The Metaphysics of Space-Time Substantivalism: a Methodological Study of the Structure of Space-Time in the Context of General Relativity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Metaphysics of Space-Time Substantivalism: a Methodological Study of the Structure of Space-Time in the Context of General Relativity i The Metaphysics of Space-time Substantivalism: A Methodological Study of the Structure of Space-time in the Context of General Relativity Sarah K. Grant A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy at the University of Otago, Dunedin, New Zealand ii Abstract This thesis explores methodological approaches to studying substantivalism in metaphysics and the philosophy of science. My primary aim is to show that it is only when these two disciplines come together, that we can hope to make progress with respect to discovering the true nature of the structure of space-time. I begin by looking at Leibniz’s argument that substantivalism entails the possibility of qualitatively indiscernible worlds, which differ only with respect to how the material world is located in space-time. I explore whether there is anything more to the basis of this contention than non-naturalistic appeals to common sense and a priori metaphysical principles. I argue that there is, as a modern-day interpretation of Leibniz’s argument shows that substantivalism renders GTR indeterministic. I consider whether this problematic indeterminism arises as a result of a particular conception of substantivalism, or whether it follows from all formulations of substantivalism consistent with GTR, and to what extent it is our additional metaphysical commitments that are motivating the problem. iii Acknowledgements I would like to thank my primary supervisor Dr Heather Dyke for her comments, suggestions, criticisms and patience, and for providing models of what metaphysics can and should be. I would also like to thank my original supervisor at the University of Leeds, Professor Robin le Poidevin, without whose friendship, support and enthusiasm this thesis would not have been possible, and also Professor Alan Musgrave for his detailed comments on my work. I would like to thank my family for supporting me both financially and emotionally throughout graduate school, and my pup Cruiser for providing companionship, love and comfort during my writing up. A special thank you to my sister Emma and partner Kris, for their unwavering confidence in times of difficulty, and for always being there for me, regardless of distance. iv Table of Contents Chapter 1: Introduction 1 1.1 A Naturalistic Methodology 5 1.2 Thesis Outline 10 Chapter 2: Theories of Events 14 2.2 A Property Exemplification Account of Events 16 Identity Conditions for Events 16 An Argument from Common Sense 20 The Essentiality of Spatio-temporal Location 24 Modifying Kim’s Account 27 2.3 Davidson’s Theories of Events 30 A Casual Account of Event Identity 30 A Spatio-temporal Criterion 34 Conclusion 39 Chapter 3: Individuation and Discernibility in Space-time Metaphysics 41 3.1 The Argument from Indiscernibility 43 A Comment on Methodology 44 The Various Commitments of PII 46 Leibniz’s Argument 51 Primitive Identity for Space-Time Points 56 3.2 Forbes Against Primitive Identity 58 Forbes’s Argument 59 Theoretical Considerations 66 Conclusion 68 Chapter 4: On Explanatory Adequacy 70 4.1 The PSR and Necessitarianism 72 Leibniz’s Rationalist Model of Explanation 73 Avoiding Necessitarianism 79 4.2 The Legitimacy of Metaphysical Questions 84 The Brute Fact View 85 Sufficient Explanations 90 Conclusion 100 Chapter 5: Indeterminism and The Hole Argument 103 v 5.1 Space-time in General Relativity 104 An Illustration of the Mathematical Devices Used 105 The Hole Argument 108 Leibnizian Equivalence 110 5.2 The Threat of Determinism 113 The Failure of Determinism 114 The Threat from A Priori Metaphysics 117 5.3 An Alternative Conception of Determinism 119 A Lewisian Account 120 An Analysis of Thought-Experiments 123 Conclusion 126 Chapter 6: A Defence Against the Hole Argument 128 6.1 Is Manifold Substantivalism the Default View? 130 The Container Metaphor 131 A Cost/Benefit Analysis 133 The Linguistic Strategy 137 6.2 Manifold-plus-Metric Substantivalism 140 The Hole Argument Revisited 141 A Fine-Grained Ontological Distinction 145 6.3 Super-substantivalism 149 Varieties of Super-Substantivalism 150 Ontological Parsimony 153 Metaphysical Assumptions 156 The Modal Argument 161 Conclusion 164 Chapter 7: Denying Primitive Identity 166 7.1 Metric-field Substantivalism 167 Relationalism in Disguise 167 Responding to the Hole Argument 173 The Cost of Denying Primitive Identity 175 Conclusion 176 Concluding Remarks 178 Methodological Considerations 181 Summary and Future Directions 182 Bibliography 185 vi “Can philosophers really contribute to the project of reconciling general relativity and quantum field theory? Or is this a technical business best left to the experts? General relativity and quantum field theory are based on some profound insights about the nature of reality. These insights are crystallized in the form of mathematics, but there is a limit to how much progress we can make by just playing around with this