenge Offspring orient to and Features of a signal which are concerned display” respond to their parent’s with how easy it is for the signaller to calls more than other calls. (But parents seem transmit it, for the receiver to receive it and less responsive to their discriminate it from other signals. particular offspring’s call.) Strategic Components: The assertion display is not Properties of a signal that are concerned sent out to anyone in parti- with what good they do to the signaller, i.e. cular. But it “ought” to be how does the signaller benefit from emitting noticed by some other lizard. the signal. Conveying Hunger levels: •Common features of signals ensuring their appropriate reception: Adult birds bringing food back Both have been viewed from an adaptationist 1. Conspicuousness for nestlings. The hungrier nestlings perspective. 2. Stereotypy analogy to electronic signal transmission could scream louder. 3. Redundancy } 4. Alerting components Tactical Components and the Back to the Methodology Zone for a moment: The Nasty Statistical Issue: It is important to know if the observed relationship Environment The Comparative Method between the two variables in statistically significant. Signals’ conspicuousness seems to have evolved with However a simple linear regression (put a least- respect to the environmental background. •Definition: squares-fit line through the data and then test to see •Marchetti (1993): Plumage patterns of congeneric Quite often, the relationship between two traits, if the slope of the line is significantly different from warblers. Those living in low light environments had OR the relationship between an environmental zero) is invalid because it assumes that all the brighter plumage. characteristic and an organismal trait will be observations are independent. •Wiley (1991): Comparison of song-birds in North explored by comparison of the traits and American habitats. environments across species (or other taxa). But in the comparative method, the different points •Rated sonograms of birdsongs for The goal is to demonstrate a significant are not independent. They are related by their •period of repeat of elements correlation between the two traits in question, or common phylogenetic history. Consider: •buzzes between the environmental conditions and the trait. This, then, might be taken as evidence of •side-bands oo o adaptation. This process is called the o o •Categories for habitat type (i.e. grassland versus o forest, etc) Comparative Method. x xx x •Songs from birds in open habitat had more •Example: Length of Rep. El. reveberation-degradable features than songs from Studying, for example, the length of a repeated Env. Reverb forest habitats. element in bird songs versus the amount of x reverberation from the environment x x x xx each x represents a x x x different species o x o x xx x o Some Sonograms of different birdsongs Length of Rep. El. o Env. Reverb o If the X’s and O’s are more closely related to one another, Tactical Components and the Tactical Components and evolutionarily, then the observations in the cluster of X’s and the cluster of O’s are not independent of one another. “Audience” Unintended Audiences “Color blind organisms should not have colorful A simple linear regression will treat each point (species) as displays or signals.” Any time an animal is signalling, the message if it were an independent observation. may get picked up by an unintended receiver The Result: too much statistical significance inferred. Sensory Exploitation: (for example a predator). When signalling behavior evolves to take advantage of In reality, bird species of the “x” cluster may have all pre-existing sensory biases. Two types of alarm calls in great tits: inherited a mutation that shortens the length of song Proctor (1991): male water mites Mobbing alarm call: loud indiscreet signal to elements, and they may live in less reverberative “tremble” at a similar frequency to others to mob and molest a perched hawk. environments, but the two may not be related. prey. The females are acutely sens- itive to this (being part of their for- “Seet” alarm call: short, high-pitched, discrete There are methods to try to correct for the non- aging behavior repertoire). alarm call given to warn others of a flying hawk. independence between closely related species (for example Felsenstein (1985)). The female grabs at the The frequency of the seet call is high enough that These are what Johnstone is referring to when he uses male who somehow con- hawks cannot hear it very well, but it is well within phrases like “incorporating various measures to control tends with the female’s the range that great tits can hear well. fro the effects of phylogeny.” mouth parts, and is able to effectively mate with (Studies with hawk orientation to recorded seet her. calls.) Was this sensory