Space and Time in Loop Quantum Gravity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Space and Time in Loop Quantum Gravity Space and Time in Loop Quantum Gravity Carlo Rovelli CPT, Aix-Marseille Universit´e,Universit´ede Toulon, CNRS, F-13288 Marseille, France. (Dated: February 8, 2018) Quantum gravity is expected to require modifications of the notions of space and time. I discuss and clarify how this happens in Loop Quantum Gravity. [Written for the volume \Beyond Spacetime: The Philosophical Foundations of Quantum Gravity" edited by Baptiste Le Biha, Keizo Matsubara and Christian Wuthrich.] I. INTRODUCTION to in his Physics, Descartes founds on `contiguity', and so on. In mathematics it is studied by topol- Newton's success sharpened our understanding of the ogy. This is a very general notion of space, equally nature of space and time in the XVII century. Einstein's present in ancient, Cartesian, Newtonian, and rel- special and general relativity improved this understand- ativistic physics. ing in the XX century. Quantum gravity is expected to This notion of space is equally present in LQG. In take a step further, deepening our understanding of space LQG, in fact, we can say that something is in a cer- and time, by grasping of the implications for space and tain location with respect to something else. A par- time of the quantum nature of the physical world. ticle can be at the same location as a certain quan- The best way to see what happens to space and time tum of gravity. We can also say that two quanta are when their quantum traits cannot be disregarded is to adjacent. The network of adjacency of the elemen- look how this actually happens in a concrete theory of tary quanta of the gravitational field is captured by quantum gravity. Loop Quantum Gravity (LQG) [1{7] is the graph of a spin network (see Appendix). The among the few current theories sufficiently developed to links of the graph are the elementary adjacency re- provide a complete and clear-cut answer to this question. lations. Spin networks describe relative spacial ar- Here I discuss the role(s) that space and time play in rangements of dynamical entities: the elementary LQG and the version of these notions required to make quanta. sense of a quantum gravitational world. For a detailed discussion, see the first part of the book [1]. A brief sum- Newtonian space: In the XVII century, in the Prin- mary of the structure of LQG is given in the Appendix, cipia, Newton introduced a distinction between two for the reader unfamiliar with this theory. notions of space [9]. The first, which he called the \common" one, is the one illustrated in the previous item. The second, which he called the II. SPACE \true" one, is what has been later called Newto- nian space. Newtonian space is not a relation be- Confusion about the nature of space | even more so tween objects: it is assumed by Newton to exist for time| originates from failing to recognise that these also in the absence of objects. It is an entity with are stratified, multi-layered concepts. They are charged no dynamics, with a metric structure: that of a 3d with a multiplicity of attributes and there is no agree- Euclidean manifold. It is postulated by Newton on ment on a terminology to designate spacial or temporal the basis of suggestions from ancient Democritean physics, and is essential for his theoretical construc- notions lacking same of these attributes. When we say 1 `space' or `time' we indicate different things in different tion. Special relativity modifies this ontology only marginally, merging Newtonian space and time into arXiv:1802.02382v1 [gr-qc] 7 Feb 2018 contexts. The only route to clarify the role of space and time in Minkowski's spacetime. quantum gravity is to ask what we mean in general when In quantum gravity, Minkowski spacetime and we say `space' or `time' [8]. There are distinct answers to hence Newtonian space appear only as an approxi- this question; each defines a different notion of `space' or mations, as we shall see below. They have no role `time'. Let's disentangle them. I start with space, and at all in the foundation of the theory. move to time, which is more complex, later on. Relational space: `Space' is the relation we use when we locate things. We talk about space when we ask 1 During the XIX century, certain awkward aspects of this Newto- \Where is Andorra?" and answer \Between Spain nian hypostasis led to the development of the notion of `physical and France". Location is established in relation to reference system': the idea that Newtonian space captures the properties of preferred systems of bodies not subjected to forces. something else (Andorra is located by Spain and This is correct but already presupposes the essential ingredient: France). Used in this sense `space' is a relation a fixed metric space, permitting to locate things with respect to between things. It does not require metric conno- distant references bodies. Thus the notion of reference system tations. It is the notion of space Aristoteles refers does not add much to the novelty of the Newtonian ontology. 