mathematics. We need to go back to the insights behind general relativity and quantum field theory, learn to hold them together in our minds, and dare to imagine a world more strange, more beautiful, but ultimately more reasonable than our current theories of it. For this daunting task, philosophical reflection is bound to be of help. Baez (2001, 177) Chap. 1 - Introduction 1 Chapter 1 Introduction “Clearly our first problem must be to define the issue, since nothing is more prolific of fruitless controversy than an ambiguous question” Russell (“Determinism and Physics”) Space-time substantivalism is a metaphysical theory. It is the thesis that space-time is something real: it is a robust entity with determinate properties which can exist independently of the material objects and events which may ‘occupy’ it.1 A consequence of this is that the whole material world might have existed just as it is, but shifted over in space three feet in any given direction. This means that the world could have been different in infinitely many ways, without those differences being discernible. To put the same point in the language of possible worlds, there are an infinite number of qualitatively identical possible worlds.2 Such worlds constitute a distinction without a difference: they do not differ in any empirically detectable way. We can reinterpret this as a problem regarding the spatio-temporal location of events: if substantivalism is true, then the whole history of events in the universe might have been located differently in space-time. This is an age-old Leibnizian problem, which is raised in the Correspondence between Leibniz and Clarke against Newtonian absolute space (H.G. Alexander: 1998). But is it a legitimate problem for substantivalists? Substantivalism is currently the most plausible theory of space-time consistent with the general theory of relativity (GTR). According to GTR, space-time affects and is affected by the presence and activity of matter. Gravitational energy, for example, can be transmitted at light speed in the form of gravitational waves between material 1 I shall later argue that the occupation relation is a mischaracterization of the relationship between space-time and material objects and events. 2 Throughout this thesis I intend to remain neutral between different accounts of possible worlds. I will therefore employ the language of Lewisian Modal Realism for the sake of clarity, but everything I say about concrete possible worlds can be translated into talk about abstract possible worlds. My talk of concrete possible worlds should therefore not be understood as committing me (or the substantivalist) to Modal Realism. Chap. 1 - Introduction 2 bodies and regions of matter-free space-time. This strongly suggests that space-time is substantival in nature, since it is extremely difficult for relationalism to explain the possibility of matter-free regions of space-time. As Dainton (2001) remarks, “How can something that can behave like this be anything other than substantival in nature?” (302) Relationalists also have difficulty explaining the odd behaviour of material objects as they move through regions of space with variable curvature (non-Euclidean holes) (Dainton: 2001). In such regions, objects alter their shape in a way that is not explained in terms of other forces, for example gravity or magnetism. Whereas substantivalists explain this behaviour straightforwardly in terms of alterations in the shape of space, relationalists have no such solution, since only material objects and spatial relations exist. The relationalist must therefore account for this odd behaviour in terms of relations between material bodies and other material bodies (object-object relations). However, given the various possible configurations of other material bodies, the laws involved in such an explanation, although possible, will be incredibly complex.3 While neither of these examples rules out relationalism altogether, it is clear that relationalism cannot compete with substantivalism in explaining natural phenomena in GTR. As Hoefer (1996, 1-2) remarks: “For this reason, just about everyone who writes on GTR… is broadly speaking, a substantivalist.” In light of this, to what extent should we take Leibniz’s musings seriously? When faced with strong (and observable) physical evidence in support of substantivalism, what weight should we assign Leibniz’s purely a priori metaphysical considerations? This is an instance of a much broader question regarding the overall value and significance of metaphysical inquiry: what can metaphysics contribute with respect to the pursuit of objective truth about reality, and in particular, about space- time? The question of the contribution of metaphysics to the pursuit of truth is a highly contentious issue, and is one of the central themes of this thesis. I argue that metaphysics can and does make a significant contribution to discovering the objective nature of reality, but metaphysics and science should not be pursued independently of one another, after all, their subject matter is the same. However, if metaphysics is to 3 For a further discussion of object-object relations in non-Euclidean space, see Nerlich (1991).
