University of California Santa Cruz Heidegger

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

University of California Santa Cruz Heidegger UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA CRUZ HEIDEGGER: ONTOLOGICAL POLITICS TO TECHNOLOGICAL POLITICS A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in PHILOSOPHY by Javier Cardoza-Kon June 2014 The dissertation of Javier Cardoza-Kon is approved: ____________________________________ Professor David C. Hoy, chair ____________________________________ Professor Abraham Stone ____________________________________ Carlos A. Sanchez, Ph.D. _____________________________ Tyrus Miller Vice Provost and Dean of Graduate Studies Copyright © by Javier Cardoza-Kon 2014 Table of Contents Abstract. iv Dedication. v Introduction. 1 Chapter 1: Cultural Identity and Two Politics. 14 Chapter 2: Polemos, Auseinandersetzung, and Unconcealment. 50 Chapter 3: Auseiandersetzung, Nietzsche, and the Politics of Nihilism. 77 Chapter 4: Technology and We Late-Moderns. 113 Conclusion: Heidegger’s in the Contemporary World. 160 Bibliography and Abbreviations of Cited Material 173 iii Abstract Heidegger: Ontological Politics to Technological Politics. By Javier Cardoza-Kon As Heidegger himself has done with Nietzsche in claiming that he will articulate what Nietzsche meant but never said metaphysically, I also do with Heidegger in terms of politics. On my reading there are two kinds of politics in Heidegger’s middle and late thought that are, for the most part, murky and confused. There is a politics of ontology the deals with the encountering and articulating of what beings are and what Being itself is. There is also a politics on the more familiar level of societies and the policies that different groups establish and follow. It is in terms of the second type of politics that Heidegger is most often attacked, and for good reason. My dissertation will motivate an understanding of Dasein and Heidegger’s thought beyond Dasein in terms of these two types of politics. This will serve to bring Heidegger’s “turning” and eventual ruminations on technology into focus. I examine what it was in the confused and unarticulated relation between the two types of politics that not only allowed for his foray into Nazism, but also informed his Machiavellian views on technology. I conclude with an examination of contemporary issues in politics by putting Heidegger into a dialogue with Gianni Vattimo concerning the issues of violence, liberty, and the proliferation of 3-D printed firearms in the U.S. iv Dedication. I would like to dedicate this dissertation to Xenia Gilg, David Hoy, Carlos Sanchez, and my mother Linda for believing in me and helping to make it possible for me to pursue this noble path. Thank all of you from the bottom of my heart. Acknowledgements Abraham Stone for your help with language translations, reading Heidegger’s Nietzsche, and your comments and support. Hans Sluga for working on a paper with me on Greek politics and Heidegger, which became part of this dissertation. Gopal Balakrishnan for encouraging me to find the “space” of Heidegger’s thought and for reading Heidegger’s Nietzsche with me. Daniel Guevara and Paul Roth for your continual support, suggestions, and encouragement throughout my time at UCSC. Bert Dreyfus for allowing me to sit in on your courses. v Introduction “When we understand thinking to be the distinctive characteristic of man, we remind ourselves of a belonging together that concerns man and Being. Immediately we find ourselves grappling with the questions: What does Being mean? Who, or what, is man?” (I&D, 30) Following the seminal work Being and Time Heidegger is said to go through a “turning” (die Kehre) that sees him leaving behind the project he calls “fundamental ontology,” or the question of the “meaning of Being.” Through his so-called middle period in the 1930s and through the early 1940s, Heidegger’s ontological engagement becomes centered on what he calls the “truth of Being,” which is articulated as a history of Western metaphysics. Ultimately, this history of metaphysics manifests itself in Heidegger’s “late period” as “technology.” It is also during the middle period that Heidegger struggles with his unfortunate foray into Nazi politics. This is a popular theme in Heidegger scholarship with spirited arguments on all sides. Some interpretations attempt to separate Heidegger’s philosophy from his Nazi involvement while others seek to dismiss Heidegger’s post- Being and Time work altogether, while still others wish to defend Heidegger and still others have just wanted to explore and 1 document his involvement.1 While Heidegger’s political involvements with Nazism remain inexcusable, his political views and involvements are integral to understanding the “turning” and his later thought on technology as the manifestation of the final metaphysics of the Platonic legacy, which he calls the history of Being. With this in mind, it becomes apparent that even the lauded and controversial essay “The Question Concerning Technology” is rich with political overtones and criticisms that reframe