The Evolution of Deception in Signaling Systems Candace Ohm

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Evolution of Deception in Signaling Systems Candace Ohm Florida State University Libraries Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations The Graduate School 2013 The Evolution of Deception in Signaling Systems Candace Ohm Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact [email protected] FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF ARTS AND SCIENCES THE EVOLUTION OF DECEPTION IN SIGNALING SYSTEMS By CANDACE OHM A Dissertation submitted to the Department of Mathematics in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Degree Awarded: Fall Semester, 2013 Candace Ohm defended this dissertation on October 10, 2013. The members of the supervisory committee were: Mike Mesterton-Gibbons Professor Directing Dissertation Mark Isaac University Representative Alec Kercheval Committee Member Warren Nichols Committee Member The Graduate School has verified and approved the above-named committee members, and certifies that the dissertation has been approved in accordance with the university requirements. ii This is dedicated to my best friend, my limelight, and a man I lost along the way. To my dearest Grandpa, I will always love you. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Thank you to my advisor, Dr. Mike Mesterton-Gibbons. Thank you for challenging me every step along the way, thank you for never accepting anything less than perfect, and most of all, thank you for teaching me the definition of independence. I couldn’t have asked for a better advisor. I’d also like to thank a few good mentors and committee members I had along the way. To my committee, Dr. Nichols, Dr. Kercheval, and Dr. Isaac, thank you for your outstanding service to the academic community. Thanks to Jonathan Rowell and Patrick Fletcher, you were good friends that offered great advice. Thanks to an undergraduate professor and best friend, Dr. Pam Warton. I owe my graduate school career to Pam’s persistence, intelligence, stubbornness, and faith in me. I’d also like to thank my friends and family. I made six irreplaceable friends along the way that made Tallahassee the place I grew up and the place I call home. Michelle, Tamzyn, Celes, Jenn, Jules, and Tara-thank you for standing by me through the process. Miss Jules—thanks for assisting with your technical editing skills. Thanks to my oldest friends, my brother Matt and cousin Ciressa, for always sharing your honest opinion and for always staying close. Thanks to my uncles, Uncle Craig and Uncle Ruggy, for always making me smile. Finally, thank you to my parents, especially my father, for teaching me the value of hard work. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS ListofTables.......................................... vii ListofFigures ......................................... viii Abstract............................................. ... ix 1 Introduction 1 1.1 DeceptiveSignaling................................. 2 1.2 Signals and Learning . 4 1.3 Agenda ........................................... 5 1.4 Definitions........................................ 7 2 Review of the Literature 9 2.1 Classical Game Theory . 9 2.1.1 The Hawk-Dove Game . 10 2.2 SignalingGames ...................................... 11 2.2.1 The Frequency Dynamics of Signaling Games . 13 2.2.2 Stability Analysis . 15 2.3 Deceptive Signaling in Animal Behavior . 17 2.3.1 One-ReceiverReducedGame . 20 2.3.2 Bluffing by Berritory Holders . 23 2.4 ExtendingtheCurrentLiterature. 26 3 The Two-State Signaling Game with One Receiver 28 3.1 TheGeneralModelwithTwoStates . 28 3.1.1 The Replicator Equations . 30 3.1.2 The Learning Dynamic Equation . 35 3.1.3 A Brief Commentary . 37 3.2 Example:ManipulativeMimics . 39 3.2.1 The Dynamical System . 40 3.2.2 Results ....................................... 45 4 The Two-State Signaling Game with Multiple Receivers 49 4.1 The Replicator Equations . 50 4.2 DeceptioninRHP ..................................... 57 4.2.1 TheModel ..................................... 58 4.2.2 Strategies Within the Signaling System . 61 v 4.2.3 Creating the Payoff Functions . 64 4.2.4 The Dynamical System . 65 4.2.5 Results ....................................... 68 A n−State Games 73 A.1 The Replicator Equations . 74 A.2 TheLearningDynamics ................................. 77 B Code 80 C Copyright Permission 81 References......................................... 82 BiographicalSketch ..................................... 86 vi LIST OF TABLES 1.1 Requirements for a general theory on signaling . 6 2.1 TheHawk-Dovegame .................................... 10 2.2 Local stability analysis . 17 2.3 Payoffs in the one-receiver game . 20 2.4 Payoffsinthebluffingbyterritoryholdersmodel . 24 2.5 Parameters of the bluffing by territory holders model . 25 3.1 Summary of state variables and payoff functions . 31 3.2 Dynamical system for the two-state two receiver model . 38 3.3 Actions of the manipulative mimics game when a mimic is present. 43 3.4 Actions of the predator against a toxic model. 44 4.1 Variables in the n-receiver signaling game . 51 4.2 Dynamical system for the two-state n receivermodel................... 