Heidegger, Ontology, Metontology, and the Turn

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Heidegger, Ontology, Metontology, and the Turn Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 1988 Heidegger, Ontology, Metontology, and the Turn Kelly Edward Mink Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Mink, Kelly Edward, "Heidegger, Ontology, Metontology, and the Turn" (1988). Dissertations. 2561. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/2561 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1988 Kelly Edward Mink All Rights Reserved, Kelly Edward Mink, 1988 HEIDEGGER: ONTOLOGY, METONTOLOGY, AND THE TURN by Kelly Edward Mink A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty fo the Graduate School of Loyola University of Chicago in Partial Fulfillment of the Requireaents for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 1988 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This dissertation would not have been possible without the intellectual generosity and tolerance toward his students that char­ acterizes John Sallis as a director; it was these qualities, along with the already publicly recognized virtues of philosophical accomplish­ ment and leadership in research that led me to Loyola University of Chicago to work with Professor Sallis. I would also like to acknowledge the kindness of Professor Robert Bernasconi in agreeing to serve on my committee even though it meant a long trip from England in April solely to participate in my oral defense; and the helpfulness of Professor Thomas Sheehan in raising questions and proffering criticisms while I was working on the dissertation. The Graduate School of Loyola University awarded me a Schmitt Fellowship for the year 1986-87, without which I could not have finished the dissertation so soon after completing my course work; for this assistance I am deeply grateful. ii VITA The author, Kelly Edward Mink, is the son of C. Kelly Mink and Stella (Manning) Mink Moore. He was born February 29, 1944 in Fostor­ ia, Ohio. His elementary education was obtained primarily in the public schools of Pineville, Louisiana. His secondary education was completed in 1962 at Tioga High School in Tioga, Louisiana. In June, 1962, Mr. Mink entered Louisiana State University, re­ ceiving the degree of Bachelor of Science in mathematics in May, 1967. He completed his Master of Arts degree in philosophy in August, 1976, at Louisiana State University. In September, 1981 (teaching high school in the interim) he entered Duquesne University in Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania. From there he transferred to Loyola University of Chicago in 1984, where he was granted research assistantships contin­ uously until 1986, when he was awarded the Schmitt Fellowship. The latter enabled him to finish his dissertation, successfully defending it on April 3, 1987. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ii VITA iii INTRODUCTION 1 Chapter I. HEIDEGGER'S EARLY CONCEPT OF METAPHYSICS ..... 24 II. LEIBNIZ 1 S DOCTRINE OF JUDGMENT AND ITS ~~~1~~KTtON 57 III. NEUTRALITY AND CONCRETENESS OF DASEIN IN 110: "THE PROBLEM OF TRANSCENDENCE AND THE PROBLEM OF BE ING AND _VME" 96 IV. THE SCIENCE OF BEING AND THE TURN 135 V. "ON THE ESSENCE OF TRUTH" AS A METONTOLOGICAL TREATISE 176 SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY: HEIDEGGER 1 S WORKS 209 SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY: HEIDEGGER'S WORKS TRANSLATED INTO ENGLISH 212 BOOKS, ARTICLES, AND COLLECTIONS OF ESSAYS 214 iv INTRODUCTION The following dissertation has as its purpose an inquiry into the concrete significance of the "turn" in Heidegger's work. The 1928 lecture course entitled Metaphysische Anfangsgrtinde der Logik im Aus­ gang von Leibniz yields essential clues to the solution of the problem of the turn, for Heidegger introduces, in this text, a distinction between ontology and metontology [Metontologie] which provides a basis for understanding the transition from the early to the middle period in his work. The usual formulation of the turn as a "turn from Dasein to Being" is inadequate either as a representation of the progression of Heidegger's work or as a characterization of the sense of the turn itself. According to this perspective on Heidegger's work, usually called the "developmental" view, in the initial phase Heidegger focused upon transcendence as foundational of thought and world; in the later phase, he shifts to a "Being-centered problematic"l. David Krell2 speaks of a "developmentalist bog"3 with reference to the image of the turn as an advance from phenomenology to "the other thinking"; presum­ ably this formulation is meant to characterize Richardson's position in Heidegger: Through Phenomenology to Thought. The worst version of the developmentalist view, according to Krell, is that of Bollnow and L6with; for them, in the