2 General relativistic space: Our understanding of the days". Location of events is given with respect to actual physical nature of Newtonian space (and something else. (We shall meet after three sun- Minkowski spacetime) underwent a radical sharp- rises.) Used in this sense time is a relation between ening with the discovery of General Relativity events. This is the notion Aristoteles refers to in (GR). The empirical success of GR |slowly cumu- his Physics2, and so on. It is a very general no- lated for a century and recently booming| adds tion of time, equally present in ancient, Cartesian, much credibility to the effectiveness of this step. Newtonian, and relativistic physics. What GR shows is that Newtonian space is indeed When used in this wide sense, `time' is definitely an entity as Newton postulated, but is not non- present in LQG. In LQG we can say that some- dynamical as Newton assumed. It is a dynamical thing happens when something else happens. For entity, very much akin to the electromagnetic field: instance, a particle is emitted when two quanta of a gravitational field. Therefore in GR there are gravity join. Also, we can say that two events are two distinct spacial notions. The first is the sim- temporally adjacent. A network of temporal adja- ple fact that dynamical entities (all entities in the cency of elementary processes of the gravitational theory are dynamical) are localized with respect to field is captured by the spinfoams (see Appendix). one another (\This black hole is inside this globu- lar cluster"). The second is a left-over habit from Newtonian time: In the Principia, Newton distin- Newtonian logic: the habit of calling `space' (or guished two notions of time. The first, which he `spacetime') one particular dynamical entity: the called the \common" one, is the one in the previous gravitational field. There is nothing wrong in do- item. The second, which he called the \true" one, ing so, provided that the substantial difference be- is what has been later called Newtonian time. New- tween these three notions of space (order of local- tonian time is assumed to be “flowing uniformly", ization, Newtonian non-dynamical space, gravita- even when nothing happens, with no influence from tional field) is clear. events, and to have a metric structure: we can say LQG treats space (in this sense) precisely as GR when two time intervals have equal duration. Spe- does: a dynamical entity that behaves as Newto- cial relativity modifies the Newtonian ontology only nian space in a certain approximation. However, in marginally, merging Newtonian space and time into LQG this dynamical entity has the usual additional Minkowski spacetime. properties of quantum entities. These are three: (i) In LQG (Minkowsky spacetime and hence) Newto- Granularity. The quantum electromagnetic field nian time appears only as an approximation. It has has granular properties: photons. For the same no role at all in the foundation of the theory. reason, the quantum gravitational field has granu- lar properties: the elementary quanta represented General relativistic time: What GR has shown is by the nodes of a spin network. Photon states form that Newtonian time is indeed (part of) an entity a basis in the Hilbert state of quantum electromag- as Newton postulated, but this entity is not non- netism like spin network states form a basis in the dynamical as Newton assumed. Rather, it is an Hilbert space of LQG. (ii) Indeterminism. The dy- aspect of a dynamical field, the gravitational field. namics of the `quanta of space' (like that of pho- What the reading T of a common clock tracks, for tons) is probabilistic. (iii) Relationalism. Quan- instance, is a function of the gravitational field gµν , tum gravity inherits all features of quantum me- Z p µ ν chanics including the weirdest. Quantum theory T = gµν dx dx : (1) (in its most common interpretation) describes in- teractions among systems where properties become In GR, therefore, there are two distinct kinds of actual. So happens in LQG to the gravitational temporal notions. The first is the simple fact that field: the theory describes how it interacts with all events are localized with respect to one another other systems (and with itself) and how its prop- (\This gravity wave has been emitted when the two erties become actual in interactions. More on this neutron stars have merged", \The binary pulsar after we discuss time. emits seven hundred pulses during an orbit"). The second is a left-over habit from Newtonian logic: the habit of calling `time' (in `spacetime') aspects III.