the circumstances under which the truth of Being presents itself. As Heidegger himself has done with Nietzsche in claiming that he will articulate what Nietzsche meant but never said metaphysically, I also will do with Heidegger in terms of politics. On my reading there are two kinds of politics in Heidegger’s thought that are, for the most part, murky and confused. There is a politics of ontology the deals with the encountering and articulating what beings are and what Being itself is. There is also a politics on the more familiar level of societies and the policies that different groups establish and follow. It is in terms of the second type of politics that Heidegger is most often attacked, and for good reason. In the following I will motivate an understanding of Heidegger’s middle and late 1 For condemnation see, first, the most controversial and, arguably, most one-sided reading of Heidegger, Heidegger and Nazism by Victor Farias. A close second is Emmanuel Faye’s Heidegger: the Introduction of Nazism to Philosophy in Light of the Unpublished Seminars 1933-1935, Herman Phillipse, Heidegger’s Philosophy of Being: A Critical Interpretation. Jürgen Habermas offers perhaps the most compelling criticism of Heidegger and his engagement with Nazism in The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. There is also the compelling criticism levied by Levinas. See Entre Nous for example. There are those who wish to defend: Julian Young Heidegger: Philosophy, Nazism. Those who “defend” via the claim that Heidegger had no choice in the matter of National Socialism, Iain Thomson Heidegger On Ontotheology. And there are those who wish to explore and inform the discussion: Hans Sluga, Heidegger’s Crisis and Richard Wolin, The Heidegger Controversy: A Critical Reader and Hugo Ott, Heidegger: a Political Life. Michael Zimmerman, Heidegger’s Confrontation with Modernity. 2 thought in terms of these two types of politics. This will serve to bring Heidegger’s turning and eventual ruminations on technology into focus. In the end I will examine what it was in the confused and unarticulated relation between the two types of politics that not only allowed for his foray into Nazism, but also informed his Machiavellian views on technology and what might be done to counterbalance them. This will allow for an inquiry in to the relevance of Heidegger’s political thought in today’s situation. At the beginning of Heidegger’s middle period (roughly 1928 to 1946) Heidegger begins to understand that his work up to that point falls within the selfsame modernist framework that he is struggling to free his thought of. At this time he also becomes the first National Socialist Rector of Freiburg University.2 This is the initial intersection between his politics and philosophy. In fact, it is in the “Rectoral Address” that we find Heidegger explicitly identifying the importance and task of philosophy as intertwined with politics.3 As Heidegger moves through this period his fundamental questioning about Being shifts to that of the “truth of Being.” This shift begins with a series of essays between 1929-1931 following Being and Time in which he begins to understand the history of metaphysics since Plato as the history of an “error” – echoing Nietzsche in his understanding of Plato’s categories of “truth” as relegated to the “supransensory” world. This contrasts the pre-Platonic notion of truth as a-lētheia that describes the categories of Being based on the encounters 2 Heidegger tries to deny this in the posthumously published Der Spiegel interview. 3 For an extensive discussion on this see Richard Wolin’s Politics of Being and Karl Löwith’s “The Political Implications of Heidegger’s Existentialism.” 3 (“uncovering” “unconcealing” or “revealing”) of mankind with his surroundings, which has been displaced by the Platonic forms.4 This marks the beginning of Heidegger’s attempt to find a way to abandon the modernist categories of truth in terms of objective “correctness” and to recall the early conception of Greek “truth” as alētheia – a recollection that he sees as important in his overall project of articulating how mankind might come back into an open relationship with Being. This is expressed by Heidegger in his 1935 lectures that were later published as An Introduction to Metaphysics. At this time Heidegger noted a metaphysical “heritage” that begins with the Greeks and is expressed in terms of the polis. This philosophical and political work is an attempt to examine the historical metaphysical “inception” of the West in an examination of the Greeks and their ontological understanding. Essentially, an examination of the beginning of Western metaphysical understanding as the bedrock upon which all Western history has followed would inform Heidegger’s project to “reground” the ontologically depraved West that he finds himself in. For Heidegger the question of what the truth of Being is forms the key to understanding the history of metaphysics that he sees as the foundation of the catastrophic technological and political machinations of mid-twentieth century world politics and events.