later Heidegger "a mystical and mystifying contemplation of pure Being replaces existential analysis"4. Krell correctly insists, against every parody of the turn, that 1 2 Heidegger continues in his later period to emphasize the "antic fundament"5 that supports the thinking of Being. Surely one can ask, however, whether some view of Heidegger's "development" isn't possible which neither runs roughshod over the central concerns of each phase of Heidegger's work, nor which neglects the textual evidence that essen­ tial changes occur in Heidegger's approach. Krell, in his own discus­ sion, fails to account for or even recognize the change of approach manifest in Heidegger's middle- and late-period texts. In opposition to the developmentalist view, he says only that "'Heidegger-II' intro­ duces humanity (der Mensch) into his texts far more liberally than does the 'Heidegger-I' who analyzes Da-Sein"6. Apparently content with merely disputing the claim that Heidegger turns from man to Being in his later work, Krell fails to recognize that it is precisely the prob­ lem of the "antic fundament" which leads to the crisis in Heidegger's work to which the turn is a response. Even while suggesting that the changes in Heidegger's thought arise from an increasing concern with the problematic of finitude, Krell takes a rationalistic view of the effect of this issue on Hei­ degger's thought. For he holds that, because Heidegger is aware quite early ("in 1924 or 1925"7) that the project of ontology is threatened by the concept of the finitude of time, "the difficulty is whether the word Kehre in the developmentalist sense can mean anything at all any more"8. Krell seems actually to suggest that if a determinate set of problems can be found which Heidegger addresses in his work, then there is no need to attempt to characterize and account for the manifest changes in his work. Thus in his essay "Heidegger's Ostensible Turn- 3 ing," we find the following remarks: By now the disadvantage of all such developmentalist approaches--whatever semblance of order they provide--ought to have become apparent. Whether we subdivide Heidegger into two or three or even more parts, the problem remains that the moment we begin to think about any element of any part that element itself turns back and forth to all the remaining elements of Heidegger's thought .... Each element of Heidegger's thought turns, showing itself in sundry perspectives. These turnings seem to have had no first beginning in Heidegger's career; they certainly have no final end once we ourselves begin to turn with them.9 That the elements of Heidegger's thought remain, in a certain sense, a constant set, and that Heidegger explores these in different ways at different times, "turning" back and forth among them, is undoubtedly true but of rather minimal significance by itself. What philosopher doesn't reexamine the "elements" of his thought over and over again? Krell's remarks here trivialize the issue. They offer no clue concern- ing a question which demands a response in this context: Given that there are changes in Heidegger's thought--i.e., reformulations, mani- fest in the texts themselves, of the issues of central concern in Heidegger's problematic--how can they be characterized and accounted for? It is not at all necessary to suppose, as Krell so strangely does, that the problem of the turn can be formulated only in terms of a change of focus from man to Being (or vice versa) and that it can be answered by saying that Heidegger's attention moves from one element to another at different times. The notion of a "turn" has already entered into the tradition of Heidegger scholarship; the usage of this word is legitimate, as long as it is understood that we cannot presume that we already know in what the turn consists, in any concrete sense. Perhaps the characterization of neither the ''developmentalists" nor those who, 4 like Krell, simply oppose them, is correct. The root of the problem, we maintain, lies in the polemical, and quite "unphenomenological" choice offered us: to defend the identity of the "matter itself" throughout Heidegger's career, and thus to be charged with having to find evidence that his "thought" never changes: or to take Heidegger's work as though a series of position-papers were being offered, so that his "philosophy" changes depending upon whether its focus is transcen­ dence, truth, or time. The question of the turn is, however, first of I!!! a textual issue: Through what changes of focus, transpositions, or reformulations are we conducted as we proceed along the vectors encoun­ tered in, and even constitutive of, Heidegger's texts? And the ques­ tion of unity would then no longer ask about the "unchanging content" of Heidegger's work, but about what fundamental inquiry, pursued with ever-deepening insistence, is responsible for precisely those changes.