exploita- tion? (Proctor 1992) and phylogenies. The Evolution of Strategic Signalling and Conflict of Honest Signals Interest Components of Signals An honest signal is one which reflects the true state of Signaller and Receiver don’t always stand to benefit in the sender by virtue of physical necessity Traditional Ethological View (Pre-1970’s) the same way •Signals were there to “facilitate and coordinate Examples: social interactions by making information available Examples: Hill and Montgemorie (1994): Correlation between to be shared.” Displays of territory owners coloration and nutritional condition of male house •Reasonable for cooperative signaling--- finches •When both the signaller and the receiver In some species males seek matings with as many benefit females as possible while females seek to mate with •Deceit was not commonly considered, even the “most fit” males though it was well-known on an inter-specific level, i.e. Batesian mimicry: Early 1970’s. Maynard Smith and game theory for signalling---without appropriate controls deceit should abound and signals should evolve to become meaningless. Since signals are not all meaningless, something has Clutton-Brock and red deer roaring contests maintained their honesty or utility. What? Two main (and related) types of explanation: Also, frog-croaking tone. Small frogs •“Honest Signals” are unable to croak at the lowest freqs. •Handicap Principle Main point = direct link between the ability to generate the Viceroy Butterfly Monarch Butterfly These reflect other evolutionary pressures that may be signal and the physical condition or foraging ability (taken Basilarchia archipus Danaus plexipus acting on signalling behavior to be a surrogate for fitness) of the signaller Another way (in theory) to curtail deceit Handicap Principle At the heart of the Handicap Principle are (Zahavi 1975 and later) Condition-Dependent Cost or •Similar to the Honest Signal notion, but here the link Benefits between condition and the ability to generate the signal is The signal/handicap must cost more for the “low-quality” not so clear. individual than the “high-quality” individual •Rather, deceit is discouraged because one must have high fitness in order to overcome the handicap of the signal. Conceptually/Graphically: •Example: Andersson (1982): Male Widowbirds in central Costs to africa. The “signal” is the long tail. Low Qual. Benefit of •Females have a preference for males with long tails Indiv. the signal •The tails don’t confer a fitness advantage to the males- --if anything they are a handicap. Male Widowbird Costs to Hi Qual. Indiv. Costs and Benefits Notion of the handicap principle Signal Intensity echoes Veblen (1899): The Theory of the Leisure Class, and his idea of This has made actual testing of the Handicap “conspicuous Principle very difficult. Almost no studies consumption” have managed to quantify condition-dependent costs..
Recommended publications
  • Does the Handicap Principle Explain the Evolution of Dimorphic Ornaments?
    Animal Behaviour xxx (2018) e1ee4 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Animal Behaviour journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/anbehav Forum Does the handicap principle explain the evolution of dimorphic ornaments? * Szabolcs Szamad o a, , Dustin J. Penn b a RECENS ‘Lendület’ Research Group, MTA Centre for Social Science, Budapest, Hungary b Konrad Lorenz Institute of Ethology, Department of Integrative Biology and Evolution, University of Veterinary Medicine, Vienna, Austria article info Article history: Received 12 July 2017 Initial acceptance 5 October 2017 Final acceptance 22 November 2017 Available online xxx MS. number: 17-00560 Keywords: Handicap principle Honest signalling Dimorphic ornaments Bimodal fitness Playing-the-field Many species are sexually dimorphic and, interestingly, males in concluding that it provides an explanation for the evolution of male some species are dimorphic themselves: some males develop dimorphisms. weapons and ornaments, whereas others express rudimentary or- There are many versions and interpretations of the handicap naments or none at all (horned beetles, Onthophagus taurus: Emlen, hypothesis, but it is unclear which version was implemented for the Lavine, & Ewen-Campen, 2007; Moczek & Emlen, 2000; bluegill authors' new model. This omission makes it impossible to under- sunfish, Lepomis macrochirus: Dominey, 1980; Gross & Charnov, stand the novelty of the model and how it succeeds in explaining 1980; ruffs, Philomachus pugnax: Lank, Smith, Hanotte, Burke, & male dimorphisms or why others failed. The authors cite the Cooke, 1995; for a review see Simpson, Sword, & Lo, 2011). Males original handicap hypothesis (Zahavi, 1975), and yet this version can be so extremely dimorphic that the morphs have been mis- does not work (reviewed in Kirkpatrick 1986).
