The Theory of Countable Analytical Sets Author(S): Alexander S

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Theory of Countable Analytical Sets Author(S): Alexander S The Theory of Countable Analytical Sets Author(s): Alexander S. Kechris Source: Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. 202 (Feb., 1975), pp. 259-297 Published by: American Mathematical Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1997311 . Accessed: 22/05/2013 14:36 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Mathematical Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 131.215.71.79 on Wed, 22 May 2013 14:36:53 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 202, 1975 THE THEORYOF COUNTABLEANALYTICAL SETS(1) BY ALEXANDER S. KECHRIS ABSTRACT. The purpose of this paper is the study of the structure of countable sets in the various levels of the analytical hierarchy of sets of reals. It is first shown that, assuming projective determinacy, there is for each odd n a largest countable n set of reals, en (this is also true for n even, replacing 1n by En and has been established earlier by Solovay for n = 2 and by Moschovakis and the author for all even n > 2). The internal structure of the sets Con is then investigated in detail, the point of departure being the fact that each CO is a set of A1-degrees, wellordered under their usual partial ordering. Finally, a number of applications of the preceding theory is presented, covering a variety of topics such as specification of bases, w-models of analysis, higher- level analogs of the constructible universe, inductive definability, etc. It is a classicaltheorem of effectivedescriptive set theorythat a S thin (i.e. containingno perfectset) subsetof the continuumis countableand in fact containsonly Al reals. As a consequence,among the countable S1 sets of realsthere is no largestone. Solovay[41] showedthat everythin 2 set con- tainsonly constructiblereals and therefore(in sharpcontrast with the previous case),assuming a measurablecardinal exists, thereis a largestcountable T4 set of reals,namely the set of constructibleones. In [19] Moschovakisand the author extendedSolovay's theorem to all evenlevels of the analyticalhierarchy. It was provedthere that, assumingprojective determinacy (PD), thereis a largestcount- able 4,n set for all n > 1, whichwe denoteby C2n. The firstmain result we provein this paper(see ?1) is the existenceof a largestcountable H?,+ 1 set (whichwe denoteby C2n + ) for all n > 0, assumingPD again. For n = 0 our proofshows, in ZF + DC only, the existenceof a largestthin Hl set of realsC1, a fact whichwas also independentlydiscovered by D. Guaspari[12] andG. E. Sacks[38]. (To completethe picture,we remarkhere that it was shown in [17], using PD, that no largest countable 2An-+1 or I21n sets exist.) Once the existenceof the largestcountable sets Cn is establishedthe rest of ?1 is devotedto the study of theirinternal structure. We show here that Cn is actuallya set of An-degreeswhich is lwellordered under the usualordering of Al-degrees. Let us denoteby {d-}<pn the increasinghierarchy of the Al- Received by the editors September 13, 1973. AMS (MOS) subject classifications (1970). Primary 04A15, 02K30, 28A05, 54H05; Secondary 02F35, 02K05, 02K25, 02K35, 04A30. ( ) Research partially supported by NSF grant GP 27964. Copyriglht ? 1975. AmiiericaniMatlhcmiiatical Society 259 This content downloaded from 131.215.71.79 on Wed, 22 May 2013 14:36:53 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 260 A. S. KECHRIS degreesof (elementsof) Cn. As we (hope to) illustratein this paperthe hierarchy {dn},<p playsa significantrole in the generalstructure theory of the analytical sets of the nth level.It provides a commonframe of referenceand a startingpoint for investigationsin a varietyof diversetopics such as specificationof bases, co- modelsof analysis,higher-level analogs of L, inductivedefinability, etc. After the generaltheory is discussed,we examinein moredetail in ?2 the structureof C1, the largestthin HII set (partof the resultshere have been in- dependentlydiscovered by D. Guaspari[12] andG. E. Sacks[38]). Weshow, amongother things, that {df}l<Pl=tj coincideswith the hierarchyof the hy- perdegreesof the Boolos-Putnamcomplete sets of integers.A naturalquasi- hierarchyof hyperdegreesis then defined,which extends (through all the con- structiblereals) the naturalhierarchy of hyperdegreesand it is shownto be ex- actly {d1},<,q. ? 