Recommended publications
  • Putting Space in Place: Philosophical Topography and Relational
    Putting Space in Place: Philosophical Topography and Relational Geography 1. Introduction: Space and Geography Although a discipline often characterized as essentially spatial in its orientation, geography seems only very seldom to have devoted significant attention to exploring the concept of space itself. Indeed, the shift in geographical thinking over the last fifty years or so towards a mode of thinking that takes space as bound up with social and political process actually serves to reinforce, rather than rectify, the neglect of space itself within geographical theorizing. A similar point could also be made with respect to many of the theorists on whom geography draws. Both Foucault and Lefebvre, for instance, while they emphasize the inextricability of the spatial and the socio-political, nevertheless rely upon a notion of space that remains essentially unarticulated and largely unexplored. Just what the phenomenon of space might be that is at issue in the various spatialities and spatializations that appear in their work thus remains obscure (in spite of Lefebvre’s own claims) – and it is no less so in most of the other thinkers who have been taken up within recent geographic discourse or in the geographical appropriations of their thought. Thus from Deleuze through to Sloterdijk spatial ideas and images are constantly in play, and yet what is at issue in the very idea of space and the spatial is almost never directly addressed. In this latter respect, any criticism of geographical theory for its relative neglect of space cannot be restricted to geography alone – with some notable exceptions, very few thinkers, no matter what the discipline, have given serious attention to the phenomenon of space, any more than to the phenomena of time and of place, but have tended instead to deal with various forms or modes of space – to spatialities rather than to space as such.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Spa E and Time
    Topicsin Philosophy of Physics: Philosophy of Space and Time Philosophy 426 T 1:10-4:10pm, 210 Miller Hall J. North ([email protected]) We will focus on the following question. Do space and time exist in addition to material objects? In modern terms: does spacetime exist? We will look at his- torical and contemporary arguments from physics and philosophy. One theme will be that it is not clear what the traditional debate amounts to, nor whether it is a substantive dispute. Our aim is to better understand this dispute and how it could be decided in favor of one side or the other. Time and student interest permitting, we may discuss related issues in the philosophy of space and time. Readings Required books, available at the bookstore (https://tinyurl.com/F18-Course-Material-730426) and on reserve at the Alexander Library undergraduate circulation desk: John Earman, World Enough and Space-Time Robert Geroch, General Relativity from A to B Nick Huggett, Space from Zeno to Einstein Tim Maudlin, Philosophy of Physics: Space and Time Hans Reichenbach, The Philosophy of Space and Time Optional books (at the bookstore and on reserve at Alexander): Michael Friedman, Foundations of Space-Time Theories Lawrence Sklar, Space, Time, and Spacetime All other readings are available at the course website (address given out in class) Prerequisites I will assume that you have had some high school physics (for instance, F = ma should be familiar to you), but this needn’t be at your ngertips. I assume no background in philosophy, although one previous course is recommended.
    [Show full text]
  • Space, Time, and Ontology in Classical and Quantum Gravity
    WHATEVER IS NEVER AND NOWHERE IS NOT: SPACE, TIME, AND ONTOLOGY IN CLASSICAL AND QUANTUM GRAVITY by Gordon Belot B.Sc., University of Toronto, 1991 M.Sc., University of Toronto, 1993 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of University of Pittsburgh in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 1996 John Earman Joseph Camp Adolf Grünbaum John Norton Carlo Rovelli ii WHATEVER IS NEVER AND NOWHERE IS NOT: SPACE, TIME, AND ONTOLOGY IN CLASSICAL AND QUANTUM GRAVITY Gordon Belot, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 1996 Substantivalists claim that spacetime enjoys an existence analogous to that of material bodies, while relationalists seek to reduce spacetime to sets of possible spatiotemporal relations. The resulting debate has been central to the philosophy of space and time since the Scientific Revolution. Recently, many philosophers of physics have turned away from the debate, claiming that it is no longer of any relevance to physics. At the same time, there has been renewed interest in the debate among physicists working on quantum gravity, who claim that the conceptual problems which they face are intimately related to interpretative questions concerning general relativity (GR). My goal is to show that the physicists are correct—there is a close relationship between the interpretative issues of classical and quantum gravity. In the first part of the dissertation I challenge the received view that substantivalism has a commanding advantage over relationalism on grounds internal to GR. I argue that this view is based on a misconception of the relationships between realism and substantivalism, and between empiricism and relationalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading List in Philosophy of Spacetime and Symmetry David Wallace, June 2018
    Reading list in Philosophy of Spacetime and Symmetry David Wallace, June 2018 1. Introduction .............................................................................................................................................. 2 2. Math and Physics resources ...................................................................................................................... 4 3. The substantivalist/relationist debate ...................................................................................................... 6 4. The Hole Argument ................................................................................................................................. 10 5. General Covariance, Background Independence, and the Meaning of Coordinates.............................. 13 6. Dynamical vs geometrical approaches to spacetime theories ............................................................... 15 7. Spacetime structure in pre-relativistic physics ....................................................................................... 17 8. Spacetime topics in quantum gravity ..................................................................................................... 18 9. Philosophy of Symmetry ......................................................................................................................... 19 10. Other topics in special and general relativity ....................................................................................... 22 A note on electronic resources When I include a book