    [Show full text]
  • 1160 Animal Signals and the Overlooked Costs Of
    Evolution, 59(5), 2005, pp. 1160±1161 ANIMAL SIGNALS AND THE OVERLOOKED COSTS OF EFFICACY1 MICHAEL J. RYAN2 AND MOLLY E. CUMMINGS Section of Integrative Biology C0930, University of Texas, Austin, Texas 78712 2E-mail: [email protected] Received March 22, 2005. costly; handicaps can make it more costly, but lack of hand- The most striking aspects of many animals are signals. icap does not make it cost free. This book concentrates on Thus one might expect Animal Signals by John Maynard strategic costs, but offers some tantalizing discussions of ef- Smith and David Harper to discuss the detailed biology of ®cacy costs, which the authors suggest are underappreciated. this half of the communication dyad. Not so. Instead, they We second that notion but feel it is not strong enough. concentrate on a single question, why signals are reliable, The most basic ef®cacy costs of signaling are incurred in and emphasize one methodology to its solution: game theory. creating its morphology, behavior, and neural circuitry. In ad- Although not embracing the entire biology of signaling, the book grapples with a continuing problem. dition, some animals scour the environment to obtain their Signals evolved to communicate information and manip- signals; bowerbirds steal decorations for their bowers (Borgia ulate receivers to the signaler's bene®t. Similarly, the re- and Mueller 1992), and some moths sequester plant alkaloids ceiver's response to signals is under selection to promote its for the ¯occulent showers they bestow upon females (Conner ®tness. The issue at hand is the con¯ict between signal and et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Diploid Models of the Handicap Principle
    Heredity 60 (1988) 283—293 The Genetical Society of Great Britain Received 22June1987 Diploid models of the handicap principle I. P. M. Tomlinson Department of Genetics, Downing Street, Cambridge CB2 3EH, U.K. "Fisherian" models of sexual selection by female choice assume that females prefer male characters which are initially advantageous or neutral; character and preference then spread through the population. Once female preference has evolved to a higher frequency, the male character can become more extreme and disadvantageous by the action of some force such as the "super-normal stimulus". By contrast, the "handicap principle" of sexual selection proposes that females should prefer more extreme, disadvantaged males: males who survive the disadvantage of the "handicap" must be fitter in other respects. Previous models of various forms of the "handicap principle" have shown that it is very unlikely to work as an alternative to the "Fisherian process". However, recent haploid models have shown that a "condition-dependent handicap" might evolve. Diploid models show that the "condition-dependent handicap" model does not work. Models of "handicaps" operating together with the "Fisherian process" are also presented. It is inferred that "Fisherian" models are more likely than "handicap" models to account for the evolution of male sexual ornaments, although a "handicap" mechanism may aid the operation of the "Fisherian process". INTRODUCTION Darwin (1871) and analysed by Fisher (1930): preferred males tend to find mates more easily, Darwin(1871) saw that the males of many species mate earlier in the breeding season in more favour- were often brightly coloured or possessed complex able conditions and therefore gain a natural selec- secondary adornments; females on the other hand tive advantage.
    [Show full text]
  • The Handicap Principle a Missing Piece of DarwinS Puzzle
    Jumping to Bold Conclusions A Review of The Handicap Principle A Missing Piece of Darwins Puzzle by Amotz Zahavi and Avishag Zahavi Oxford University Press Pp $ Seth Bullo ck Center for Adaptive Behavior and Cognition Max Planck Institute for Human Development Lentzeallee D Berlin Dahlem Tel Fax Email bullockmpibberlinmpgde Occasionally a grazing gazelle notices the approach of a predatory lion Rather than immediately taking ight at top sp eed she often jumps high in the air several times b efore eeing Perhaps these stots are warnings to closeby p ossibly related gazelles If this is the case why is the warning so energetic Surely evolution would favor less exhausting signals since exhaustion is to b e avoided when one is ab out to b e pursued by a predator Amotz and Avishag Zahavi op en their recent b o ok with a dierent explanation for this b ehavior They maintain that the stotting gazelle is not warning consp ecics of danger but informing the lion of its own escap e ability Because the lion has no desire to waste time and energy fruitlessly chasing uncatchable prey this information is of use to it but only if the information is truthful It is here the Zahavis claim that an explanation is to b e found for the otherwise inexplicable brio of the gazelles display The authors construe the stotting display as a handicap a signaling b ehavior that incurs the depletion of the very quality it advertises They interpret the gazelles vigorous leaping to convey the honest message that she is t enough and fast enough to waste just so much
    [Show full text]
  • Indirect Selection and Individual Selection in Sociobiology: My Personal Views on Theories of Social Behaviour
    ANIMAL BEHAVIOUR, 2003, 65, 859–863 doi:10.1006/anbe.2003.2109 ANNIVERSARY ESSAY Indirect selection and individual selection in sociobiology: my personal views on theories of social behaviour AMOTZ ZAHAVI Institute for Nature Conservation Research, Tel-Aviv University (Received 25 September 2002; accepted 4 December 2002; MS. number: AE4) This is the story of my involvement in sociobiological studies. I first discuss group selection models, which were common in the 1950s. I then move on to kin selection and reciprocity models, which were developed to replace group selection models and are still being used by many sociobiologists, even though I argue that they contain the same weaknesses that led group selection to be rejected. As an alternative, I present the handicap principle, an essential component in all signalling. The handicap principle is useful in understanding many components of social systems, not the least of which is why individuals invest in the benefit of other members of a social system (altruism). 2003 Published by Elsevier Science Ltd on behalf of The Association for the Study of Animal Behaviour. I have been watching birds since childhood. As a student the kind of questions asked at Oxford at the time: ‘(1) of biology in the early 1950s, I was attracted by the great what is the survival value of the observed behaviour; (2) advances in cell biology and in biochemistry that took what is its causation; (3) how does it develop; and (4) how place at that time. But after spending several months has it evolved?’ Theories that were developed at that time cooped up in a laboratory, I could not resist the temp- to explain the adaptive significance of a particular behav- tation to go out again into the field, looking for rare birds iour did not necessarily seek an ultimate explanation of and watching birds display.