Recommended publications
  • Heidegger, Being and Time
    Heidegger's Being and Time 1 Karsten Harries Heidegger's Being and Time Seminar Notes Spring Semester 2014 Yale University Heidegger's Being and Time 2 Copyright Karsten Harries [email protected] Heidegger's Being and Time 3 Contents 1. Introduction 4 2. Ontology and Fundamental Ontology 16 3. Methodological Considerations 30 4. Being-in-the-World 43 5. The World 55 6. Who am I? 69 7. Understanding, Interpretation, Language 82 8. Care and Truth 96 9. The Entirety of Dasein 113 10. Conscience, Guilt, Resolve 128 11. Time and Subjectivity 145 12. History and the Hero 158 13. Conclusion 169 Heidegger's Being and Time 4 1. Introduction 1 In this seminar I shall be concerned with Heidegger's Being and Time. I shall refer to other works by Heidegger, but the discussion will center on Being and Time. In reading the book, some of you, especially those with a reading knowledge of German, may find the lectures of the twenties helpful, which have appeared now as volumes of the Gesamtausgabe. Many of these have by now been translated. I am thinking especially of GA 17 Einführung in die phänomenologische Forschung (1923/24); Introduction to Phenomenological Research, trans. Daniel O. Dahlstrom (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 2005) GA 20 Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (1925); History of the Concept of Time, trans. Theodore Kisiel (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 1985) GA 21 Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit (1925/26). Logic: The Question of Truth, trans. Thomas Sheehan GA 24 Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (1927); The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Westphalia: Rethinking Fundamental Ontology in IR Written by Andreas Aagaard Nohr
    Beyond Westphalia: Rethinking Fundamental Ontology in IR Written by Andreas Aagaard Nohr This PDF is auto-generated for reference only. As such, it may contain some conversion errors and/or missing information. For all formal use please refer to the official version on the website, as linked below. Beyond Westphalia: Rethinking Fundamental Ontology in IR https://www.e-ir.info/2012/07/05/beyond-westphalia-rethinking-fundamental-ontology-in-ir/ ANDREAS AAGAARD NOHR, JUL 5 2012 ‘Our task is to broaden our reasoning to make it capable of grasping what, in ourselves and others, precedes and exceeds reason’ – Maurice Merleau-Ponty[1] The Western philosophical tradition has been entrenched in a particular understanding of human beings by Plato’s love for theory. Theory, the notion that the universe can be understood in a detached and abstract way, by finding the principles that underlie the abundance of phenomena was surely powerful. And in effect, Plato held that we could have a theory of everything, even human beings and their relation to the world.[2] Man had to crawl out of the cave, where his existence had been meek shadow imagery. To be sure, this means that Plato had an implicit theory of how human beings relate to things. As such, the tradition has been build on the basic understanding of human beings as subjects contemplating, or relating to, objects. Man is a cogito, a thinking subject – a rational animal – in a world of objects. The consequence of this assumption is a categorical split between the mind and the world. So much becomes clear in the philosophy of René Descartes, who tried to doubt everything until there was only one thing he could not doubt: his own existence.