    [Show full text]
  • SPACE AS a KEY WORD David Harvey Paper for Marx and Philosophy Conference, 29 May 2004, Institute of Education, London
    1 SPACE AS A KEY WORD David Harvey Paper for Marx and Philosophy Conference, 29 May 2004, Institute of Education, London If Raymond Williams were contemplating the entries for his celebrated text on Keywords today, he would surely have included the word “space.” He may well have included it in that short list of concepts, such as “culture” and “nature”, to be listed as “one of the most complicated words in our language.” How, then, can the range of meanings that attach to the word “space” be expanded upon and clarified without losing ourselves in some labyrinth (itself an interesting spatial metaphor) of complications? Space is, of course, one of those words that frequently elicits modification. The complications perhaps arise more out of the modifications (which all too frequently get omitted in the telling or the writing) rather than out of any inherent complexity of the notion of space itself. When, for example, we write of “material”, “metaphorical”, “liminal”, “personal”, “social” or “psychic” space (just to take a few examples) we thereby indicate a considerable diversity of contexts which so inflect matters as to seem to render the meaning of space itself entirely contingent upon the context. Similarly, when we designate its range of applications in terms such as spaces of fear, of play, of cosmology, of dreams, of anger, of particle physics, of capital, of geopolitical tension, of hope, of memory, or of ecological interaction (again, just to indicate a few of a seemingly infinite range of potential sites of deployment of the term) then we seem to be saying that the arena of application defines something so special about the meaning of space as to render any general consideration of its properties a hopeless task.
    [Show full text]
  • Space and Time As Containers of the “Physical Material World” with Some Conceptual and Epistemological Consequences in Modern Physics
    Space and Time as Containers of the “Physical Material World” with some Conceptual and Epistemological Consequences in Modern Physics Mauricio Mondragon * & Luis Lopez a aInstituto Tecnológico y de Estudios Superiores de Occidente , Departamento de Matemáticas y Física , Periférico Manuel Gómez Morín 8585, C. P. 45090, Tlaquepaque, Jalisco, Mexico Abstract A particular science is not only defined by its object of study, but also by the point of view and method under which it considers that same object. Taking space and time as an illustrative example, our main aim here is to bring out an almost forgotten conception of science found in many doctrines that seek mainly—but not only—a qualitative and synthetic knowledge rather than, as in modern physics, for example, a quantitative and analytic knowledge. The latter point of view is found to be very limited and fragmented, leaving outside many scientific questions and answers, while the former opens up the way to valuable and interesting answers to those and many other questions. In particular, we argue that the conception of space and time as containers of, respectively, bodies and events clarify many conceptual and epistemological issues of modern science related to the physical material world. Key words : Space; time; spacetime; probability; corporeal world; possible; compossible; doctrines from the West and the East; synthetic knowledge; analytic knowledge I. Introduction About 60 years ago, Erwin Schrödinger said that the “...image of material reality is today more unsettled and uncertain than it has been for a long time. We know a great many interesting details; every week we learn new ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Mechanics
    Relationism Rehabilitated? I: Classical Mechanics Oliver Pooley∗ Exeter College, University of Oxford Harvey R. Brown† Sub-Faculty of Philosophy, University of Oxford April 10, 2001 Abstract The implications for the substantivalist–relationist controversy of Bar- bour and Bertotti’s successful implementation of a Machian approach to dynamics are investigated. It is argued that in the context of Newtonian mechanics the Machian framework provides a genuinely relational interpre- tation of dynamics and that it is more explanatory than the conventional, substantival interpretation. In a companion paper (Pooley 2001), the im- plications of the Machian approach for the interpretation of relativistic physics are explored. 1 Introduction A brief summary of the recent history of the substantivalist–relationist debate might go as follows: The late 1960s and the 1970s saw the rise of the modern form of substantival- ism. With the demise of logical empiricism, and with the rise of scientific realism, the spacetime manifold started to be seen as a respectable entity. It appeared integral to our best physical theories and thus we were justified in postulating its existence (Earman 1970, Stein 1970). Relationist1 critics of realistically con- strued spacetime, while able to offer a clear account of the relational content of substantivalist models (at least in the prerelativistic context), were exposed as ∗e-mail: [email protected]. †e-mail: [email protected] 1Here and throughout, we conform to the standard practice of using “relationist” to stand for someone who denies that space, or spacetime, is a basic entity, ontologically on a par with matter. An alternative use of the word also has some currency according to which “relationism” is roughly synonymous with “anti-haecceitism”.