55 4.3 Possible states in the deceptive strength game. 58 4.4 List of values for the deceptive strength game . 59 4.5 Possible states of the deception in RHP game . 60 4.6 Nash mixed strategy equilibria of the deception in RHP game . 60 4.7 Players’ actions in the deception in RHP game . 63 4.8 Payoffs in the deception in RHP game . 65 4.9 Dynamical system for the deception in RHP game . 68 A.1 Variables in the n-state signaling game . 75 vii LIST OF FIGURES 2.1 Lewis signaling games . 13 2.2 The one-receiver game with interior equilibrium . 22 3.1 Extensive form manipulation game . 29 3.2 Themimicoctopus ................................... 40 3.3 A tree of the manipulative mimics game . 42 3.4 Manipulative mimics game vector field . 48 4.1 Manipulation game with n receivers ............................ 50 4.3 Stable interior fixed points for 0.973 / γ ≤ 1 ....................... 69 4.2 DeceptioninRHPequilibria ........................... 72 A.1 The n-statemodel ...................................... 74 viii ABSTRACT In this dissertation, we create a dynamical learning model that helps to explain the evolution of deception in signaling systems. In our model, the signaler may choose to signal either of two possible states. We apply this model to Batesian mimicry and to deceptive signaling of fighting ability, or resource holding potential. We show how to expand this model to allow for multiple receivers as well as multiple possible states. External code for the Batesian mimicry and deceptive signaling of fighting ability models can be accessed via the following link: https://dl.dropboxusercontent.com/u/18728677/Dissertation%20Code.zip ix CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION John Maynard-Smith and David Harper define a signaling device as, “An act or structure that alters the behavior of another organism, which has evolved because of that effect, and which is effective because the receiver’s response has also evolved” [28]. Signals can be externally visible features, behavior patterns, or sounds, all of which are, “designed by natural selection” [25]. Darwinian theory suggests that signaling systems exist because communication, on average, increases the long-term fitness of both the signaler and receiver. The value of a signal to a receiver is as a source of information. The receiver uses this information to choose the behavioral, physiological, or developmental responses that will maximize its fitness [37]. A signal is honest if some characteristic of the signal (which can include its absence or presence) is consistently correlated with some attribute of the signaler or its environment and receivers benefit from having information about this attribute [37]. A signal is a handicap when its honesty is guaranteed because the signaler’s associated costs of the signal are greater than the signal’s requirements for being effective [28]. For example, the antlers of a stag are a sign of strength and dominance because antlers are a stag’s primary tool in battle. However, larger antlers are more costly because there is a direct correlation between antler size and weight, and so larger antlers incur a greater cost over a stag’s lifetime. Thus, antlers are a handicap [50]. According to Zahavi’s handicap principle, all signals must be, on average, honest [50]. The handicap principle explains how honest signaling is able to evolve when a signaler has an obvious motivation to deceive or exaggerate the signal [11, 50]. The three conditions of the handicap 1 principle state that: (1) on average signals must be honest, (2) signals are costly, and (3) the differential costs of signaling correlate to the true quality of the signaler [11, 50]. Zahavi’s handicap principle, initially rejected by many scientists [28, 36, 37, 48], became gener- ally accepted when Alan Grafen constructed various game-theoretic models. The models created by Grafen clarified the handicap principle and substantially increased its importance and scope. The handicap models created by Grafen [11] show under fairly general conditions that if the handicap principle’s conditions are met, then an evolutionarily stable signaling equilibrium exists and any signaling equilibrium must satisfy the conditions of the handicap principle. A signaling equilib- rium is a pair of signaler and receiver strategies such that neither individual gains by selecting a different strategy [11]. Grafen further explained three possible interpretations of the handicap principle. These are: (1) the possession of the handicap puts an extra predation risk upon the individual, (2) differences in quality are exhibited by revealing the handicap (for example, a stag’s quality is revealed in a battle because its antlers, which are a handicap, are being utilized. In contrast, differences in quality are not exhibited when a stag is foraging because antlers do not aid in foraging), and (3) only high quality males are capable of expressing the handicap. 1.1 Deceptive Signaling If honesty is used to define the fundamental conjunction of signal level and perfect information, where information is based on what the receiver wants to know, then virtually no signaling system will be completely honest [41]. Deceit occurs when the signaler’s fitness increases at the cost of the receiver’s fitness [30].