    [Show full text]
  • Ontology and Ethics at the Intersection of Phenomenology and Environmental Philosophy*
    Inquiry, 47, 380–412 Ontology and Ethics at the Intersection of Phenomenology and Environmental Philosophy* Iain Thomson University of New Mexico The idea inspiring the eco-phenomenological movement is that phenomenology can help remedy our environmental crisis by uprooting and replacing environmentally- destructive ethical and metaphysical presuppositions inherited from modern philosophy. Eco-phenomenology’s critiques of subject/object dualism and the fact/value divide are sketched and its positive alternatives examined. Two competing approaches are discerned within the eco-phenomenological movement: Nietzscheans and Husserlians propose a naturalistic ethical realism in which good and bad are ultimately matters of fact, and values should be grounded in these proto- ethical facts; Heideggerians and Levinasians articulate a transcendental ethical realism according to which we discover what really matters when we are appropriately open to the environment, but what we thereby discover is a transcendental source of meaning that cannot be reduced to facts, values, or entities of any kind. These two species of ethical realism generate different kinds of ethical perfectionism: naturalistic ethical realism yields an eco-centric perfectionism which stresses the flourishing of life in general; transcendental ethical realism leads to a more ‘humanistic’ perfectionism which emphasizes the cultivation of distinctive traits of Dasein. Both approaches are examined, and the Heideggerian strand of the humanistic approach defended, since it approaches the best elements of the eco-centric view while avoiding its problematic ontological assumptions and anti-humanistic implications. I. Introduction: Uncovering the Conceptual Roots of Environmental Devastation What happens when you cross phenomenology with environmental philoso- phy? According to the editors of Eco-Phenomenology: Back to the Earth Itself, you get an important interdisciplinary movement.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger's Basic Assumptions
    Daniel O. Dahlstrom Heidegger’s Basic Assumptions If we improve our understanding of ordinary talk of physical things, it will not be by reducing that talk to a more familiar idiom; there is none. It will be by clarifying the connections, causal or otherwise, between ordinary talk of physical things and various further matters, which in turn we grasp with help of ordinary talk of physical things. W. V. O. Quine, Word and Object1 In Being and Time Heidegger sets out from three assumptions: first, that we generally have some understanding of what it means to be, some sense of being; second, that this understanding matters to us and, in an essential way, constitutes our manner of being; and third, that we are capable of giving an appropriate analysis or interpretation of this understanding.2 These are by no means the only suppositions driving the project begun in Being and Time but they certainly figure among its most basic assumptions. The first of these assumptions is Heidegger’s „preontological“ and „preexistential“ assumption, the second his „existential“ assumption, and the third his „ontological“ assumption. These basic assumptions, moreover, exhibit an order that is equally basic to Heidegger’s project at the time. The existential assumption presupposes the preontological assumption and his fundamental ontology presupposes the existential character of our preontological sense of being. Despite an increasing appreciation of the relevance of many of Heidegger’s investigations to concerns of contemporary analytic philosophers, these basic assumptions continue to be roundly viewed with a mixture of suspicion and bemusement. It would be extremely difficult – and no attempt will be made here – to give an adequate explanation of all the reasons for this recalcitrance.
    [Show full text]
  • HAAS, ALEXANDER, MA August 2020
    HAAS, ALEXANDER, M.A. August 2020 PHILOSOPHY MARION, HEIDEGGER, AND THE QUESTION OF GIVENNESS (74 pp.) Thesis Advisor: Gina Zavota In Being Given, Jean-Luc Marion claims that Heidegger errs in subordinating the givenness of phenomena to Ereignis, unduly restricting the ways in which phenomena can be said to “give themselves”. The problem, however, is that without this stricture, we are unable to make certain distinctions that are indispensable for understanding phenomena in the diversity of their appearing. Take, for example, technological phenomena (e.g., televisions, radios, computers, etc.) On Marion’s account, these phenomena give themselves; show themselves insofar as they give themselves. But is this really giving, or instead, a kind of intrusion, a permeating of our space by technological phenomena? What Marion is missing, is a robust account of the context, or better, the locus of apparition that allows us to differentiate the ways in which phenomena show up. I will argue that Heidegger’s notion of Ereignis is such a locus. MARION, HEIDEGGER, AND THE QUESTION OF GIVENNESS A thesis submitted To Kent State University in partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Alexander Haas August 2020 © Copyright All rights reserved Except for previously published materials Thesis written by Alexander Haas B.A., Kent State University, 2015 M.A. Kent State University, 2020 Approved by _______________________________, Advisor Gina Zavota _______________________________, Chair, Department of Philosophy Michael Byron