    [Show full text]
  • The Puzzle of Altruism Reconsidered: Biological Theories of Altruism and One- Shot Altruism
    Ratio Working Paper No. 103 The Puzzle of Altruism Reconsidered: Biological Theories of Altruism and One- Shot Altruism Doron Shultziner Arnon Dattner Box 3203 Besöksadress: ratio.se 103 64 Stockholm Sveavägen 59, 4tr The Puzzle of Altruistic Behavior Reconsidered: Biological Theories of Altruism and One-Shot Altruism By Doron Shultziner, Politics & IR Department, University of Oxford Arnon Dattner, Department of Zoology, Tel Aviv University Abstract This paper critically examines the state of the literature in evolutionary biology regarding theories of altruistic behavior. The shared theoretical problems of Kin- selection and Group-selection are examined. Theoretical and severe methodological problems of Reciprocal Altruism theory are also discussed. We offer new conceptual clarifications of the Handicap Principle theory regarding costs and benefits to both the donor and the recipient of an altruistic act. We also summarize supportive empirical studies which demonstrate how Handicap Principle theory easily explains altruistic behavior on a different logic than the one employed by other theories of altruistic behavior. Finally, we discuss the phenomenon of one-shot altruism in order to evaluate, and distinguish between, the predictive and explanatory power of different theories of altruistic behavior. We thank Alan Grafen and Danny Priel for their help in preparing this paper. We are especially grateful to Avishag and Amotz Zahavi for their valuable comments. This paper was presented at the “Trust, Reciprocity and Social Capital: The 2006 Ratio Colloquium for Young Social Scientists” Stockholm, 24th-26th of August 2006. We thank Niclas Berggren and Andreas Bergh of the Ratio Institute for organizing and sponsoring the colloquium which gave us the incentive to write this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • The Application of Animal Signaling Theory to Human Phenomena: Some Thoughts and Clari®Cations
    Biology and social life Biologie et vie sociale Lee Cronk The application of animal signaling theory to human phenomena: some thoughts and clari®cations Abstract. Animal signaling theory has recently become popular among anthropologists as a way to study human communication. One aspect of animal signaling theory, often known as costly signaling or handicap theory, has been used particularly often. This article makes four points regarding these developments: (1)signaling theory is broader than existing studies may make it seem; (2)costly signaling theory has roots in the social as well as the biological sciences; (3)not all honest signals are costly and not all costs borne by signalers serve to ensure honesty; and (4)hard-to-fake signals are favored when the interests of broad categories of signalers and receivers con¯ict but the interests of individual signalers and receivers converge. Key words. Costly signaling theory ± Costly signals ± Hard-to-fake signals ± Honest signals ± Receiver psychology ± Signaling theory ± Signals ReÂsumeÂ. La theÂorie des systeÁmes de signaux chez l'animal est reÂcemment devenue populaire parmi les anthropologues en tant qu'outil d'eÂtude de la communication humaine. L'un des aspects de cette theÂorie, souvent connu sous le nom de theÂorie des systeÁmes de signaux couÃteux, a eÂte le plus souvent utiliseÂ. Cet article tente de faire quatre points sur la question: (1)la theÂorie des systeÁmes de signaux chez l'animal est plus large que les eÂtudes actuelles peuvent le laisser croire; (2)la theÂorie des systeÁmes de signaux couÃteux prend ses racines dans les sciences sociales et les sciences biologiques; I should like to thank Carl Bergstrom, William Irons, Beth L.