Recommended publications
  • Putting Space in Place: Philosophical Topography and Relational
    Putting Space in Place: Philosophical Topography and Relational Geography 1. Introduction: Space and Geography Although a discipline often characterized as essentially spatial in its orientation, geography seems only very seldom to have devoted significant attention to exploring the concept of space itself. Indeed, the shift in geographical thinking over the last fifty years or so towards a mode of thinking that takes space as bound up with social and political process actually serves to reinforce, rather than rectify, the neglect of space itself within geographical theorizing. A similar point could also be made with respect to many of the theorists on whom geography draws. Both Foucault and Lefebvre, for instance, while they emphasize the inextricability of the spatial and the socio-political, nevertheless rely upon a notion of space that remains essentially unarticulated and largely unexplored. Just what the phenomenon of space might be that is at issue in the various spatialities and spatializations that appear in their work thus remains obscure (in spite of Lefebvre’s own claims) – and it is no less so in most of the other thinkers who have been taken up within recent geographic discourse or in the geographical appropriations of their thought. Thus from Deleuze through to Sloterdijk spatial ideas and images are constantly in play, and yet what is at issue in the very idea of space and the spatial is almost never directly addressed. In this latter respect, any criticism of geographical theory for its relative neglect of space cannot be restricted to geography alone – with some notable exceptions, very few thinkers, no matter what the discipline, have given serious attention to the phenomenon of space, any more than to the phenomena of time and of place, but have tended instead to deal with various forms or modes of space – to spatialities rather than to space as such.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Spa E and Time
    Topicsin Philosophy of Physics: Philosophy of Space and Time Philosophy 426 T 1:10-4:10pm, 210 Miller Hall J. North ([email protected]) We will focus on the following question. Do space and time exist in addition to material objects? In modern terms: does spacetime exist? We will look at his- torical and contemporary arguments from physics and philosophy. One theme will be that it is not clear what the traditional debate amounts to, nor whether it is a substantive dispute. Our aim is to better understand this dispute and how it could be decided in favor of one side or the other. Time and student interest permitting, we may discuss related issues in the philosophy of space and time. Readings Required books, available at the bookstore (https://tinyurl.com/F18-Course-Material-730426) and on reserve at the Alexander Library undergraduate circulation desk: John Earman, World Enough and Space-Time Robert Geroch, General Relativity from A to B Nick Huggett, Space from Zeno to Einstein Tim Maudlin, Philosophy of Physics: Space and Time Hans Reichenbach, The Philosophy of Space and Time Optional books (at the bookstore and on reserve at Alexander): Michael Friedman, Foundations of Space-Time Theories Lawrence Sklar, Space, Time, and Spacetime All other readings are available at the course website (address given out in class) Prerequisites I will assume that you have had some high school physics (for instance, F = ma should be familiar to you), but this needn’t be at your ngertips. I assume no background in philosophy, although one previous course is recommended.
    [Show full text]
  • Space, Time, and Ontology in Classical and Quantum Gravity
    WHATEVER IS NEVER AND NOWHERE IS NOT: SPACE, TIME, AND ONTOLOGY IN CLASSICAL AND QUANTUM GRAVITY by Gordon Belot B.Sc., University of Toronto, 1991 M.Sc., University of Toronto, 1993 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of University of Pittsburgh in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 1996 John Earman Joseph Camp Adolf Grünbaum John Norton Carlo Rovelli ii WHATEVER IS NEVER AND NOWHERE IS NOT: SPACE, TIME, AND ONTOLOGY IN CLASSICAL AND QUANTUM GRAVITY Gordon Belot, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 1996 Substantivalists claim that spacetime enjoys an existence analogous to that of material bodies, while relationalists seek to reduce spacetime to sets of possible spatiotemporal relations. The resulting debate has been central to the philosophy of space and time since the Scientific Revolution. Recently, many philosophers of physics have turned away from the debate, claiming that it is no longer of any relevance to physics. At the same time, there has been renewed interest in the debate among physicists working on quantum gravity, who claim that the conceptual problems which they face are intimately related to interpretative questions concerning general relativity (GR). My goal is to show that the physicists are correct—there is a close relationship between the interpretative issues of classical and quantum gravity. In the first part of the dissertation I challenge the received view that substantivalism has a commanding advantage over relationalism on grounds internal to GR. I argue that this view is based on a misconception of the relationships between realism and substantivalism, and between empiricism and relationalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading List in Philosophy of Spacetime and Symmetry David Wallace, June 2018
    Reading list in Philosophy of Spacetime and Symmetry David Wallace, June 2018 1. Introduction .............................................................................................................................................. 2 2. Math and Physics resources ...................................................................................................................... 4 3. The substantivalist/relationist debate ...................................................................................................... 6 4. The Hole Argument ................................................................................................................................. 10 5. General Covariance, Background Independence, and the Meaning of Coordinates.............................. 13 6. Dynamical vs geometrical approaches to spacetime theories ............................................................... 15 7. Spacetime structure in pre-relativistic physics ....................................................................................... 17 8. Spacetime topics in quantum gravity ..................................................................................................... 18 9. Philosophy of Symmetry ......................................................................................................................... 19 10. Other topics in special and general relativity ....................................................................................... 22 A note on electronic resources When I include a book