    [Show full text]
  • Martin Heidegger on Aletheia (Truth) As Unconcealment
    Martin Heidegger on Aletheia (Truth) as Unconcealment https://www.ontology.co/heidegger-aletheia.htm Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Martin Heidegger on Aletheia (Truth) as Unconcealment PRELIMINARY NOTE In its initial form this section will offer five pages on Martin Heidegger (the first two are contributions to the History of Truth): 1) Heidegger's contributions to the interpretation of the Greek word for Truth (Aletheia) as Unconcealment and to the history of his translation in Latin as Veritas; 2) An annotated bibliography of Heidegger's texts on Aletheia and a selection of critical studies; 3) Heidegger's contributions to the interpretation of the History of Metaphysics as Ontotheology; 4) An annotated bibliography of Heidegger's texts on the History of Metaphysics as Ontotheology and a selection of critical studies; 5) A complete list of Heidegger's German works published in the Gesamtausgabe (Collected Works Edition). INTRODUCTION "We come now to a decisive point in Heidegger's development. The effort to ground metaphysics (fundamental ontology) began as a search to illuminate the intrinsic correlation between the Being-process as such and the finitude of the being that comprehends it, sc. There-being. The first step (Sein und Zeit) was to analyse There-being phenomenologically in order to find in the pre-ontic comprehension of Being some means of discerning the sense of Being. Subsequently the author has become more and more preoccupied with Being itself, but chiefly in terms of the problem of truth, since the sense of Being is its truth. The growing importance of the problematic of truth is discernible in all of the works that followed SZ and culminates now in the essay "On the Essence of Truth," where Heidegger thematizes the problem, retaining as intrinsic to it the 1 di 10 05/01/2019, 18:26 Martin Heidegger on Aletheia (Truth) as Unconcealment https://www.ontology.co/heidegger-aletheia.htm problem of finitude, sc.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger's Project
    Heidegger’s Project 7 1 Heidegger’s Project In his 1935 summer semester lecture course at the University of Freiburg, entitled “Introduction to Metaphysics,” Heidegger asks a seemingly innocuous question: “How does it stand with being?,” or, translated in a colloquial sense: “How’s it going with being?” (IM, 41)1 The answer is: not well. Today, humankind is consumed by an instrumental relationship with beings; we have closed off other world- views, forcing all beings—including humans—to show up or reveal themselves in only one way, as objects to be effi ciently manipulated and controlled. The prognosis, according to Heidegger, is bleak. In an oft-quoted passage from these lectures, he gives his assessment: The spiritual decline of the earth has progressed so far that people are in danger of losing their last spiritual strength, the strength that makes it possible even to see the decline and to appraise it as such. This simple observation has nothing to do with cultural pessimism—nor with any opti- mism either, of course; for the darkening of the world, the fl ight of the gods, the destruction of the earth, the reduc- tion of human beings into a mass, the hatred and mistrust of everything creative and free has already reached such proportions throughout the whole earth that such childish categories as pessimism and optimism have become laugh- able. (IM, 40–41) Heidegger refers to this modern predicament as “nihilism.” Nihil- ism shows itself when the “question of being” (Seinsfrage) is forgotten and humankind is concerned with the world only as a vast storehouse of beings to be used.
    [Show full text]
  • The Sporting Exploration of the World: Toward a Fundamental Ontology of the Sporting Human Being
    This file was dowloaded from the institutional repository Brage NIH - brage.bibsys.no/nih Breivik, G. (2019). The Sporting Exploration of the World: Toward a Fundamental Ontology of the Sporting Human Being. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy, 14(2), 146-162 Dette er siste tekst-versjon av artikkelen, og den kan inneholde små forskjeller fra forlagets pdf-versjon. Forlagets pdf-versjon finner du her: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2019.1572214 This is the final text version of the article, and it may contain minor differences from the journal's pdf version. The original publication is available here: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17511321.2019.1572214 The sporting exploration of the world; towards a fundamental ontology of the sporting human being ABSTRACT My goal in this article is to give a portrait of how modern sport philosophy, which started in 1972, developed from relatively narrow paradigmatic borders to become a diverse and multi- paradigmatic international discipline. This development has included several changes but also some continuity. I identify three main tenets that may be viable in the future. One is to focus on the traditional sport philosophical paradigm, which had an ambition to identify the essence of sport. A second option is to develop more specific approaches, focusing on single sports or types of sport, like football or climbing. A third alternative is to develop a philosophy, not only of sport but of ‘homo movens’, studying the moving human being in different environmental and socio-cultural contexts. All three options are viable and should be welcomed. KEYWORDS: Sport philosophy, historical development, diversification, future, identity Introduction My perspective in this article will be to look at sport and other physical activities as a way of exploring and experimenting with the environing world.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger on the Unity of Metaphysics and The