Recommended publications
  • Reflexivity and Social Phenomenology Benjamin K
    UNF Digital Commons UNF Graduate Theses and Dissertations Student Scholarship 2011 Reflexivity and Social Phenomenology Benjamin K. Hoffman University of North Florida Suggested Citation Hoffman, Benjamin K., "Reflexivity and Social Phenomenology" (2011). UNF Graduate Theses and Dissertations. 130. https://digitalcommons.unf.edu/etd/130 This Master's Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at UNF Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in UNF Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of UNF Digital Commons. For more information, please contact Digital Projects. © 2011 All Rights Reserved Reflexivity and Social Phenomenology by Benjamin K. Hoffman A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Masters of Practical Philosophy and Applied Ethics UNIVERSITY OF NORTH FLORIDA COLLEGE OF ARTS AND SCIENCES July, 2011 CERTIFICATE OF APPROVAL Reflexivity and Social Phenomenology Ben Hoffman Date Signature Deleted (/~/!I ( J Signature Deleted Signature Deleted Erinn Gilson, Assistant Prof of Philosophy Signature Deleted Coordinator, Philosophy Dept MA Program Signature Deleted ~ 7 Hans-Her~ o{;g]ef Chairperson, Department of Philosophy Accepted for the College: Signature Deleted Barbara HJriC Dean of COlle{e of Arts and Sciences Accepted for the University: Signature Deleted Dean of Graduate School ii Abstract This thesis develops an account of human understanding on the basis of an analysis of German philosopher Martin Heidegger’s Being and Time, and in relation to the thought of the Kyoto School philosopher Watsuji Tetsurô. The aim is to describe shared human intelligibility as founded upon a historical tradition and maintained by concrete practices, and yet as expressed only by interpretive projections, and therefore always open to revision.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant As an Unfamiliar Source of Racism
    Philosophers on Race: Critical Essays Edited by Julie K. Ward, Tommy L. Lott Copyright © 2002 by Blackwell Publishers Ltd CHAPTER 8 Kant as an Unfamiliar Source of Racism ROBERT BERNASCONI 1 In 1972 Isaiah Berlin gave a lecture on “Kant as an Unfamiliar Source of National- ism”, which has recently been published in The Sense of Reality.1 The lecture began: At first sight nothing would seem more disparate than the idea of nationality and the sane, rational, liberal internationalism of the great Königsberg philosopher. Of all the influential thinkers of his day, Kant seems the most remote from the rise of nationalism. (SR, p. 232) Just as Berlin shows a connection between Kant and nationalism, I propose to do the same for Kant and racism. However, the form of Berlin’s argument is somewhat dif- ferent from mine. Berlin does not question the legitimacy of the image of Kant’s phi- losophy as “deeply rational and cosmopolitan” (SR, p. 244). Berlin’s interest is, rather, to show how “ideas turn into their opposites” (SR, p. 248). He has in mind what became of Kant’s ideas in Herder and Fichte. My thesis, by contrast, is that, in spite of Kant’s avowed cosmopolitanism that is evident in such essays as his “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose,” one also finds within his philosophy expres- sions of a virulent and theoretically based racism, at a time when scientific racism was still in its infancy. Although the blatant and unremitting racist declarations of Europeans at this time, like Edward Long’s History of Jamaica of 1776, are shocking and deplorable and call for further intellectual inquiry, some authors present a further puzzle that has a particular interest for philosophers and historians of ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Book Review: Gadamer's Ethics of Play: Hermeneutics and the Other
    Eastern Illinois University The Keep Faculty Research and Creative Activity Kinesiology, Sport & Recreation January 2013 Book Review: Gadamer’s Ethics of Play: Hermeneutics and the Other Chad R. Carlson Eastern Illinois University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://thekeep.eiu.edu/kss_fac Part of the Kinesiology Commons Recommended Citation Carlson, Chad R., "Book Review: Gadamer’s Ethics of Play: Hermeneutics and the Other" (2013). Faculty Research and Creative Activity. 19. https://thekeep.eiu.edu/kss_fac/19 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Kinesiology, Sport & Recreation at The Keep. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Research and Creative Activity by an authorized administrator of The Keep. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEW Chad Carlson Eastern Illinois University Gadamer’s ethics of play: Hermeneutics and the other, by Monica Vilhauer, Lanham, MD, Lexington Books, 2010, 166 pp., £37 (hardback), ISBN 978-0739139141 As a naıve graduate student, I remember signing up for a course in the Philosophy Department entitled, ‘Art and Truth’. Although I was studying sport and play in a different department, I was intrigued by the title – art seemed closely related to play and sport in the landscape of human experiences. Further, the course was offered at a convenient time and it fulfilled a deficiency I had toward graduation. Unfortunately, I had no idea what I was getting into. The course readings, which included Martin Heidegger, Friedrich Nietzsche, Maurice Merleau- Ponty, Jacques Derrida, Jurgen Habermas, and, most prominently, Hans-Georg Gadamer, seemed so dense that they necessitated long hours of introduction and prior training that I did not have.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Indication, Philosophy, and Theology: Bonhoeffer's Critique of Heidegger