    [Show full text]
  • SPACE AS a KEY WORD David Harvey Paper for Marx and Philosophy Conference, 29 May 2004, Institute of Education, London
    1 SPACE AS A KEY WORD David Harvey Paper for Marx and Philosophy Conference, 29 May 2004, Institute of Education, London If Raymond Williams were contemplating the entries for his celebrated text on Keywords today, he would surely have included the word “space.” He may well have included it in that short list of concepts, such as “culture” and “nature”, to be listed as “one of the most complicated words in our language.” How, then, can the range of meanings that attach to the word “space” be expanded upon and clarified without losing ourselves in some labyrinth (itself an interesting spatial metaphor) of complications? Space is, of course, one of those words that frequently elicits modification. The complications perhaps arise more out of the modifications (which all too frequently get omitted in the telling or the writing) rather than out of any inherent complexity of the notion of space itself. When, for example, we write of “material”, “metaphorical”, “liminal”, “personal”, “social” or “psychic” space (just to take a few examples) we thereby indicate a considerable diversity of contexts which so inflect matters as to seem to render the meaning of space itself entirely contingent upon the context. Similarly, when we designate its range of applications in terms such as spaces of fear, of play, of cosmology, of dreams, of anger, of particle physics, of capital, of geopolitical tension, of hope, of memory, or of ecological interaction (again, just to indicate a few of a seemingly infinite range of potential sites of deployment of the term) then we seem to be saying that the arena of application defines something so special about the meaning of space as to render any general consideration of its properties a hopeless task.
    [Show full text]
  • Space and Time As Containers of the “Physical Material World” with Some Conceptual and Epistemological Consequences in Modern Physics
    Space and Time as Containers of the “Physical Material World” with some Conceptual and Epistemological Consequences in Modern Physics Mauricio Mondragon * & Luis Lopez a aInstituto Tecnológico y de Estudios Superiores de Occidente , Departamento de Matemáticas y Física , Periférico Manuel Gómez Morín 8585, C. P. 45090, Tlaquepaque, Jalisco, Mexico Abstract A particular science is not only defined by its object of study, but also by the point of view and method under which it considers that same object. Taking space and time as an illustrative example, our main aim here is to bring out an almost forgotten conception of science found in many doctrines that seek mainly—but not only—a qualitative and synthetic knowledge rather than, as in modern physics, for example, a quantitative and analytic knowledge. The latter point of view is found to be very limited and fragmented, leaving outside many scientific questions and answers, while the former opens up the way to valuable and interesting answers to those and many other questions. In particular, we argue that the conception of space and time as containers of, respectively, bodies and events clarify many conceptual and epistemological issues of modern science related to the physical material world. Key words : Space; time; spacetime; probability; corporeal world; possible; compossible; doctrines from the West and the East; synthetic knowledge; analytic knowledge I. Introduction About 60 years ago, Erwin Schrödinger said that the “...image of material reality is today more unsettled and uncertain than it has been for a long time. We know a great many interesting details; every week we learn new ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Mechanics
    Relationism Rehabilitated? I: Classical Mechanics Oliver Pooley∗ Exeter College, University of Oxford Harvey R. Brown† Sub-Faculty of Philosophy, University of Oxford April 10, 2001 Abstract The implications for the substantivalist–relationist controversy of Bar- bour and Bertotti’s successful implementation of a Machian approach to dynamics are investigated. It is argued that in the context of Newtonian mechanics the Machian framework provides a genuinely relational interpre- tation of dynamics and that it is more explanatory than the conventional, substantival interpretation. In a companion paper (Pooley 2001), the im- plications of the Machian approach for the interpretation of relativistic physics are explored. 1 Introduction A brief summary of the recent history of the substantivalist–relationist debate might go as follows: The late 1960s and the 1970s saw the rise of the modern form of substantival- ism. With the demise of logical empiricism, and with the rise of scientific realism, the spacetime manifold started to be seen as a respectable entity. It appeared integral to our best physical theories and thus we were justified in postulating its existence (Earman 1970, Stein 1970). Relationist1 critics of realistically con- strued spacetime, while able to offer a clear account of the relational content of substantivalist models (at least in the prerelativistic context), were exposed as ∗e-mail: [email protected]. †e-mail: [email protected] 1Here and throughout, we conform to the standard practice of using “relationist” to stand for someone who denies that space, or spacetime, is a basic entity, ontologically on a par with matter. An alternative use of the word also has some currency according to which “relationism” is roughly synonymous with “anti-haecceitism”.
