<<

Downloaded by guest on October 1, 2021 nyafamn fteaimo hienml dependent choice–namely of of subsets axiom all which the in is of and (DC)—holds which which fragment choice in of (ZF) a famous theory only most explosion Zermelo–Fraenkel indepen- an the of off model for among set Solovay’s 1960s results, forcing early the independence of in of theory method set in the proofs dence of Ellentuck introduction the Cohen’s in measurability Baire of on terms topology in analytic Ram- the property and characterized Borel 1974 sey in that (4) shown Ellentuck finally was and it Ramsey, 3, and sets 2 all refs. not that implies choice or www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1906183116 is there if Ramsey, is ply a families mad Schrittesser no David implies property Ramsey The oee nte16sad17s nti ae,w eoeby denote we paper, this In 1970s. S and dis- 1960s were [X the theorem in this covered of generalizations infinite-dimensional set infinite an or if is that there says combinatorics then in theorem Ramsey of infinite subsets all of set the lemma Zorn’s from choice). of easily axiom follows the families (equivalently, mad infinite of and Finite tence numbers family. even e.g., disjoint exist, of almost to set an seen of easily are subset families proper mad family a disjoint not almost an is is which family”) (“mad family disjoint almost if that R-Unif + numbers DC natural + ZF theory the this in answer 2). maxi- we working (Definition infinite paper affirmative, this no the In have are families. in (mad) there sets disjoint that “all almost infinite- implies mal statement forcing. property” combinatorial families, of Ramsey the method disjoint the whether Cohen’s almost asked and maximal He theory, of Ramsey theory dimensional set rial I theory set property Ramsey complicated more addi- to of relative number families a ideals. mad Borel announce about we results Furthermore, is tional set. family “large” mad a purported relation on a equivalence theory, to the ergodic associated under in invariant roots certain use a natural We theory: that its set descriptive has invariant and dynamics, which topological Mathias idea to an back exploits goes Mathias, that D. positive problem a R. gives long-standing [A. This a principles. to choice weak solution only dis- with Zermelo–Fraenkel theory almost in proved set maximal is of implication infinite The subsets families. no 2019) (mad) infinite are 10, joint April of there review collections then for property, (received all 2019 Ramsey if 30, July that approved and show CA, We Berkeley, California, of University Ribet, A. Kenneth by Edited Denmark Copenhagen, utG Kurt ⊆ ewe ifrn da nmteais h combinato- the connection mathematics: a in established ideas (1) different Mathias 3 paper, between seminal his n ocretwt hs eeomnsi asytheory, Ramsey in developments these with Concurrent ie set a Given the (on family disjoint almost An notions: key the recall us Let ] [B [ ∞ B [ N] ] ] h e fcutbyifiiesbesof subsets infinite countably of set the dlRsac etr nvriyo ina 00Ven,Asra and Austria; Vienna, 1090 Vienna, of University Center, Research odel k ∞ ¨ x ∞ ∩ , ∩ | ewl a that say will we , y S oe ideals Borel S A ∈ = [N] = oiae yaqeto fErd of question a by Motivated ∅. X hneither then , | Erd ∅. ∞ aia lotdson families disjoint almost maximal . safamily a is N) n.Mt.Logic Math. Ann. n aua number natural a and a,1 sadRd hwdta h xo of axiom the that showed Rado and os ˝ n se T Asger and X O ihexactly with B S stesto d ubr.Teexis- The numbers. odd of set the is x ∈ a h asypoet,o sim- or property, Ramsey the has B = [N] S A ⊆ y ⊆ ∞ N or fifiiesbesof subsets infinite of 2 911(97] h proof The (1977)]. 