3 accountsfor the structuraldifferences between C21n. with n > 0 and C1. The basicreason for themis the fact that the notion of "wellordering on co" is 'An 1 if n > 0, but not Al. Martinand Solovay[29] madea remarkableuse of this fact to producea counterexampleto the well-knowncon- jecturethat the Kleenebasis theorem for 11 generalizes,under PD, in a straight- forwardfashion to all I',,+2n+1 1 with n > 0. The Martin-Solovaydiscovery re- vealedfor the first time an importantstructural difference between the first and the higherodd levelsof the analyticalhierarchy. In the firstpart of ? 3 we deal with reflectingpointclasses and we unearthmore suchstructural differences. This eventuallyleads us to the subjectof Q-theory(see ?3B), whichwas developed by Martinand Solovayand independentlyby the author.And we end ? 3 with a briefsummary of the connectionbetween countable analytical sets andhigher level analogsof L. Finally,in ? 4, questionsconcerning countable analytical sets in innermodels like L are discussedand various consistency and independenceresults are obtained. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS.Part of the resultsin this paperis containedin the author'sPh.D. thesis (UCLA 1972). Wewish to thankour thesissupervisor ProfessorY. N. Moschovakisfor his guidanceand encouragementand most of all for creatingour interestin descriptiveset theoryand for directingour attention to the problemof countablesets. Weare also gratefulto Dr. L. Harringtonand ProfessorsD. A. Martin,G. E. Sacksand R. Solovayfor numeroushelpful dis- cussionson this subject. 0. Preliminaries.OA. Let co = {O, 1, 2, . .} be the set of natural numbersand R = 'co the set of all functionsfrom X to X or (for sim- plicity) reals. Letters i, j, k, 1, m, . denote elements of co and a, j, 7, 6, . reals. Subsetsof co aremany times below identified with theircharac- teristicfunctions. We studysubsets of the productspaces X = Xl X X2 X... X Xk, This content downloaded from 131.215.71.79 on Wed, 22 May 2013 14:36:53 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE THEORY OF COUNTABLE ANALYTICAL SETS 261 x&hereX, is X or R. We call such subsetspointsets. Sometimeswe thinkof themas relationsand we writeinterchangeably x EA * A(x). A pointclassis a classof pointsets,usually in all productspaces. Weshall be concernedprimarily in this paperwith the analyticalpointclasses S1, ni, Al and theircorresponding projective pointclasses El, f1, Al. For information aboutthem we referto [37], [39] and the introductionof [30] fromwhich we also drawsome of our nonstandardnotation. If r is a pointclasswe put F={X-A:AEr,A C X} = the dual of r, and A = r n r, while for each a E R, 1(a) = {A: For some B E1r, A(x) * B(x, a)} and A(a) = r(a) n r(a). Wealso let r =U 1r(a) and A =frn r. aER If A C X X co, put 3wA = {x: 3nA(x, a)}, V 'A = {x: VnA(x, n)} andif A C X X R, put 3RA= {x: 3aA(x, a)}, VRA= {x: VaA(x, a)}. If 4) is any operationon pointsets(like e.g. 3W above), let (Dr={(DA: A Er} andsay that r is closedunder 4) if (Drc r. Let r be a pointclass,X a productspace (X = co or R is enoughfor this definition).We say that r is X-parametrizedif for any productspace y there isa GEr, GC YXX sothat f Gx = {y:(y,x)EG}then {Gx:xEX}= {A CY: Aer}. In this casewe say that G is X-universalfor r subsetsof Y. If A = Gx, x is calleda code of A. A pointclassr is adequateif it containsall the recursivesets (in all prod- uct spaces) and is closedunder conjunction, disjunction, number quantification of both kindsand substitution by total recursivefunctions. It is clearthat all analyticalpointclasses are adequateand all 11, HI are -parametrizedwhile all projectivepointclasses are adequate and all Z1, II' are R-parametrized.In generalif r is adequateand c-parametrized,r is adequateand R-parametrized Moreoverthe R-universalsets for r can be takento be in r. Wheneverwe workwith a parametrizedpointclass which has also some closureproperties we shallalways assume that universalsets for this classare chosenso that the pointclassis uniformlyclosed (e.g. if r is assumedclosed under A n B, a fixed recursivefunction will computea code for A n B from codesof A, B). OB. Let A be a pointset. A norm on A is a map 0: A -*+X from A This content downloaded from 131.215.71.79 on Wed, 22 May 2013 14:36:53 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 262 A. S. KECHRIS onto an ordinal X, the lengthof 0 (notation: length(q) = I?1 =X). With eachsuch norm we associatethe prewellordering(i.e. the reflexive,transitive, connected,wellfounded relation) v on A, definedby x < *y (x) <?(y). Put also x <0y *(x)<4OM. Converselyeach prewellordering< with field A givesrise to a uniquenorm 4: A -X such that < we thencall X the lengthof ;. If r is a pointclassand 0 is a normon A, we say that ? is a r-normif thereexist relations?r, 4 in r, r respectivelyso that y E A =V x {[x E A & @(x)S y)] *x <,? y * x? y}.