Recommended publications
  • Does the Handicap Principle Explain the Evolution of Dimorphic Ornaments?
    Animal Behaviour xxx (2018) e1ee4 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Animal Behaviour journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/anbehav Forum Does the handicap principle explain the evolution of dimorphic ornaments? * Szabolcs Szamad o a, , Dustin J. Penn b a RECENS ‘Lendület’ Research Group, MTA Centre for Social Science, Budapest, Hungary b Konrad Lorenz Institute of Ethology, Department of Integrative Biology and Evolution, University of Veterinary Medicine, Vienna, Austria article info Article history: Received 12 July 2017 Initial acceptance 5 October 2017 Final acceptance 22 November 2017 Available online xxx MS. number: 17-00560 Keywords: Handicap principle Honest signalling Dimorphic ornaments Bimodal fitness Playing-the-field Many species are sexually dimorphic and, interestingly, males in concluding that it provides an explanation for the evolution of male some species are dimorphic themselves: some males develop dimorphisms. weapons and ornaments, whereas others express rudimentary or- There are many versions and interpretations of the handicap naments or none at all (horned beetles, Onthophagus taurus: Emlen, hypothesis, but it is unclear which version was implemented for the Lavine, & Ewen-Campen, 2007; Moczek & Emlen, 2000; bluegill authors' new model. This omission makes it impossible to under- sunfish, Lepomis macrochirus: Dominey, 1980; Gross & Charnov, stand the novelty of the model and how it succeeds in explaining 1980; ruffs, Philomachus pugnax: Lank, Smith, Hanotte, Burke, & male dimorphisms or why others failed. The authors cite the Cooke, 1995; for a review see Simpson, Sword, & Lo, 2011). Males original handicap hypothesis (Zahavi, 1975), and yet this version can be so extremely dimorphic that the morphs have been mis- does not work (reviewed in Kirkpatrick 1986).
    [Show full text]
  • CONTENT2 2.Pages
    DRAFT PROPOSITIONAL CONTENT in SIGNALS (for Special Issue Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science C ) Brian Skyrms and Jeffrey A. Barrett Introduction We all think that humans are animals, that human language is a sophisticated form of animal signaling, and that it arises spontaneously due to natural processes. From a naturalistic perspective, what is fundamental is what is common to signaling throughout the biological world -- the transfer of information. As Fred Dretske put it in 1981, "In the beginning was information, the word came later." There is a practice of signaling with information transfer that settles into some sort of a pattern, and eventually what we call meaning or propositional content crystallizes out. The place to start is to study the evolution, biological or cultural, of information transfer in its most simple and tractable forms. But once this is done, naturalists need first to move to evolution of more complex forms of information transfer. And then to an account of the crystallization process that gives us meaning. There often two kinds of information in the same signal: (1) information about the state of the world that the signaler observes (2) information about the act that the receiver will perform on receiving the signal. [See Millikan (1984), Harms (2004), Skyrms (2010)]. The meaning that crystalizes out about the states, we will single out here as propositional meaning. The simplest account that comes to mind will not quite do, as a general account of this kind of meaning, although it may be close to the mark in especially favorable situations.
    [Show full text]
  • Information Games and Robust Trading Mechanisms
    Information Games and Robust Trading Mechanisms Gabriel Carroll, Stanford University [email protected] October 3, 2017 Abstract Agents about to engage in economic transactions may take costly actions to influence their own or others’ information: costly signaling, information acquisition, hard evidence disclosure, and so forth. We study the problem of optimally designing a mechanism to be robust to all such activities, here termed information games. The designer cares about welfare, and explicitly takes the costs incurred in information games into account. We adopt a simple bilateral trade model as a case study. Any trading mechanism is evaluated by the expected welfare, net of information game costs, that it guarantees in the worst case across all possible games. Dominant- strategy mechanisms are natural candidates for the optimum, since there is never any incentive to manipulate information. We find that for some parameter values, a dominant-strategy mechanism is indeed optimal; for others, the optimum is a non- dominant-strategy mechanism, in which one party chooses which of two trading prices to offer. Thanks to (in random order) Parag Pathak, Daron Acemoglu, Rohit Lamba, Laura Doval, Mohammad Akbarpour, Alex Wolitzky, Fuhito Kojima, Philipp Strack, Iv´an Werning, Takuro Yamashita, Juuso Toikka, and Glenn Ellison, as well as seminar participants at Michigan, Yale, Northwestern, CUHK, and NUS, for helpful comments and discussions. Dan Walton provided valuable research assistance. 1 Introduction A large portion of theoretical work in mechanism design, especially in the world of market design applications, has focused on dominant-strategy (or strategyproof ) mechanisms — 1 those in which each agent is asked for her preferences, and it is always in her best interest to report them truthfully, no matter what other agents are doing.