59–111 12, ornquist [N] ¨ uhta either that such uhta either that such x k ∞ ∩ E {E lmns h classical The elements. k y r asy ae,in Later, Ramsey. are 0 ∈ n hsi constant is thus and sfiie maximal A finite. is , X let N, b,1,2 O | oevr given Moreover, . nain descriptive invariant where }, R sadRado, and os ˝ r Lebesgue are S [X ⊆ N [B ] S [N] k aethe have [B E N ⊆ ] denote ∞ ] ∞ k sthe is [N] such ⊆ ⊆ are k S S , b eateto ahmtclSine,Uiest fCpnae,2100 Copenhagen, of University Sciences, Mathematical of Department property, a ese ut aiy nti ae egv h following the give 1. we Theorem paper this this In question. and Mathias’ easily. model, to Solovay’s quite solution positive in seen holds it be that can a enough for weak is 10 which ref. 2 (Definition also sets positive see sey 9; ref. in been exis- family had the She- “med” showed that proof. Borel and they simpler questions a particular, Horowitz related of in of families. tence years; the number mad over proved that a no formulated 8 them solved ref. are also among in there lah results, authors implies further present AD the of with number work a Solovay’s joint is Bakke can of independently, in which and families construction 7 Haga ref. mad cardinal, the in Norwood no in and inaccessible Neeman are ingredient model. ref. an there crucial in which using a showed in otherwise without Shelah ZF achieved of and model be Horowitz a in after, that 2014 shortly in 6 solved and forc- was and 5, 1 families Question ref. mad renaissance. a in experienced research ing the suddenly to when A answer recently, families? negative mad a give infinite would no 2 are 1. question question there mad to sets that infinite answer all follow there positive If Are it 1) 2) does time: model? sey, the Solovay’s at in answer families to him in allow not role central a play in forcing, that Mathias proof. is show this to to connection what used their introducing sets he and by all which this model forcing, did Mathias Solovay’s late as Mathias the known fami- families. in now Erd mad already “Happy to to circulated his forcing and which in connected of who Mathias, (drafts 1960s), was (1) It paper lies” measurable. Baire and 2 1 the under Published Submission. y Direct PNAS a is article This interest.y of conflict paper. no y the declare wrote authors and The research performed A.T. and D.S. contributions: Author owo orsodnemyb drse.Eal [email protected] Email: addressed. be may correspondence whom To work.y this to equally contributed A.T. and D.S. le a xs.Ti ovsapolmta a enoe in open been has that fam- problem mad 1960s. a late infinite the solves no since This mathematics then as exist. sets, known can all ilies for principle assumption property natural a Ramsey a regularity, that the with combinatorial shows choice paper of universal axiom This of the choice. conse- replace of we paradoxical axiom if many the with called to mathematics, quences, due fundamen- of only a principle exist from tal to arising known methods mathe- are nonconstructive modern families, indirect, in mad called structures matics, combinatorial infinite Certain Significance ednt yRUi h rnil fuiomzto nRam- on uniformization of principle the R-Unif by denote We very until questions these on progress modest only was There did methods his which questions, central 2 asked Mathias hnteeaen nnt a families. mad infinite no are there then F+D R-Unif + DC + (ZF NSlicense.y PNAS S ⊆ .RUi sawa hieprinciple, choice weak a is R-Unif ). [N] ∞ ) r asy a families, Mad Ramsey. are falst aeteRamsey the have sets all If sadRd’ question Rado’s and os ˝ NSLts Articles Latest PNAS S ⊆ [N] V ∞ = r Ram- are L(R) | f5 of 1 +

MATHEMATICS We note that Theorem 1 implies the main results of refs. dom(s) ⊆ dom(t) and s(i) = t(i) for all i ∈ dom(s); we will write 5 and 7. s ⊥ t (“s and t are incompatible”) if s 6⊆ t and t 6⊆ s. < Theorem 1 may seem all the more surprising given another For each s ∈ N N, let recent result of Horowitz and Shelah (11), who show that for a N variety of measurability notions including the Lebesgue , Ns = {f ∈ N :(∀i ∈ dom(s)) f (i) = s(i)}. “all sets are measurable” is compatible with the existence of an infinite mad family.