    [Show full text]
  • From Prespace Metaphysics to Discrete Quantum Mechanics
    The Computable Universe: From Prespace Metaphysics to Discrete Quantum Mechanics Martin Leckey B.Sc. (Hons.), M.A. Submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Philosophy Department, Monash University October 1997 arXiv:1807.10826v1 [quant-ph] 30 Jun 2018 Contents Contents iii List of Figures vi Abstract vii Statement of Originality ix Acknowledgments xi 1 Introduction 1 2 Spaces, Causation, and Reality 7 2.1 Introduction . 7 2.2 Substantivalism, relationism, and the property view . 8 2.3 Spaces and perception . 8 2.4 Spaces and reality . 11 2.5 Spaces as property spaces . 12 2.6 Spaces and causation . 23 2.7 Space-time and causation . 26 2.8 Properties and laws . 26 2.9 Spaces and reduction . 28 2.10 Configuration space, phase space and logical space . 30 2.11 Quantum mechanics . 32 2.12 The wave function and reality . 36 2.13 Conclusion . 39 3 Prespace and Cellular Automata 43 3.1 Introduction . 43 3.2 Building the universe . 46 3.2.a UM1|Solipsistic dualism . 46 3.2.b UM2|Strong dualism . 47 iii Contents 3.2.c UM3|Materialism . 48 3.3 Cellular automata and discrete physics . 49 3.4 Functionalism . 52 3.5 Position and causation . 54 3.6 Mechanism . 56 3.7 Monism . 58 3.8 Spinoza . 58 3.9 Leibniz . 59 3.10 Kant . 60 3.11 Holism . 60 3.12 Relativity . 61 3.13 Computational heuristic principle . 62 3.14 Weak dualism . 64 3.15 Theism . 64 3.16 Conclusion . 67 4 Quantum Mechanics and Discrete Physics 69 4.1 Introduction .
    [Show full text]
  • Substantival Vs. Relational Space(-Time) 1: Pre-Relativistic Theories Pt
    Substantival vs. relational space(-time) 1: Pre-relativistic theories Pt. II Philosophy of Physics Lecture 1, 16 January 2015, Adam Caulton ([email protected]) 1 Newton's three laws From Newton's The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (1687): 1. Every body perseveres in its state of rest or of uniform motion in a right line unless it is compelled to change that state by forces impressed thereon. (, existence of inertial frames) 2. The alteration of motion is ever proportional to the motive force impressed and is made in the direction of the right line in which that force is impressed. (, Fi = miai) 3. To every action there is always opposed an equal reaction: or the mutual actions of two bodies upon each other are always equal and directed to contrary parts. P (, Fi = j fij and fij = −fji ) conservation of linear momentum) 2 Absolute vs. relative; substantival vs. relational Absolutism vs. relativism about velocity: • Absolutism about velocity. The velocity of any material body (e.g. point particles) is a property of that body that makes no reference to any other material body. (Monadic property or relation to spatial points?) • Relativism about velocity. Velocity is an irreducible relation between material bodies. We can formulate absolutism and relativism about any other mechanical quantity: e.g. loca- tion, acceleration, etc. • Relativism about all motion. All motion is a relation between material bodies. Substantivalism vs. relationism about space (we'll consider space-time later): • Substantivalism about space. Spatial points/regions are real objects, which persist over time. The geometrical properties (& relations) of material bodies are parasitic on the geometrical properties (& relations) of these spatial points/regions.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 DESCARTES, SPACE-TIME, and RELATIONAL MOTION* Edward Slowik†‡ Department of Philosophy, University of Alaska Fairbanks
    1 DESCARTES, SPACE-TIME, AND RELATIONAL MOTION* Edward Slowik†‡ Department of Philosophy, University of Alaska Fairbanks ________________________________________________________________________ * Received March 1997, Revised October 1997 † I would like to thank Mark Wilson and Calvin Normore for helpful discussions, and two anonymous referees from the Philosophy of Science for comments on earlier version of this paper. ‡ Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, University of Alaska Fairbanks, 405 Fine Arts Complex, P. O. Box 755740, Fairbanks, AK, 99775-5740. 