    [Show full text]
  • From Prespace Metaphysics to Discrete Quantum Mechanics
    The Computable Universe: From Prespace Metaphysics to Discrete Quantum Mechanics Martin Leckey B.Sc. (Hons.), M.A. Submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Philosophy Department, Monash University October 1997 arXiv:1807.10826v1 [quant-ph] 30 Jun 2018 Contents Contents iii List of Figures vi Abstract vii Statement of Originality ix Acknowledgments xi 1 Introduction 1 2 Spaces, Causation, and Reality 7 2.1 Introduction . 7 2.2 Substantivalism, relationism, and the property view . 8 2.3 Spaces and perception . 8 2.4 Spaces and reality . 11 2.5 Spaces as property spaces . 12 2.6 Spaces and causation . 23 2.7 Space-time and causation . 26 2.8 Properties and laws . 26 2.9 Spaces and reduction . 28 2.10 Configuration space, phase space and logical space . 30 2.11 Quantum mechanics . 32 2.12 The wave function and reality . 36 2.13 Conclusion . 39 3 Prespace and Cellular Automata 43 3.1 Introduction . 43 3.2 Building the universe . 46 3.2.a UM1|Solipsistic dualism . 46 3.2.b UM2|Strong dualism . 47 iii Contents 3.2.c UM3|Materialism . 48 3.3 Cellular automata and discrete physics . 49 3.4 Functionalism . 52 3.5 Position and causation . 54 3.6 Mechanism . 56 3.7 Monism . 58 3.8 Spinoza . 58 3.9 Leibniz . 59 3.10 Kant . 60 3.11 Holism . 60 3.12 Relativity . 61 3.13 Computational heuristic principle . 62 3.14 Weak dualism . 64 3.15 Theism . 64 3.16 Conclusion . 67 4 Quantum Mechanics and Discrete Physics 69 4.1 Introduction .
    [Show full text]
  • Substantival Vs. Relational Space(-Time) 1: Pre-Relativistic Theories Pt
    Substantival vs. relational space(-time) 1: Pre-relativistic theories Pt. II Philosophy of Physics Lecture 1, 16 January 2015, Adam Caulton ([email protected]) 1 Newton's three laws From Newton's The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (1687): 1. Every body perseveres in its state of rest or of uniform motion in a right line unless it is compelled to change that state by forces impressed thereon. (, existence of inertial frames) 2. The alteration of motion is ever proportional to the motive force impressed and is made in the direction of the right line in which that force is impressed. (, Fi = miai) 3. To every action there is always opposed an equal reaction: or the mutual actions of two bodies upon each other are always equal and directed to contrary parts. P (, Fi = j fij and fij = −fji ) conservation of linear momentum) 2 Absolute vs. relative; substantival vs. relational Absolutism vs. relativism about velocity: • Absolutism about velocity. The velocity of any material body (e.g. point particles) is a property of that body that makes no reference to any other material body. (Monadic property or relation to spatial points?) • Relativism about velocity. Velocity is an irreducible relation between material bodies. We can formulate absolutism and relativism about any other mechanical quantity: e.g. loca- tion, acceleration, etc. • Relativism about all motion. All motion is a relation between material bodies. Substantivalism vs. relationism about space (we'll consider space-time later): • Substantivalism about space. Spatial points/regions are real objects, which persist over time. The geometrical properties (& relations) of material bodies are parasitic on the geometrical properties (& relations) of these spatial points/regions.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 DESCARTES, SPACE-TIME, and RELATIONAL MOTION* Edward Slowik†‡ Department of Philosophy, University of Alaska Fairbanks
    1 DESCARTES, SPACE-TIME, AND RELATIONAL MOTION* Edward Slowik†‡ Department of Philosophy, University of Alaska Fairbanks ________________________________________________________________________ * Received March 1997, Revised October 1997 † I would like to thank Mark Wilson and Calvin Normore for helpful discussions, and two anonymous referees from the Philosophy of Science for comments on earlier version of this paper. ‡ Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, University of Alaska Fairbanks, 405 Fine Arts Complex, P. O. Box 755740, Fairbanks, AK, 99775-5740. 