Notation and Background Definitions Definition 2. In this section we summarize the background needed for the 1) For Polish spaces X , Y , and R ⊆ X × Y , we say that R has proof. A good general reference for all of the background full projection on X , if for every x ∈ X there is y ∈ Y such that needed is ref. 12. A comprehensive treatise on modern, infinitary (x, y) ∈ R. Ramsey theory is ref. 13. 2) Let X , Y be Polish spaces, let Z ⊆ X , and let R ⊆ X × Y be a set with full projection. A function ϑ : Z → Y is said to A. Descriptive . A topological space X is called Pol- uniformize R on Z if for all x ∈ Z we have (x, ϑ(x)) ∈ R. ish if it is separable and admits a complete metric that 3) The Ramsey uniformization principle, abbreviated R-Unif, is the ∞ induces the topology. In this paper we will be working with following statement: For all Y Polish and all R ⊆ [N] × Y 2N = {0, 1}N N with full projection, there is an infinite set A ⊆ N and a function the and N (with the product topol- ∞ ∞ ogy, taking {0, 1} and N discrete) and subspaces of these ϑ :[A] → Y which uniformizes R on [A] . spaces. Recall the following key notion from descriptive set That the Ramsey uniformization principle holds in Solovay’s theory: model follows by the argument given in ref. 14, section 1.12, p. 46 with Random forcing replaced everywhere by Mathias forcing. Definition 1. A subset A ⊆ X of a Polish space X is analytic if there is a continuous f : Y → X from a Polish space Y to X such that D. Invariance under Finite Changes. The last ingredient for the A = ran(f ). proof is the notion of “E0 invariance.” Since NN maps continuously onto any Polish space, we have that A ⊆ X is analytic iff there is a continuous f : NN → X Definition 3. such that ran(f ) = A. We will use this characterization as our ∞ 1) E0 is the equivalence relation defined on [ ] by definition of the analytic set below. N For the proof of Theorem 1 we need the following combi- n xE0y ⇐⇒|x4y| < ∞. natorial description of the topology on NN. We denote by N

2 of 5 | www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1906183116 Schrittesser and Tornquist¨ Downloaded by guest on October 1, 2021 Downloaded by guest on October 1, 2021 all 3. Subclaim 65. p. of top T that scniuu on continuous is some find can every we for Then claim. the fies all are there on if only all for z ucam2. Subclaim 1. Subclaim that and 12 ref. of sense the in map identifying By xacniuu function continuous a fix iuu.Then tinuous. replacing all for hr is there | anClaim. Main theorem: the prove will oethat Note (a nraigfnto uhthat such function increasing o nifiiesbe fa lmn of element an of subset infinite an now crtesradT and Schrittesser infi- Dedekind are sets that infinite assume all may that We implies nite). DC that use + we DC + ZF that show assumptions: property.” Ramsey following the have the sets “all + under R-Unif work We 1 Theorem of Proof suefrsmlct htif that simplicity for assume replacing possibly by that Moreover, shows imal. diagonalization easy an otherwise since ˆ ˜ z ˜ (k n rmnwo efix we on now From Proof: Proof: Proof: For ups h li sfle hnb asyuniformization Ramsey by Then false. is claim the Suppose ealta when that Recall Let Let ∩ o all for y y [W 0 ) 0 0 y n z + [N] ∈N ∈ ∈ | x 0 7→ z i (a z ⊆ A < | i 0 ] a z ˜ f f ∈ W ∞ ∞ ˆ = ) ∈ ∈ \ z ˆ ∈ n xdaoe en o each for define above, fixed 0 (N (N T ∞. ( s z ∩ tflosthat follows It N. W ) . Suppose [W By A [N] ups no Suppose k T → N | 0 n z 0 ∈ z [N] ˜ ∈ ups hr are there Suppose h function The t s z f hr is There , ∈N +i z 0 0 u sntmaximal. not is scntn on constant is 0 s ∩ (x m [N] hr is There ∞ 2 rpsto 2 Proposition [W iha nnt ustof subset infinite an with ) ) 0 (k ] ornquist = ¨ 1 ∞ ) ∞ N B P a and and and (ˆ let , 0 ea netv euneo lmnsin elements of sequence injective an be )| 0 (N = [W + z ˜ ea nnt lotdson aiy ewill We family. disjoint almost infinite an be = (k ≤ | ] T ˜ h edrcnesl eiythat verify easily can reader The . ∞ m ∈ = ϑ |z y 1 [W 00 and = and . ; 0 u v n 0 ) ) x t ∈ let Claim , Main m z ] 0 1 1 A/n Let 0. | ∞ i ehv that have we , ∈ i contradicting ∅, a a ehv o all for have we c c y ∩ n sntdabove, noted as and Claim, Main 0 z z ˜ 0 ⊆ ∈ a > ⊆ N 1 ∈ n n ∈ ∈ 0 ∗ ] x f n ∈ [ s 0 ∞ (j (j x < N hr ssome is there [W ∩ 0 B ∈ v T max(a (N u N Then N. 1 i 1 ∩ [W 2 t uhthat such ∈ = 2 ) ) u · · · f > 0 t ecnte rag htfor that arrange then can we ∈ z f ehv that have we · · · ⊆ a 1 ∈ ∈ 0 s i · · · ⊆ (x / 0 00 N (N ⊆ A t {i 0 W n u 0 N 1 but 0, uhta o all for that such ⊆ and ehave we ] 0 a a ) s 0 u ] ∞ ∞ = x ∞ v n n s ⊆ i )| ∈ 0 0 1 0 sntmxml hc is which maximal, not is and u 00 z ˆ 0 00 i . ; , NSLts Articles Latest PNAS ( ∈ ). ∅ 00 = A and ∈ s n v that and and T ehave we 0 ∞ ) |f o all for ∈ T ˜ ran( [ : ∞ 00 f f z y ∩ W ∈ i i (u T (u od,te since then holds, ) a (x ∈ 1 ˜ = y = > y t T n n x | 0 ˜ and ∈ ∗ z 1 ˜ ∞ 0 This 4. Subclaim 0 N z ∞ ˜ ∗ 1 y 0 T ] f and ∩ z T ) n B ∈ ⊆ ∞ ∩ ) ˜ f and ∩ N ∗ ∈ ) ) ∈ ) a n 6=f z ∈ lal,for Clearly, }. (N y ∩ n B ∈ S 6 =f x 0 iial,if Similarly, . sasbe of subset a is ϑ for | N f esc that such be ∗ ∈ ecnthen can we z [W ˜ 1 m ∩ (z (x f v 1 s ea nthe in as be (x v t f sfiiefor finite is W and 1 (v i (v z 1 0 0 ∩ a (N )| y i )4f ) 0 1 ⊆ uhthat such ∈ 00 ⊆ n ∈ 1 ∞ ehave we ∞ 0 ) ,1 {0, ∈ ucam3.a Subclaim f B ∈ ehave we ] = ucam4.a Subclaim . s f ∞ = n for and v (x [W s )| ) | 0 n (x 00 ∞ 1 = ) (x 0 since ∅ 1 = f5 of 3 ∈ ∈ 0 that )| 0 ∈ not 0 ) for ] ∞ ). by ∞ T T =  }. ∅, N ˜ ˜ ∩

MATHEMATICS Remarks: in V [x] as in the proof of Theorem 1, is almost disjoint from every 00 ∞ z ∈ A. Otherwise, we can choose a Mathias condition (s, A) with 1) In the proof above, a crucial point was obtaining W0 ∈ [W0] 00 ∞ 0 0 s ⊆ x ⊆ A and a name y˙ such that p y˙ ∩ x˜˙G is infinite and Ψ(y ˙ ) such that (∀z ∈ [W0 ] )z ˜ ⊆ an or z˜ ∩ an = ∅. Note that an 00 (where x˙G is a name for the Mathias real). By a well-known prop- alternative and quick way to obtain such W0 is to appeal to W 00 erty of Mathias forcing (so-called continuous reading of names) Ramsey’s theorem for pairs and take 0 to be a homoge- ∞ {n, j } we can assume that there is a ϑ:[N] → neous set for the 2-coloring of unordered pairs , where ∞ assuming n < j we let [N] with code in V such that p forces that y˙ = ϑ(x ˙G ). It is easy to see that ϑ(y) ∈ A for any y ∈ [x]∞ (here we use the definabil- ( 0 ity of A). But then ran(ϑ) would be an analytic almost disjoint 1 if an (j ) ∈ an , c(n, j ) = c family such that any element of {y˜ : y ∈ [x]∞} has infinite inter- 0 otherwise. section with some element of ran(ϑ), which is impossible by the proof of Theorem 1.  