    [Show full text]
  • Pheromones and Animal Behaviour Communication by Smell and Taste
    Pheromones and Animal Behaviour Communication by Smell and Taste Tristram D. Wyatt University of Oxford published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org © Cambridge University Press 2003 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2003 Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typeface Swift 9/13pt System QuarkXPress® [tb] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Wyatt, Tristram D., 1956– Pheromones and animal behaviour: communication by smell and taste / Tristram D. Wyatt. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references (p. ). ISBN 0 521 48068 X – ISBN 0 521 48526 6 (pb.) 1. Animal communication. 2. Pheromones. 3. Chemical senses. I. Title. QL776 .W93 2002 591.59 – dc21 2002024628 ISBN 0 521 48068 X hardback ISBN 0 521 48526 6 paperback The publisher has used its best endeavours to ensure that the URLs for external web sites re- ferred to in this book are correct and active at time of going to press. However, the publisher has no responsibility for the web sites and can make no guarantee that a site will remain live or that the content is or will remain appropriate.
    [Show full text]
  • Sexual Selection and the Evolution of Animal Signals. In: Squire LR (Ed.) Encyclopedia of Neuroscience, Volume 8, Pp
    This article was originally published in the Encyclopedia of Neuroscience published by Elsevier, and the attached copy is provided by Elsevier for the author's benefit and for the benefit of the author's institution, for non- commercial research and educational use including without limitation use in instruction at your institution, sending it to specific colleagues who you know, and providing a copy to your institution’s administrator. All other uses, reproduction and distribution, including without limitation commercial reprints, selling or licensing copies or access, or posting on open internet sites, your personal or institution’s website or repository, are prohibited. For exceptions, permission may be sought for such use through Elsevier's permissions site at: http://www.elsevier.com/locate/permissionusematerial Searcy W A and Nowicki S (2009) Sexual Selection and the Evolution of Animal Signals. In: Squire LR (ed.) Encyclopedia of Neuroscience, volume 8, pp. 769- 776. Oxford: Academic Press. Author's personal copy Sexual Selection and the Evolution of Animal Signals 769 Sexual Selection and the Evolution of Animal Signals W A Searcy , University of Miami, Coral Gables, FL, such as mammals and birds, with extensive parental USA care. Largely as a result of these parental investment S Nowicki , Duke University, Durham, NC, USA patterns, females typically have lower maximal rates ã 2009 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. of reproduction. Thus sexual biases in both parental investment and maximal rates of reproduction predict the predominance of female choice. Introduction Many of the greats of evolutionary biology who followed Darwin were skeptical of the importance of Darwin defined sexual selection in On the Origin of female choice as a selective mechanism.
    [Show full text]
  • Taking Turns: Bridging the Gap Between Human and Animal Communication
    This is a repository copy of Taking turns: bridging the gap between human and animal communication. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/150857/ Version: Published Version Article: Pika, Simone, Wilkinson, Ray, Kendrick, Kobin H. orcid.org/0000-0002-6656-1439 et al. (1 more author) (2018) Taking turns: bridging the gap between human and animal communication. Proceedings of the royal society b-Biological sciences. 20180598. ISSN 1471-2954 https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2018.0598 Reuse This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) licence. This licence allows you to distribute, remix, tweak, and build upon the work, even commercially, as long as you credit the authors for the original work. More information and the full terms of the licence here: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Downloaded from http://rspb.royalsocietypublishing.org/ on July 30, 2018 Taking turns: bridging the gap between rspb.royalsocietypublishing.org human and animal communication Simone Pika1,2, Ray Wilkinson3, Kobin H. Kendrick4 and Sonja C. Vernes5,6 1Department of Primatology, Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology, Deutscher Platz 6, 04103 Leipzig, Germany Review 2Department of Comparative Biocognition, Institute of Cognitive Science, University of Osnabru¨ck, Osnabru¨ck, Germany Cite this article: Pika S, Wilkinson R, 3Department of Human Communication Sciences, University of Sheffield, Sheffield, UK Kendrick KH, Vernes SC.