Recommended publications
  • Calibrating Determinacy Strength in Levels of the Borel Hierarchy
    CALIBRATING DETERMINACY STRENGTH IN LEVELS OF THE BOREL HIERARCHY SHERWOOD J. HACHTMAN Abstract. We analyze the set-theoretic strength of determinacy for levels of the Borel 0 hierarchy of the form Σ1+α+3, for α < !1. Well-known results of H. Friedman and D.A. Martin have shown this determinacy to require α+1 iterations of the Power Set Axiom, but we ask what additional ambient set theory is strictly necessary. To this end, we isolate a family of Π1-reflection principles, Π1-RAPα, whose consistency strength corresponds 0 CK exactly to that of Σ1+α+3-Determinacy, for α < !1 . This yields a characterization of the levels of L by or at which winning strategies in these games must be constructed. When α = 0, we have the following concise result: the least θ so that all winning strategies 0 in Σ4 games belong to Lθ+1 is the least so that Lθ j= \P(!) exists + all wellfounded trees are ranked". x1. Introduction. Given a set A ⊆ !! of sequences of natural numbers, consider a game, G(A), where two players, I and II, take turns picking elements of a sequence hx0; x1; x2;::: i of naturals. Player I wins the game if the sequence obtained belongs to A; otherwise, II wins. For a collection Γ of subsets of !!, Γ determinacy, which we abbreviate Γ-DET, is the statement that for every A 2 Γ, one of the players has a winning strategy in G(A). It is a much-studied phenomenon that Γ -DET has mathematical strength: the bigger the pointclass Γ, the stronger the theory required to prove Γ -DET.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind
    Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind Anne Newstead Abstract. The mathematician Georg Cantor strongly believed in the existence of actually infinite numbers and sets. Cantor’s “actualism” went against the Aristote- lian tradition in metaphysics and mathematics. Under the pressures to defend his theory, his metaphysics changed from Spinozistic monism to Leibnizian volunta- rist dualism. The factor motivating this change was two-fold: the desire to avoid antinomies associated with the notion of a universal collection and the desire to avoid the heresy of necessitarian pantheism. We document the changes in Can- tor’s thought with reference to his main philosophical-mathematical treatise, the Grundlagen (1883) as well as with reference to his article, “Über die verschiedenen Standpunkte in bezug auf das aktuelle Unendliche” (“Concerning Various Perspec- tives on the Actual Infinite”) (1885). I. he Philosophical Reception of Cantor’s Ideas. Georg Cantor’s dis- covery of transfinite numbers was revolutionary. Bertrand Russell Tdescribed it thus: The mathematical theory of infinity may almost be said to begin with Cantor. The infinitesimal Calculus, though it cannot wholly dispense with infinity, has as few dealings with it as possible, and contrives to hide it away before facing the world Cantor has abandoned this cowardly policy, and has brought the skeleton out of its cupboard. He has been emboldened on this course by denying that it is a skeleton. Indeed, like many other skeletons, it was wholly dependent on its cupboard, and vanished in the light of day.1 1Bertrand Russell, The Principles of Mathematics (London: Routledge, 1992 [1903]), 304.