2) Finally, the following obvious question must be addressed: Surprisingly, the connection between the Ramsey property in Can a similar result be obtained without assuming R-Unif? ∞ [N] and mad families relative to the ideal of finite sets extends We think it is unlikely and that the assumptions of Theo- to much more complicated Borel ideals. We construct a family rem 1 are the minimal natural assumptions needed to obtain of ideals using the familiar Fubini sum: Given, for each n ∈ , a positive solution to Mathias’ problem; but we do not know. N an ideal Jn on a countable set Sn we obtain an ideal J on S = F S Corollaries and Further Results n n as follows:

Corollary 3 (Tornquist¨ (5)). There are no mad families in Solovay’s M ∞ model. J = Jn = {X ⊆ S :(∀ n) X ∩ Sn ∈ Jn } Proof: By ref. 14, Solovay’s model is a model of ZF + DC. n That the Ramsey property holds in this model follows from where (∀∞n) means “for all but finitely many n.” The Fubini ref. 1. Finally, the Ramsey uniformization principle holds by our sum L FIN (where FIN denotes the ideal of finite sets on remarks after Definition 2. n  FIN × FIN FIN2 We point out that the proof of Theorem 1 above localizes as N) is also known as or ; iterating Fubini FINα α < ω follows. sums into the transfinite we obtain , 1. This fam- ily of ideals of lies cofinally in the in terms of Corollary 4. If Γ, Γ0 are reasonable such that every complexity. relation R ∈ Γ can be uniformized on a Ramsey positive set by a The notion of the mad family can be extended to arbitrary Γ0-measurable function and all sets in Γ0 are Ramsey, then there ideals on a countable set: If J is such an ideal, a J -almost dis- joint family is a subfamily A of P(S) \J such that for any 2 are no infinite mad families in Γ. 0 0 Note that in particular, this gives an additional proof of distinct A, A ∈ A, A ∩ A ∈ J .A J -mad family is of course a Mathias’ classical result that there are no analytic infinite mad J -almost disjoint family which is maximal under ⊆ among such families: Apply the corollary taking the of analytic sub- families. ∞ In ref. 16 we show the following: sets of [N] for Γ, and the σ algebra generated by the analytic sets for Γ0, and use the Jankov–von Neumann uniformization Theorem 7. (ZF + DC + R-Unif) Let α < ω1. If all sets theorem (ref. 12, theorem 18.1). α Our first corollary also allows us to draw consequences have the Ramsey property, then there are no infinite FIN -mad regarding the axiom of projective (in short, PD). families. As for classical mad families, we immediately obtain corollar- Corollary 5 (7, 8). PD implies there are no projective infinite mad ies regarding the axiom of projective determinacy and Solovay”s families. model. The first corollary was already shown in ref. 8 using Proof: The hypotheses of the previous theorem hold with forcing over inner models. Γ0 = Γ equal to the of projective sets: PD implies that this pointclass has the uniformization property, and by ref. 15, all Corollary 8. (ZF + PD) For each α < ω1 there are no infinite α projective sets are completely Ramsey under PD.  projective FIN -mad families. Another consequence of our proof is that Mathias forcing α destroys mad families from the ground model: Corollary 