    [Show full text]
  • Game Theory and Evolutionary Biology 1
    Chapter 28 GAME THEORY AND EVOLUTIONARY BIOLOGY PETER HAMMERSTEIN Max-Planck-Institut für Verhaltensphysiologie REINHARD SELTEN University of Bonn Contents 1. Introduction 931 2. Conceptual background 932 2.1. Evolutionary stability 932 2.2. The Darwinian view of natural selection 933 2.3. Payoffs 934 2.4. Game theory and population genetics 935 2.5. Players 936 2.6. Symmetry 936 3. Symmetric two-person games 937 3.1. Definitions and notation 937 3.2. The Hawk-Dove garne 937 3.3. Evolutionary stability 938 3.4. Properties ofevolutionarily stable strategies 940 4. Playing the field 942 5. Dynamic foundations 948 5.1. Replicator dynamics 948 5.2. Disequilibrium results 951 5.3. A look at population genetics 952 6. Asymmetric conflicts 962 * We are grateful to Olof Leimar, Sido Mylius, Rolf Weinzierl, Franjo Weissing, and an anonymous referee who all helped us with their critical comments. We also thank the Institute for Advanced Study Berlin for supporting the final revision of this paper. Handbook of Garne Theory, Volume 2, Edited by R.J. Aumann and S. Hart © Elsevier Science B.V., 1994. All rights reserved 930 P. Hammerstein and R. Selten 7. Extensive two-person games 965 7.1. Extensive garnes 965 7.2. Symmetric extensive garnes 966 7.3. Evolutionary stability 968 7.4. Image confrontation and detachment 969 7.5. Decomposition 970 8. Biological applications 971 8.1. Basic qnestions about animal contest behavior 972 8.2. Asymmetric animal contests 974 8.3. War of attrition, assessment, and signalling 978 8.4. The evolution of cooperation 980 8.5.
    [Show full text]
  • Signal Reliability and Intraspecific Deception
    Author's personal copy Signal Reliability and Intraspecific Deception William A Searcy, University of Miami, Coral Gables, FL, United States Stephen Nowicki, Duke University, Durham, NC, United States © 2019 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Abstract A signal is considered to be reliable if (1) some feature of the signal is consistently correlated with an attribute of the signaler or its environment and (2) receivers benefit from knowing about that attribute. Signaling systems that do not provide reliable information may exist if signal features exploit a sensory bias of the receiver. At evolutionary equilibrium, however, signals are expected to be reliable on average, meaning that they are reliable enough that a receiver benefits overall from responding to them rather than ignoring them. When there is a conflict of interest between signaler and receiver, signal reliability requires some mechanism to be maintained. Proposed mechanisms include (1) physical and informational constraints on signal production; (2) signal costs that differentially affect signalers of varying quality (the handicap mechanism); (3) differential benefits, which produce honest signals of need; and (4) receiver-dependent costs, which produce conventional signals whose meaning is not related to their physical structure but rather results from an arbitrary convention. The requirement that signals be reliable only on average allows the possibility of some admixture of intra-specific deception, which has been observed in various types of signals, including signals used in aggression, courtship, predator warning, and begging. Keywords Conventional signals; Dance language; Deception; Developmental stress hypothesis; Handicap principle; Handicaps; Index signals; Matching; Quorum sensing; Receiver-dependent costs; Sensory exploitation; Signal reliability; Signals of need; Song type matching Introduction Signal reliability essentially means honesty: signals are considered to be reliable if they are honest about something of interest to the intended receivers of the signal.