    [Show full text]
  • Effective Cardinals of Boldface Pointclasses
    EFFECTIVE CARDINALS OF BOLDFACE POINTCLASSES ALESSANDRO ANDRETTA, GREG HJORTH, AND ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. Assuming AD + DC(R), we characterize the self-dual boldface point- classes which are strictly larger (in terms of cardinality) than the pointclasses contained in them: these are exactly the clopen sets, the collections of all sets of ξ ξ Wadge rank ≤ ω1, and those of Wadge rank < ω1 when ξ is limit. 1. Introduction A boldface pointclass (for short: a pointclass) is a non-empty collection Γ of subsets of R such that Γ is closed under continuous pre-images and Γ 6= P(R). 0 0 0 Examples of pointclasses are the levels Σα, Πα, ∆α of the Borel hierarchy and the 1 1 1 levels Σn, Πn, ∆n of the projective hierarchy. In this paper we address the following Question 1. What is the cardinality of a pointclass? Assuming AC, the Axiom of Choice, Question 1 becomes trivial for all pointclasses Γ which admit a complete set. These pointclasses all have size 2ℵ0 under AC. On the other hand there is no obvious, natural way to associate, in a one-to-one way, 0 an open set (or for that matter: a closed set, or a real number) to any Σ2 set. This 0 0 suggests that in the realm of definable sets and functions already Σ1 and Σ2 may have different sizes. Indeed the second author in [Hjo98] and [Hjo02] showed that AD + V = L(R) actually implies 0 0 (a) 1 ≤ α < β < ω1 =⇒ |Σα| < |Σβ|, and 1 1 1 (b) |∆1| < |Σ1| < |Σ2| < .
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor's Discovery of Transfinite Numbers
    HISTORIA MATHEMATICA 22 (1995), 33-42 "What Fermented in Me for Years": Cantor's Discovery of Transfinite Numbers Jos~ FERREIROS History of Science and Technology, 543 Stephens Hall, Unioersity of California at Berkeley, Berkeley, California 94720 Transfinite (ordinal) numbers were a crucial step in the development of Cantor's set theory. The new concept depended in various ways on previous problems and results, and especially on two questions that were at the center of Cantor's attention in September 1882, when he was about to make his discovery. First, the proof of the Cantor-Bendixson theorem motivated the introduction of transfinite numbers, and at the same time suggested the "principle of limitation," which is the key to the connection between transfinite numbers and infinite powers. Second, Dedekind's ideas, which Cantor discussed in September 1882, seem to have played an important heuristic role in his decision to consider the "symbols of infinity" that he had been using as true numbers, i.e., as autonomous objects; to this end Cantor introduced in his work, for the first time, ideas on (well) ordered sets. © 1995 Academic Press, Inc. Los ntimeros (ordinales) transfinitos constituyeron un paso clave en el desarrollo de la teorfa de conjuntos de Cantor. La nueva idea dependi6 en varias formas de resultados y problemas previos, pero especialmente de dos cuestiones que ocuparon a Cantor en septiem- bre de 1882, estando a punto de realizar su descubrimiento. En primer lugar, el teorema de Cantor-Bendixson, cuya demostraci6n motiv6 la introducci6n de los ntimeros transfinitos, y a la vez sugiri6 el "principio de limitaci6n" que constituye la clave de la conexi6n entre ntimeros transfinitos y potencias infinitas.
    [Show full text]
  • The Envelope of a Pointclass Under a Local Determinacy Hypothesis
    THE ENVELOPE OF A POINTCLASS UNDER A LOCAL DETERMINACY HYPOTHESIS TREVOR M. WILSON Abstract. Given an inductive-like pointclass Γ and assuming the Ax- iom of Determinacy, Martin identified and analyzede the pointclass con- taining the norm relations of the next semiscale beyond Γ, if one exists. We show that much of Martin's analysis can be carriede out assuming only ZF + DCR + Det(∆Γ). This generalization requires arguments from Kechris{Woodin [10] ande e Martin [13]. The results of [10] and [13] can then be recovered as immediate corollaries of the general analysis. We also obtain a new proof of a theorem of Woodin on divergent models of AD+, as well as a new result regarding the derived model at an inde- structibly weakly compact limit of Woodin cardinals. Introduction Given an inductive-like pointclass Γ, Martin introduced a pointclass (which we call the envelope of Γ, following [22])e whose main feature is that it con- tains the prewellorderingse of the next scale (or semiscale) beyond Γ, if such a (semi)scale exists. This work was distributed as \Notes on the nexte Suslin cardinal," as cited in Jackson [3]. It is unpublished, so we use [3] as our reference instead for several of Martin's arguments. Martin's analysis used the assumption of the Axiom of Determinacy. We reformulate the notion of the envelope in such a way that many of its essen- tial properties can by derived without assuming AD. Instead we will work in the base theory ZF+DCR for the duration of the paper, stating determinacy hypotheses only when necessary.