9. For each α < ω1 there are no infinite FIN -mad families in Solovay’s model. Theorem 6. In the Mathias extension, there is no infinite mad family Σ ACKNOWLEDGMENTS. This paper is dedicated to the memory of Professor which is definable by a 1 formula in the language of set theory with Richard Timoney (School of Mathematics, Trinity College Dublin), who sadly parameters in the ground model. In particular, no infinite almost passed away on 1 January 2019. We thank Professor Christian Rosendal and disjoint family from the ground model is maximal in the Mathias the anonymous reviewers for their useful comments and suggestions. D.S. extension. thanks the Austrian Science Fund for through Grant P29999. A.T. Proof: Suppose x is Mathias over V and that in V [x], A = thanks the Danish Council for Independent Research for generous support ∞ through Grant 7014-00145B. A.T. also gratefully acknowledges his associa- {z ∈ [N] : Ψ(z)} is an infinite almost disjoint family, where Ψ(z) tion with the Center for Symmetry and Deformation, funded by the Danish is Σ1 (with parameter in V ). We show that x˜, where x˜ is defined National Research Foundation (DNRF92).

1. A. R. D. Mathias, Happy families. Ann. Math. Logic 12, 59–111 (1977). 8. K. Bakke Haga, D. Schrittesser, A. Tornquist,¨ Maximal almost disjoint families, 2. F. Galvin, K. Prikry, Borel sets and Ramsey’s theorem. J. Symb. Log. 38, 193–198 (1973). determinacy, and forcing. arXiv:1810.03016 (6 October 2018). 3. J. Silver, Every analytic set is Ramsey. J. Symb. Log. 35, 60–64 (1970). 9. H. Horowitz, S. Shelah, A Borel maximal eventually different family. arXiv:1605.07123 4. E. Ellentuck, A new proof that analytic sets are Ramsey. J. Symb. Log. 39, 163–165 (23 May 2016). (1974). 10. D. Schrittesser, Compactness of maximal eventually different families. Bull. Lond. 5. A. Tornquist,¨ Definability and almost disjoint families. Adv. Math. 330, 61–73 (2018). Math. Soc. 50, 340–348 (2018). 6. H. Horowitz, S. Shelah, Can you take Tornquist’s¨ inaccessible away? arXiv:1605.02419 11. H. Horowitz, S. Shelah, Madness and regularity properties. arXiv:1704.08327 (26 April (9 May 2019). 2017). 7. I. Neeman, Z. Norwood, Happy and mad families in L(R). J. Symb. Log. 83, 572–597 12. A. S. Kechris, Classical , Graduate Texts in Mathematics (2018). (Springer, New York, NY, 1995), vol. 156.

4 of 5 | www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1906183116 Schrittesser and Tornquist¨ Downloaded by guest on October 1, 2021 Downloaded by guest on October 1, 2021 4 .M ooa,Amdlo e-hoyi hc vr e frasi Lebesgue is reals of set every which in set-theory of model A Solovay, M. R. 14. Todorcevic, S. 13. crtesradT and Schrittesser measurable. Studies) PictnUiest rs,Pictn J 00,vl 174. vol. 2010), NJ, Princeton, Press, University (Princeton n.Math. Ann. nrdcint asySae A-7)(naso Mathematics of (Annals (AM-174) Spaces Ramsey to Introduction ornquist ¨ –6(1970). 1–56 92, 6 .Shitse,A T A. ordinals. Schrittesser, on games D. of determinacy 16. the On Kechris, S. A. Harrington, A. L. 15. aiis ri:94084(5Arl2019). April (15 arXiv:1904.05824 families. Logic 0–5 (1981). 109–154 20, rqit h asypoet n ihrdmninlmad dimensional higher and property Ramsey The ornquist, ¨ NSLts Articles Latest PNAS n.Math. Ann. | f5 of 5

MATHEMATICS