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 24 Issue 2 Article 5 4-1-2007 Formal Indication, Philosophy, and Theology: Bonhoeffer's Critique of Heidegger Brian Gregor Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Gregor, Brian (2007) "Formal Indication, Philosophy, and Theology: Bonhoeffer's Critique of Heidegger," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 24 : Iss. 2 , Article 5. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil200724227 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol24/iss2/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. FORMAL INDICATION, PHILOSOPHY, AND THEOLOGY: BONHOEFFER’S CRITIQUE OF HEIDEGGER Brian Gregor This paper examines Heidegger’s account of the proper relation between philosophy and theology, and Dietrich Bonhoeff er’s critique thereof. Part I outlines Heidegger’s proposal for this relationship in his lecture “Phe- nomenology and Theology,” where he suggests that philosophy might aid theology by means of ‘formal indication.’ In that context Heidegger never articulates what formal indication is, so Part II exposits this obscure notion by looking at its treatment in Heidegger’s early lecture courses, as well as its roots in Husserl. Part III presents Bonhoeff er’s theological response, which challenges Heidegger’s att empt to maintain a neutral ontology that remains unaff ected by both sin and faith.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger, Being and Time
    Heidegger's Being and Time 1 Karsten Harries Heidegger's Being and Time Seminar Notes Spring Semester 2014 Yale University Heidegger's Being and Time 2 Copyright Karsten Harries [email protected] Heidegger's Being and Time 3 Contents 1. Introduction 4 2. Ontology and Fundamental Ontology 16 3. Methodological Considerations 30 4. Being-in-the-World 43 5. The World 55 6. Who am I? 69 7. Understanding, Interpretation, Language 82 8. Care and Truth 96 9. The Entirety of Dasein 113 10. Conscience, Guilt, Resolve 128 11. Time and Subjectivity 145 12. History and the Hero 158 13. Conclusion 169 Heidegger's Being and Time 4 1. Introduction 1 In this seminar I shall be concerned with Heidegger's Being and Time. I shall refer to other works by Heidegger, but the discussion will center on Being and Time. In reading the book, some of you, especially those with a reading knowledge of German, may find the lectures of the twenties helpful, which have appeared now as volumes of the Gesamtausgabe. Many of these have by now been translated. I am thinking especially of GA 17 Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung (1923/24); Introduction to Phenomenological Research, trans. Daniel O. Dahlstrom (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 2005) GA 20 Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (1925); History of the Concept of Time, trans. Theodore Kisiel (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1985) GA 21 Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit (1925/26). Logic: The Question of Truth, trans. Thomas Sheehan GA 24 Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (1927); The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Westphalia: Rethinking Fundamental Ontology in IR Written by Andreas Aagaard Nohr
    Beyond Westphalia: Rethinking Fundamental Ontology in IR Written by Andreas Aagaard Nohr This PDF is auto-generated for reference only. As such, it may contain some conversion errors and/or missing information. For all formal use please refer to the official version on the website, as linked below. Beyond Westphalia: Rethinking Fundamental Ontology in IR https://www.e-ir.info/2012/07/05/beyond-westphalia-rethinking-fundamental-ontology-in-ir/ ANDREAS AAGAARD NOHR, JUL 5 2012 ‘Our task is to broaden our reasoning to make it capable of grasping what, in ourselves and others, precedes and exceeds reason’ – Maurice Merleau-Ponty[1] The Western philosophical tradition has been entrenched in a particular understanding of human beings by Plato’s love for theory. Theory, the notion that the universe can be understood in a detached and abstract way, by finding the principles that underlie the abundance of phenomena was surely powerful. And in effect, Plato held that we could have a theory of everything, even human beings and their relation to the world.[2] Man had to crawl out of the cave, where his existence had been meek shadow imagery. To be sure, this means that Plato had an implicit theory of how human beings relate to things. As such, the tradition has been build on the basic understanding of human beings as subjects contemplating, or relating to, objects. Man is a cogito, a thinking subject – a rational animal – in a world of objects. The consequence of this assumption is a categorical split between the mind and the world. So much becomes clear in the philosophy of René Descartes, who tried to doubt everything until there was only one thing he could not doubt: his own existence.