    [Show full text]
  • The Realm of Ordinal Analysis
    The Realm of Ordinal Analysis Michael Rathjen Department of Pure Mathematics, University of Leeds Leeds LS2 9JT, United Kingdom Denn die Pioniere der Mathematik hatten sich von gewissen Grundlagen brauchbare Vorstellungen gemacht, aus denen sich Schl¨usse,Rechnungsarten, Resultate ergaben, deren bem¨achtigten sich die Physiker, um neue Ergebnisse zu erhalten, und endlich kamen die Techniker, nahmen oft bloß die Resultate, setzten neue Rechnungen darauf und es entstanden Maschinen. Und pl¨otzlich, nachdem alles in sch¨onste Existenz gebracht war, kamen die Mathematiker - jene, die ganz innen herumgr¨ubeln, - darauf, daß etwas in den Grundlagen der ganzen Sache absolut nicht in Ordnung zu bringen sei; tats¨achlich, sie sahen zuunterst nach und fanden, daß das ganze Geb¨audein der Luft stehe. Aber die Maschinen liefen! Man muß daraufhin annehmen, daß unser Dasein bleicher Spuk ist; wir leben es, aber eigentlich nur auf Grund eines Irrtums, ohne den es nicht entstanden w¨are. ROBERT MUSIL: Der mathematische Mensch (1913) 1 Introduction A central theme running through all the main areas of Mathematical Logic is the classification of sets, functions or theories, by means of transfinite hierarchies whose ordinal levels measure their ‘rank’ or ‘complexity’ in some sense appropriate to the underlying context. In Proof Theory this is manifest in the assignment of ‘proof the- oretic ordinals’ to theories, gauging their ‘consistency strength’ and ‘computational power’. Ordinal-theoretic proof theory came into existence in 1936, springing forth from Gentzen’s head in the course of his consistency proof of arithmetic. To put it roughly, ordinal analyses attach ordinals in a given representation system to formal theories.
    [Show full text]
  • Determinacy and Large Cardinals
    Determinacy and Large Cardinals Itay Neeman∗ Abstract. The principle of determinacy has been crucial to the study of definable sets of real numbers. This paper surveys some of the uses of determinacy, concentrating specifically on the connection between determinacy and large cardinals, and takes this connection further, to the level of games of length ω1. Mathematics Subject Classification (2000). 03E55; 03E60; 03E45; 03E15. Keywords. Determinacy, iteration trees, large cardinals, long games, Woodin cardinals. 1. Determinacy Let ωω denote the set of infinite sequences of natural numbers. For A ⊂ ωω let Gω(A) denote the length ω game with payoff A. The format of Gω(A) is displayed in Diagram 1. Two players, denoted I and II, alternate playing natural numbers forming together a sequence x = hx(n) | n < ωi in ωω called a run of the game. The run is won by player I if x ∈ A, and otherwise the run is won by player II. I x(0) x(2) ...... II x(1) x(3) ...... Diagram 1. The game Gω(A). A game is determined if one of the players has a winning strategy. The set A is ω determined if Gω(A) is determined. For Γ ⊂ P(ω ), det(Γ) denotes the statement that all sets in Γ are determined. Using the axiom of choice, or more specifically using a wellordering of the reals, it is easy to construct a non-determined set A. det(P(ωω)) is therefore false. On the other hand it has become clear through research over the years that det(Γ) is true if all the sets in Γ are definable by some concrete means.