    [Show full text]
  • 1160 Animal Signals and the Overlooked Costs Of
    Evolution, 59(5), 2005, pp. 1160±1161 ANIMAL SIGNALS AND THE OVERLOOKED COSTS OF EFFICACY1 MICHAEL J. RYAN2 AND MOLLY E. CUMMINGS Section of Integrative Biology C0930, University of Texas, Austin, Texas 78712 2E-mail: [email protected] Received March 22, 2005. costly; handicaps can make it more costly, but lack of hand- The most striking aspects of many animals are signals. icap does not make it cost free. This book concentrates on Thus one might expect Animal Signals by John Maynard strategic costs, but offers some tantalizing discussions of ef- Smith and David Harper to discuss the detailed biology of ®cacy costs, which the authors suggest are underappreciated. this half of the communication dyad. Not so. Instead, they We second that notion but feel it is not strong enough. concentrate on a single question, why signals are reliable, The most basic ef®cacy costs of signaling are incurred in and emphasize one methodology to its solution: game theory. creating its morphology, behavior, and neural circuitry. In ad- Although not embracing the entire biology of signaling, the book grapples with a continuing problem. dition, some animals scour the environment to obtain their Signals evolved to communicate information and manip- signals; bowerbirds steal decorations for their bowers (Borgia ulate receivers to the signaler's bene®t. Similarly, the re- and Mueller 1992), and some moths sequester plant alkaloids ceiver's response to signals is under selection to promote its for the ¯occulent showers they bestow upon females (Conner ®tness. The issue at hand is the con¯ict between signal and et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind and Deception
    PS452 Intelligent Behaviour Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind and Deception Maxwell J Roberts Department of Psychology University of Essex www.tubemapcentral.com version date: 19/11/2019 Part 3: Intelligent Behaviour in Animals • Lecture 7: Animal Intelligence Tests Measuring animal cognitive capacity • Learning and logic between species • The ubiquitous g factor • Lecture 8: Tools, Puzzles, Beliefs, and Intentions Complex interactions with objects • Natural tool use • Understanding the properties of objects 2 Part 3: Intelligent Behaviour in Animals • Lecture 9: Animal Communication Mindless signals or deliberate acts • Natural communication • Taught language in the laboratory • Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind and Deception In search of proto-modules • Animal (lack of) awareness of other minds • Social versus non-social origins of general intelligence 3 Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind & Deception • 10.1 Theory of Mind: A Tool for Deception • Theory of Mind and modularity • Evidence for Theory of Mind in animals • 10.2 The Special Case of Deception • Deception in the wild • Primate deception in the wild • Deception in the laboratory • Return of the crows • 10.3 Evaluation: Theory of Mind & Deception 4 Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind & Deception • 10.4 The Origins of General Intelligence? • 10.5 Animal, Human, and Machine Intelligence 5 10.1 Theory of Mind: A Tool for Deception • Theory of Mind: A popular concept in child psychology • The assumption that other beings are intentional systems and have mental states, including: Knowledge
    [Show full text]
  • Diploid Models of the Handicap Principle
    Heredity 60 (1988) 283—293 The Genetical Society of Great Britain Received 22June1987 Diploid models of the handicap principle I. P. M. Tomlinson Department of Genetics, Downing Street, Cambridge CB2 3EH, U.K. "Fisherian" models of sexual selection by female choice assume that females prefer male characters which are initially advantageous or neutral; character and preference then spread through the population. Once female preference has evolved to a higher frequency, the male character can become more extreme and disadvantageous by the action of some force such as the "super-normal stimulus". By contrast, the "handicap principle" of sexual selection proposes that females should prefer more extreme, disadvantaged males: males who survive the disadvantage of the "handicap" must be fitter in other respects. Previous models of various forms of the "handicap principle" have shown that it is very unlikely to work as an alternative to the "Fisherian process". However, recent haploid models have shown that a "condition-dependent handicap" might evolve. Diploid models show that the "condition-dependent handicap" model does not work. Models of "handicaps" operating together with the "Fisherian process" are also presented. It is inferred that "Fisherian" models are more likely than "handicap" models to account for the evolution of male sexual ornaments, although a "handicap" mechanism may aid the operation of the "Fisherian process". INTRODUCTION Darwin (1871) and analysed by Fisher (1930): preferred males tend to find mates more easily, Darwin(1871) saw that the males of many species mate earlier in the breeding season in more favour- were often brightly coloured or possessed complex able conditions and therefore gain a natural selec- secondary adornments; females on the other hand tive advantage.