2 ABSTRACT This paper examines Descartes' problematic relational theory of motion, especially when viewed within the context of his dynamics, the Cartesian natural laws. The work of various commentators on Cartesian motion is also surveyed, with particular emphasis placed upon the recent important texts of D. Garber and D. Des Chene. In contrast to the methodology of most previous interpretations, however, this essay employs a modern "space-time" approach to the problem. By this means, the role of dynamics in Descartes' theory, which has often been neglected in favor of kinematic factors, is shown to be central to finding a solution to the puzzle of Cartesian motion. 3 1. Introduction. There are few topics in Cartesian natural philosophy more problematic than Descartes' hypotheses on space and motion, a treatment that has often been classified as "relationalist"; i.e., which rejects that space and motion are, or require, anything over and above the relations among bodies. From Descartes' time down to our own, his alleged advocacy of a relational hypothesis has prompted a number of negative critical responses and lengthy denunciations, both from the "absolutists" who deny relationalism, such as Newton, and from fellow relationalists committed to his general, if not exact, goals, such as Leibniz.
    [Show full text]
  • Motion in Leibniz's Physics and Metaphysics
    Chapter 4 Motion in Leibniz’s Physics and Metaphysics 4.1 Introduction Leibniz’s mechanics was, as we shall see, a theory of elastic collisions, not formulated like Huygens’ in terms of rules explicitly covering every possible combination of relative masses and velocities, but in terms of three conservation principles, including (e↵ectively) the conservation of momentum and kinetic energy. That is, he proposed what we now call (ironically enough) ‘Newtonian’ (or ‘classical’) elastic collision theory. While such a theory is, for instance, vital to the foundations of the kinetic theory of gases, it is not applicable to systems – like gravitational systems – in which fields of force are present. Thus, Leibniz’s mechanical principles never led to developments of the order of Newton’s in the Principia (additionally, he hamstrung their application by embedding them in a baroque philosophical system). All the same, I wish to demonstrate, against the tendency of many modern readers, that Leibniz’s responses to the Newtonians must be understood in the context of his theory of motion, not in terms of Newtonian mechanics. As we shall see, his problems lie primarily in his own physics, not in misunderstanding Newton’s. Our ultimate goals are to understand Leibniz’s views on relativity (kinematic and dynamical) and ‘absolute’ quantities of motion (i.e., those that cannot be understood in terms of the relative motions of bodies alone). Of course, such an analysis will require that we also study his metaphysics, concerning matter and space especially, and his mechanics; these will be the topics of the next four sections.
    [Show full text]
  • Container Space and Relational Space
    10 CONTAINER SPACE AND RELATIONAL SPACE Leibniz's attack on Newton's conception of space and Einstein's special theory of relativity are the two important starting points for modern philosophical discussions of space. The theories of Leibniz and Einstein contradict Newton's ideas but in different ways. Newtonian space is a complex notion, it is possible to criticize it in some respects and defend it in others. In order to capture the category of space its different constituent aspects must be carefully distinguished. In post-Newtonian discussions they have all too often been run together in an unfortunate manner. Leibniz's criticism is mainly that Newtonian space is not relational. The specifically Einsteinian criticism has been that space has a relativistic metric. There is also a third kind of criticism, associated with Ernst Mach, which should be kept clearly apart from the other two. It claims that what is wrong with Newtonian space is that it is not relative. Newtonian space is neither relational, nor relative, nor relativistic. It is absolute, but 'absolute' means one thing when contrasted with 'relational', something else when contrasted with 'relative' and something else again when contrasted with 'relativistic'. I shall therefore avoid this ambiguous term as far as possible and instead use 'container space', 'non-relative space', and 'non-relativistic space' respectively. I shall argue that these distinctions are related as in Figure 10.1.1 The important thing about this figure is that it shows that the category 'container space' subsumes the different concepts of space which are or have been, proposed within physical science.
    [Show full text]