    [Show full text]
  • Effective Descriptive Set Theory
    Effective Descriptive Set Theory Andrew Marks December 14, 2019 1 1 These notes introduce the effective (lightface) Borel, Σ1 and Π1 sets. This study uses ideas and tools from descriptive set theory and computability theory. Our central motivation is in applications of the effective theory to theorems of classical (boldface) descriptive set theory, especially techniques which have no classical analogues. These notes have many errors and are very incomplete. Some important topics not covered include: • The Harrington-Shore-Slaman theorem [HSS] which implies many of the theorems of Section 3. • Steel forcing (see [BD, N, Mo, St78]) • Nonstandard model arguments • Barwise compactness, Jensen's model existence theorem • α-recursion theory • Recent beautiful work of the \French School": Debs, Saint-Raymond, Lecompte, Louveau, etc. These notes are from a class I taught in spring 2019. Thanks to Adam Day, Thomas Gilton, Kirill Gura, Alexander Kastner, Alexander Kechris, Derek Levinson, Antonio Montalb´an,Dean Menezes and Riley Thornton, for helpful conversations and comments on earlier versions of these notes. 1 Contents 1 1 1 1 Characterizing Σ1, ∆1, and Π1 sets 4 1 1.1 Σn formulas, closure properties, and universal sets . .4 1.2 Boldface vs lightface sets and relativization . .5 1 1.3 Normal forms for Σ1 formulas . .5 1.4 Ranking trees and Spector boundedness . .7 1 1.5 ∆1 = effectively Borel . .9 1.6 Computable ordinals, hyperarithmetic sets . 11 1 1.7 ∆1 = hyperarithmetic . 14 x 1 1.8 The hyperjump, !1 , and the analogy between c.e. and Π1 .... 15 2 Basic tools 18 2.1 Existence proofs via completeness results .
    [Show full text]
  • Applications of Ultrafilters in Ergodic Theory and Combinatorial Number
    Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam Jagiellonian University Master Thesis Applications of Ultrafilters in Ergodic Theory and Combinatorial Number Theory Supervisors: Author: Dr. Tanja Eisner Jakub Konieczny Prof. Dr. Ale Jan Homburg Dr Piotr Niemiec A thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Mathematics in the Department of Mathematics, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam Instytut Matematyki, Jagiellonian University arXiv:1310.1056v2 [math.DS] 16 Oct 2013 October 2013 Declaration of Authorship I, Jakub Konieczny, declare that this thesis titled “Applications of Ultrafilters in Ergodic Theory and Combinatorial Number Theory” is my own. I confirm that: This work was done wholly or mainly while in candidature for a research degree at these Universities. Where I have consulted the published work of others, this is always clearly at- tributed. Where I have quoted from the work of others, the source is always given. With the exception of such quotations, this thesis is entirely my own work. I have acknowledged all main sources of help. Signed: Date: i “Thanks to my solid academic training, today I can write hundreds of words on virtually any topic without possessing a shred of information, which is how I got a good job in journalism." Dave Barry VRIJE UNIVERSITEIT AMSTERDAM JAGIELLONIAN UNIVERSITY Abstract Faculty of Sciences, Department of Mathematics Wydział Matematyki i Informatyki, Instytut Matematyki Master of Mathematics Applications of Ultrafilters in Ergodic Theory and Combinatorial Number Theory by Jakub Konieczny Ultrafilters are very useful and versatile objects with applications throughout mathemat- ics: in topology, analysis, combinarotics, model theory, and even theory of social choice. Proofs based on ultrafilters tend to be shorter and more elegant than their classical coun- terparts.