    [Show full text]
  • University of California Santa Cruz Heidegger
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA CRUZ HEIDEGGER: ONTOLOGICAL POLITICS TO TECHNOLOGICAL POLITICS A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in PHILOSOPHY by Javier Cardoza-Kon June 2014 The dissertation of Javier Cardoza-Kon is approved: ____________________________________ Professor David C. Hoy, chair ____________________________________ Professor Abraham Stone ____________________________________ Carlos A. Sanchez, Ph.D. _____________________________ Tyrus Miller Vice Provost and Dean of Graduate Studies Copyright © by Javier Cardoza-Kon 2014 Table of Contents Abstract. iv Dedication. v Introduction. 1 Chapter 1: Cultural Identity and Two Politics. 14 Chapter 2: Polemos, Auseinandersetzung, and Unconcealment. 50 Chapter 3: Auseiandersetzung, Nietzsche, and the Politics of Nihilism. 77 Chapter 4: Technology and We Late-Moderns. 113 Conclusion: Heidegger’s in the Contemporary World. 160 Bibliography and Abbreviations of Cited Material 173 iii Abstract Heidegger: Ontological Politics to Technological Politics. By Javier Cardoza-Kon As Heidegger himself has done with Nietzsche in claiming that he will articulate what Nietzsche meant but never said metaphysically, I also do with Heidegger in terms of politics. On my reading there are two kinds of politics in Heidegger’s middle and late thought that are, for the most part, murky and confused. There is a politics of ontology the deals with the encountering and articulating of what beings are and what Being itself is. There is also a politics on the more familiar level of societies and the policies that different groups establish and follow. It is in terms of the second type of politics that Heidegger is most often attacked, and for good reason.
    [Show full text]
  • The Supplement
    3 Supplement Robert Bernasconi In Of Grammatology Derrida took up the term supplément from his reading of both Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Claude Lévi-Strauss and used it to formulate what he called “the logic of supplementarity” (G: 144–45). Derrida returned to Lévi-Strauss’s use of the word “supplement” in “Structure, Sign and Play” (WD: 289) and in Given Time (GT: 66–77), but I will focus here on Derrida’s reading of this word in Rousseau’s Confessions, Discourse on the Origin and Foundation of Inequality among Men,andEssay on the Origin of Languages because his reading of Rousseau has proved so powerful and because the logic of supple- mentarity is better illustrated than generalised. As Derrida observed, Rousseau in these works employed binary oppositions: nature versus society, passion versus need, south versus north, and, most significantly for Derrida in the late 1960s, speech versus writing. In the course of declaring these oppositions Rousseau can be found writing the ambiguous term supplément and its cognates into his narratives. The supplement is an addition from the outside, but it can also be understood as supplying what is missing and in this way is already inscribed within that to which it is added. In this way the word, “supplement” seems to account for “the strange unity” of two gestures: “on the side of experience, a recourse to literature as appropriation of presence, that is to say, … of Nature; on the side of theory, an indict- ment against the negativity of the letter, in which must be read the degeneracy of culture and the disruption of the community” (G: 144).
    [Show full text]
  • The Hermeneutical Circle Or the Hermeneutical Spiral?