    [Show full text]
  • "Costly Signaling in Human Culture" In
    Costly Signaling in Human Culture JOHN H. SHAVER1 AND RICHARD SOSIS2 1University of Otago, New Zealand 2University of Connecticut, United States Social scientists have long sought to explain seemingly inefficient and maladaptive aspectsofhumanbehavior.Acrosstheworld’scultures,peoplegiveawayfoodwithout expectation of reciprocity, engage in nonoptimal foraging activities, spend time and energy enduring dangerous and painful religious rites, and add functionless ornamen- tationtomaterialobjectsandarchitecture.Thesebehaviorsareespeciallyperplexing to evolutionary scientists, who assume that selection processes result in phenotypes that maximize somatic and reproductive effort. Rather than viewing such behaviors as maladaptive, however, evolutionary anthropologists and archaeologists interpret the wastefulness of these behaviors as enabling reliable and honest communication between individuals with at least partially conflicting interests. Originating with the insights of evolutionary biologist Amotz Zahavi (1975), costly signaling theory (CST) was first used to interpret many of the extravagant behavioral displays and excessive ornamentation found throughout the animal kingdom, such as malereddeerroaring,meral-spreaddisplaysofstomatopods,andlargeantlersamong males of many species. For example, upon spotting a predator (most commonly African wild dogs), Thomson’s gazelles (Eudorcas thomsonii) leap straight up in the air with their backs arched rather than immediately running away. This conspicuous jumping behavior, known as “stotting,” appears to be detrimental to a gazelle’s survival since it likely captures the predator’s attention and requires an expenditure of energy that cannot be used for fleeing. Individual gazelles range in their fitness and their ability to escape predators, and healthy gazelles would do better to not have to bother to flee. Conversely, predators would do better to not have to expend energy chasing a healthy gazelle, when chasing a less fit gazelle would offer a greater net energetic return.
    [Show full text]
  • The Handicap Principle Is an Artifact
    The Handicap Principle Is an Artifact Simon M. Huttegger, Justin P. Bruner, and Kevin J. S. Zollman*y The handicap principle is one of the most influential ideas in evolutionary biology. It as- serts that when there is conflict of interest in a signaling interaction signals must be costly in order to be reliable. While in evolutionary biology it is a common practice to distin- guish between indexes and fakable signals, we argue this dichotomy is an artifact of exist- ing popular signaling models. Once this distinction is abandoned, we show one cannot adequately understand signaling behavior by focusing solely on cost. Under our re- framing, cost becomes one—and probably not the most important—of a collection of fac- tors preventing deception. 1. Introduction. The handicap principle is one of the most influential ideas in evolutionary biology ðZahavi 1975; Grafen 1990; Maynard Smith 1991; Bergstrom and Lachmann 1997; Maynard Smith and Harper 2003; Searcy and Nowicki 2005Þ. It asserts that when there is conflict of interest in a sig- naling interaction signals must be costly in order to be reliable. Such situ- ations are relevant whenever an informed sender has an incentive to hide some information from an uninformed receiver. Examples of this can be found in models of sexual selection, in interactions between predator and prey, and in relationships between parents and offspring. If there are suffi- ciently high differential costs or differential benefits in the signaling inter- action, then honest signaling becomes a feature of an evolutionarily stable state despite conflicts of interest. However, the handicap principle faces se- rious problems from both empirical ðBorgia 1993; Haskell 1994; Caro et al.
    [Show full text]
  • What Maintains Signal Honesty in Animal Colour Displays Used in Mate Choice? Rstb.Royalsocietypublishing.Org Ryan J
    What maintains signal honesty in animal colour displays used in mate choice? rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org Ryan J. Weaver, Rebecca E. Koch and Geoffrey E. Hill Department of Biological Sciences, Auburn University, Auburn, AL 36849, USA RJW, 0000-0002-6160-4735 Review Many of the colour displays of animals are proposed to have evolved in Cite this article: Weaver RJ, Koch RE, Hill GE. response to female mate choice for honest signals of quality, but such 2017 What maintains signal honesty in animal honest signalling requires mechanisms to prevent cheating. The most widely accepted and cited mechanisms for ensuring signal honesty are colour displays used in mate choice? Phil. based on the costly signalling hypothesis, which posits that costs associated Trans. R. Soc. B 372: 20160343. with ornamentation prevent low-quality males from being highly ornamen- http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2016.0343 ted. Alternatively, by the index hypothesis, honesty can be achieved via cost-free mechanisms if ornament production is causally linked to core Accepted: 29 January 2017 physiological pathways. In this essay, we review how a costly signalling fra- mework has shaped empirical research in mate choice for colourful male ornaments and emphasize that alternative interpretations are plausible One contribution of 19 to a theme issue under an index signalling framework. We discuss the challenges in both ‘Animal coloration: production, perception, empirically testing and distinguishing between the two hypotheses, noting function and application’. that they need not be mutually exclusive. Finally, we advocate for a compre- hensive approach to studies of colour signals that includes the explicit consideration of cost-free mechanisms for honesty.
    [Show full text]