    [Show full text]
  • A Classification of Projective-Like Hierarchies in L(R)
    A classification of projective-like hierarchies in L(R) Rachid Atmai Universit¨atWien Kurt G¨odelResearch Center W¨ahringerStraße 25 1090 Vienna [email protected] Steve Jackson Dept. of Mathematics General Academics Building 435 1155 Union Circle 311430 University of North Texas Denton, TX 76203-5017 [email protected] October 10, 2016 Abstract We provide a characterization of projective-like hierarchies in L(R) in the context of AD by combinatorial properties of their associated Wadge ordinal. In the second chapter we concentrate on the type III case of the analysis. In the last chapter, we provide a characterization of type IV projective-like hierarchies by their associated Wadge ordinal. 1 Introduction 1.1 Outline The paper is roughly organized as follows. We first review basic definitions of the abstract theory of pointclasses. In the second section we study the type III pointclasses and the clo- sure properties of the Steel pointclass generated by a projective algebra Λ in the case where cof(o(Λ)) > !. In particular we show that Steel's conjecture is false. This leads to isolat- ing a combinatorial property of the Wadge ordinal of the projective algebra generating the 1 Steel pointclass. This combinatorial property ensures closure of the Steel pointclass under dis- junctions. Therefore it is still possible to have κ regular, where κ is the Wadge ordinal for a projective algebra Λ generating the next Steel pointclass and yet the Steel pointclass is not closed under disjunction. In the third section, we look at the type IV projective-like hierarchies, that is the pointclass which starts the new hierarchy is closed under quantifiers.
    [Show full text]
  • Basic Computability Theory
    Basic Computability Theory Jaap van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University 1993, revised 2013 ii Introduction The subject of this course is the theory of computable or recursive functions. Computability Theory and Recursion Theory are two names for it; the former being more popular nowadays. 0.1 Why Computability Theory? The two most important contributions Logic has made to Mathematics, are formal definitions of proof and of algorithmic computation. How useful is this? Mathematicians are trained in understanding and constructing proofs from their first steps in the subject, and surely they can recognize a valid proof when they see one; likewise, algorithms have been an essential part of Mathematics for as long as it exists, and at the most elementary levels (think of long division, or Euclid’s algorithm for the greatest common divisor function). So why do we need a formal definition here? The main use is twofold. Firstly, a formal definition of proof (or algorithm) leads to an analysis of proofs (programs) in elementary reasoning steps (computation steps), thereby opening up the possibility of numerical classification of proofs (programs)1. In Proof Theory, proofs are assigned ordinal numbers, and theorems are classified according to the complexity of the proofs they need. In Complexity Theory, programs are analyzed according to the number of elementary computation steps they require (as a function of the input), and programming problems are classified in terms of these complexity functions. Secondly, a formal definition is needed once one wishes to explore the boundaries of the topic: what can be proved at all? Which kind of problems can be settled by an algorithm? It is this aspect that we will focus on in this course.
    [Show full text]
  • Souslin Quasi-Orders and Bi-Embeddability of Uncountable
    Souslin quasi-orders and bi-embeddability of uncountable structures Alessandro Andretta Luca Motto Ros Author address: Universita` di Torino, Dipartimento di Matematica, Via Carlo Alberto, 10, 10123 Torino, Italy E-mail address: [email protected] Universita` di Torino, Dipartimento di Matematica, Via Carlo Alberto, 10, 10123 Torino, Italy E-mail address: [email protected] arXiv:1609.09292v2 [math.LO] 18 Mar 2019 Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Preliminaries and notation 14 3. The generalized Cantor space 22 4. Generalized Borel sets 30 5. Generalized Borel functions 37 6. The generalized Baire space and Baire category 41 7. Standard Borel κ-spaces, κ-analyticquasi-orders,andspacesofcodes 47 8. Infinitary logics and models 55 9. κ-Souslin sets 65 10. The main construction 76 11. Completeness 85 12. Invariant universality 91 13. An alternative approach 106 14. Definable cardinality and reducibility 115 15. Some applications 126 16. Further completeness results 132 Indexes 147 Concepts 147 Symbols 148 Bibliography 151 iii Abstract We provide analogues of the results from [FMR11, CMMR13] (which correspond to the case κ = ω) for arbitrary κ-Souslin quasi-orders on any Polish space, for κ an infinite cardinal smaller than the cardinality of R. These generalizations yield a variety of results concerning the complexity of the embeddability relation between graphs or lattices of size κ, the isometric embeddability relation between complete metric spaces of density character κ, and the linear isometric embeddability relation between (real or complex) Banach spaces of density κ. Received by the editor March 19, 2019. 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 03E15, 03E60, 03E45, 03E10, 03E47.
    [Show full text]