    Intl. J. Humanities (2008) Vol. 15 ( 2): ( 99 - 111 ) The Hermeneutical Circle or the Hermeneutical Spiral? Mohammad Motahari 1 Received: 9/6/2007 Accept: 26/8/2007 Abstract The problem of the hermeneutical circle is one of the contentious issues in philosophical hermeneutics. This paper, begins with focusing on the question as to whether what hermeneuts mean by a hermeneutical circle is in fact a real circle with no analogical sense involved . Recognizing that this problem is not confined to the relation between part and whole, this study confine s itse lf to explor e the problem of the hermeneutical circle with regard to the circularity between part and whole in a sentence. I will argue that, as far as the interdependence between part and whole of a sentence is concerned, there is no real circularity betw een them . This will be followed by scrutinizing the source of such a misunderstanding, i.e. , the circular interdependence between understanding the part and the whole of a sentence . I will Downloaded from eijh.modares.ac.ir at 23:17 IRST on Friday September 24th 2021 present my analy sis through a critical reading of two contemporary hermeneuts , Eric Donald Hirsch and Graeme Nicholson, even though both are on the right track in questioning the existence of such a circle in the first place . The argument presented could apply to contexts well beyond that of the circularity between part and whole in a sentence. Keywords: Philosophical Hermeneutics, Hermeneutical Circle, Sentence , Part and Whole, Frederick Schleiermacher, Hans -Georg Gadamer, Eric Hirsch, Graeme Nicholson. 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Fanon's Black Skin, White Masks on Race Consciousness by Carolyn
    Fanon’s Black Skin, White Masks on Race Consciousness by Carolyn Cusick, Vanderbilt University Readers of Fanon’s Black Skin, White Masks often disagree about whether or not Fanon is arguing for or against the perpetuation of racial categories.1 One interpretation suggests that Fanon’s sociogenic analysis demonstrates the inevitability, if not the necessity, of racial categories. These readers, namely Kathryn Gines in “Fanon and Sartre 50 Years Later: To Retain or Reject the Concept of Race”2 focus on Chapter Five, “The Lived Experience of the Black.” Originally published as a response to Sartre’s “Black Orpheus,” Fanon’s essay introduced Léopold Senghor’s anthology of négritude poetry. In “Black Orpheus” Sartre claims that the négritude movement is essential for a new kind of humanism that will free us from racist thinking, free us from a world divided by race: The unity which will come eventually, bringing all oppressed peoples together in the same struggle, must be preceded in the colonies by what I shall call the moment of separation or negativity: this anti-racist racism is the only road that will lead to the abolition of racial differences.3 Fanon’s response is direct: “Jean-Paul Sartre, in this work, has destroyed black zeal. … I needed not to know. This struggle, this new decline had to take on an aspect of completeness.”4 Sartre’s declaring an end to racialism undermines the power of experiencing blackness positively; rendering it as a temporary move on the way to universal humanism makes it almost powerless. To succeed, négritude has to be able to be experienced as absolute.
    [Show full text]
  • Ontology and Ethics at the Intersection of Phenomenology and Environmental Philosophy*
    Inquiry, 47, 380–412 Ontology and Ethics at the Intersection of Phenomenology and Environmental Philosophy* Iain Thomson University of New Mexico The idea inspiring the eco-phenomenological movement is that phenomenology can help remedy our environmental crisis by uprooting and replacing environmentally- destructive ethical and metaphysical presuppositions inherited from modern philosophy. Eco-phenomenology’s critiques of subject/object dualism and the fact/value divide are sketched and its positive alternatives examined. Two competing approaches are discerned within the eco-phenomenological movement: Nietzscheans and Husserlians propose a naturalistic ethical realism in which good and bad are ultimately matters of fact, and values should be grounded in these proto- ethical facts; Heideggerians and Levinasians articulate a transcendental ethical realism according to which we discover what really matters when we are appropriately open to the environment, but what we thereby discover is a transcendental source of meaning that cannot be reduced to facts, values, or entities of any kind. These two species of ethical realism generate different kinds of ethical perfectionism: naturalistic ethical realism yields an eco-centric perfectionism which stresses the flourishing of life in general; transcendental ethical realism leads to a more ‘humanistic’ perfectionism which emphasizes the cultivation of distinctive traits of Dasein. Both approaches are examined, and the Heideggerian strand of the humanistic approach defended, since it approaches the best elements of the eco-centric view while avoiding its problematic ontological assumptions and anti-humanistic implications. I. Introduction: Uncovering the Conceptual Roots of Environmental Devastation What happens when you cross phenomenology with environmental philoso- phy? According to the editors of Eco-Phenomenology: Back to the Earth Itself, you get an important interdisciplinary movement.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]