    [Show full text]
  • Human–Animal Communication*
    AN46CH21-Kulick ARI 26 September 2017 7:48 Annual Review of Anthropology Human–Animal Communication∗ Don Kulick Department of Cultural Anthropology and Ethnology, Uppsala University, 751 26, Uppsala, Sweden; email: [email protected] ANNUAL REVIEWS Further Click here to view this article's online features: t%PXOMPBEmHVSFTBT115TMJEFT t/BWJHBUFMJOLFESFGFSFODFT t%PXOMPBEDJUBUJPOT t&YQMPSFSFMBUFEBSUJDMFT t4FBSDILFZXPSET Annu. Rev. Anthropol. 2017. 46:357–78 Keywords First published as a Review in Advance on August animal studies, animal communicators, animal training, ape language, 7, 2017 companion species, ethics, pets The Annual Review of Anthropology is online at by [email protected] on 11/02/17. For personal use only. anthro.annualreviews.org Abstract https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-anthro-102116- Since the demise in the 1980s of research by psychologists who attempted 041723 Annu. Rev. Anthropol. 2017.46:357-378. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org to teach human language to apes, a range of other perspectives has arisen Copyright c 2017 by Annual Reviews. ⃝ that explore how humans can communicate with animals and what the pos- All rights reserved sibility of such communication means. Sociologists interested in symbolic ∗This article is part of a special theme on interactionism, anthropologists writing about ontology, equestrian and ca- Human–Animal Interaction. For a list of other articles in this theme, see http://www. nine trainers, people with autism who say they understand animals because annualreviews.org/doi/full/10.1146/annurev- they think like animals, and a ragbag of sundry New Age women who claim an-46-themes to be able to converse with animals through telepathy have started discussing human–animal communication in ways that recast the whole point of think- ing about it.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Introduction
    © Copyright, Princeton University Press. No part of this book may be distributed, posted, or reproduced in any form by digital or mechanical means without prior written permission of the publisher. 1 Introduction Whether signals are reliable or deceptive has been a central question in the study of animal communication in recent years. The crux of the issue is whether animal signals are honest, in the sense of conveying reliable informa­ tion from signaler to receiver, or deceitful, in the sense of conveying unreliable information, the falsity of which somehow benefits the signaler. This issue arises in a variety of contexts. When a male courts a female, do his signals honestly convey his quality relative to other males? Or does he exaggerate his quality in order to win over females that would otherwise choose some other male? When one animal signals aggressively in a contest over a resource, does the signaler honestly convey its likelihood of attack? Or does the signaler exaggerate that likelihood in order to intimidate competitors that would other­ wise defeat him? The question of reliability versus deceit arises even in interac­ tions that, on the face of things, seem to be predominantly cooperative. When an offspring begs for food from its parents, does it honestly convey its level of need? Or does the offspring exaggerate its need in order to get more food than the parents would otherwise provide? The issue of reliability and deceit in animal communication resonates with humanobservers for a variety of reasons. One is that the occurrence of deceit is fraught with moral implications.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1612.07182V2 [Cs.CL] 5 Mar 2017 in a World Populated by Other Agents
    Under review as a conference paper at ICLR 2017 MULTI-AGENT COOPERATION AND THE EMERGENCE OF (NATURAL)LANGUAGE Angeliki Lazaridou1∗, Alexander Peysakhovich2, Marco Baroni2;3 1Google DeepMind, 2Facebook AI Research, 3University of Trento [email protected], falexpeys,[email protected] ABSTRACT The current mainstream approach to train natural language systems is to expose them to large amounts of text. This passive learning is problematic if we are in- terested in developing interactive machines, such as conversational agents. We propose a framework for language learning that relies on multi-agent communi- cation. We study this learning in the context of referential games. In these games, a sender and a receiver see a pair of images. The sender is told one of them is the target and is allowed to send a message from a fixed, arbitary vocabulary to the receiver. The receiver must rely on this message to identify the target. Thus, the agents develop their own language interactively out of the need to communi- cate. We show that two networks with simple configurations are able to learn to coordinate in the referential game. We further explore how to make changes to the game environment to cause the “word meanings” induced in the game to better re- flect intuitive semantic properties of the images. In addition, we present a simple strategy for grounding the agents’ code into natural language. Both of these are necessary steps towards developing machines that are able to communicate with humans productively. 1 INTRODUCTION I tried to break it to him gently [...] the only way to learn an unknown language is to interact with a native speaker [...] asking questions, holding a conversation, that sort of thing [...] If you want to learn the aliens’ language, someone [...] will have to talk with an alien.
    [Show full text]