2 ABSTRACT This paper examines Descartes' problematic relational theory of motion, especially when viewed within the context of his dynamics, the Cartesian natural laws. The work of various commentators on Cartesian motion is also surveyed, with particular emphasis placed upon the recent important texts of D. Garber and D. Des Chene. In contrast to the methodology of most previous interpretations, however, this essay employs a modern "space-time" approach to the problem. By this means, the role of dynamics in Descartes' theory, which has often been neglected in favor of kinematic factors, is shown to be central to finding a solution to the puzzle of Cartesian motion. 3 1. Introduction. There are few topics in Cartesian natural philosophy more problematic than Descartes' hypotheses on space and motion, a treatment that has often been classified as "relationalist"; i.e., which rejects that space and motion are, or require, anything over and above the relations among bodies. From Descartes' time down to our own, his alleged advocacy of a relational hypothesis has prompted a number of negative critical responses and lengthy denunciations, both from the "absolutists" who deny relationalism, such as Newton, and from fellow relationalists committed to his general, if not exact, goals, such as Leibniz.
    [Show full text]
  • Motion in Leibniz's Physics and Metaphysics
    Chapter 4 Motion in Leibniz’s Physics and Metaphysics 4.1 Introduction Leibniz’s mechanics was, as we shall see, a theory of elastic collisions, not formulated like Huygens’ in terms of rules explicitly covering every possible combination of relative masses and velocities, but in terms of three conservation principles, including (e↵ectively) the conservation of momentum and kinetic energy. That is, he proposed what we now call (ironically enough) ‘Newtonian’ (or ‘classical’) elastic collision theory. While such a theory is, for instance, vital to the foundations of the kinetic theory of gases, it is not applicable to systems – like gravitational systems – in which fields of force are present. Thus, Leibniz’s mechanical principles never led to developments of the order of Newton’s in the Principia (additionally, he hamstrung their application by embedding them in a baroque philosophical system). All the same, I wish to demonstrate, against the tendency of many modern readers, that Leibniz’s responses to the Newtonians must be understood in the context of his theory of motion, not in terms of Newtonian mechanics. As we shall see, his problems lie primarily in his own physics, not in misunderstanding Newton’s. Our ultimate goals are to understand Leibniz’s views on relativity (kinematic and dynamical) and ‘absolute’ quantities of motion (i.e., those that cannot be understood in terms of the relative motions of bodies alone). Of course, such an analysis will require that we also study his metaphysics, concerning matter and space especially, and his mechanics; these will be the topics of the next four sections.
    [Show full text]
  • Container Space and Relational Space
    10 CONTAINER SPACE AND RELATIONAL SPACE Leibniz's attack on Newton's conception of space and Einstein's special theory of relativity are the two important starting points for modern philosophical discussions of space. The theories of Leibniz and Einstein contradict Newton's ideas but in different ways. Newtonian space is a complex notion, it is possible to criticize it in some respects and defend it in others. In order to capture the category of space its different constituent aspects must be carefully distinguished. In post-Newtonian discussions they have all too often been run together in an unfortunate manner. Leibniz's criticism is mainly that Newtonian space is not relational. The specifically Einsteinian criticism has been that space has a relativistic metric. There is also a third kind of criticism, associated with Ernst Mach, which should be kept clearly apart from the other two. It claims that what is wrong with Newtonian space is that it is not relative. Newtonian space is neither relational, nor relative, nor relativistic. It is absolute, but 'absolute' means one thing when contrasted with 'relational', something else when contrasted with 'relative' and something else again when contrasted with 'relativistic'. I shall therefore avoid this ambiguous term as far as possible and instead use 'container space', 'non-relative space', and 'non-relativistic space' respectively. I shall argue that these distinctions are related as in Figure 10.1.1 The important thing about this figure is that it shows that the category 'container space' subsumes the different concepts of space which are or have been, proposed within physical science.
    [Show full text]