    Final Draft Please do not cite without permission. HEIDEGGER ON THE UNITY OF METAPHYSICS AND THE METHOD OF BEING AND TIME Gilad Nir Forthcoming in The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 74: 3 (March 2021). Abstract The fundamental error of the metaphysical tradition, according to Heidegger, is the subordination of general ontology to the ontology of a special, exemplary entity (God, the soul, etc.). But Being and Time itself treats one kind of entity as exemplary, namely Dasein. Does this mean that Heidegger fails to free himself from the kind of metaphysics that he sought to criticize? To show how he avoids this charge I propose to examine the parallels between the methodology of Being and Time and the methodology Heidegger ascribes to Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Heidegger takes the virtue of Aristotle’s inquiry to reside in the way he resists the subordination of general to special ontology: Aristotle was guided by a “double concept” of metaphysics, pursued two irreducibly distinct methods of inquiry, and avoided the temptation to unite them. In proposing to similarly pursue a “double task” in Being and Time Heidegger seeks to apply this insight to his own work. Alongside the task of fundamental ontology, Heidegger spells out the shape of a second task, Destruktion, understood as a historical critique that traces ontological concepts back to their ontic roots. But Destruktion is not a mere addendum to fundamental ontology; the two tasks are meant to counterbalance one another and thereby prevent the collapse of the ontological difference between being and beings. Indeed, Heidegger proposes to apply Destruktion to the results of his own fundamental ontology.
    [Show full text]
  • Making Sense of Heidegger NEW HEIDEGGER RESEARCH
    Making Sense of Heidegger NEW HEIDEGGER RESEARCH Series Editors Gregory Fried, Professor of Philosophy, Suffolk University, USA Richard Polt, Professor of Philosophy, Xavier University, USA The New Heidegger Research series promotes informed and critical dialogue that breaks new philosophical ground by taking into account the full range of Heidegger’s thought, as well as the enduring questions raised by his work. Making Sense of Heidegger: A Paradigm Shift, Thomas Sheehan After the Greeks, Laurence Paul Hemming (forthcoming) Heidegger and the Environment, Casey Rentmeester (forthcoming) Making Sense of Heidegger A Paradigm Shift Thomas Sheehan London • New York Published by Rowman & Littlefield International Ltd. Unit A, Whitacre Mews, 26-34 Stannary Street, London SE11 4AB www.rowmaninternational.com Rowman & Littlefield International Ltd. is an affiliate of Rowman & Littlefield 4501 Forbes Boulevard, Suite 200, Lanham, Maryland 20706, USA With additional offices in Boulder, New York, Toronto (Canada), and Plymouth (UK) www.rowman.com Copyright © 2015 by Thomas Sheehan All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any electronic or mechanical means, including information storage and retrieval systems, without written permission from the publisher, except by a reviewer who may quote passages in a review. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN: HB 978-1-78348-118-7 PB 978-1-78348-119-4 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Sheehan, Thomas. Making sense of Heidegger : a paradigm shift / Thomas Sheehan. pages cm. — (New Heidegger research) Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 978-1-78348-118-7 (cloth : alk.
    [Show full text]
  • The Overturning of Heidegger's Fundamental Ontology
    *Author’s manuscript of paper published in the Journal of Philosophical Research, 2016: https://www.pdcnet.org/jpr/content/jpr_2016_0999_8_17_88 The Overturning of Heidegger’s Fundamental Ontology James Osborn [email protected] Abstract: In this paper I argue that the central issue in Heidegger’s path of thought from Being and Time to Contributions and beyond is what he will later call “the matter itself”: neither the meaning of being nor the analysis of Dasein but a transformational encounter in the margins of fundamental ontology. Heidegger’s account of temporality and transcendence from the late 1920s is a clue to the transformation, but it is not until the completion of fundamental ontology in the naming of ontological difference that he arrives at a crisis which performs the transformation and announces the “overturning.” This interpretation revolves around a reading of Heidegger’s 1929 treatise “On the Essence of Ground” in which the text and subsequent marginal notes prepare the transition from Being and Time to Contributions, from Sein to Seyn, and from ontological difference to its appropriation. Thus we find that the language of Ereignis beginning in the 1930s and whatever we might call the “turn” signal the doing of justice to the original task from Being and Time. 1 THE OVERTURNING I would say that [Being and Time] is not an advertisement for a new panacea which one could or should try out, but is the name for a task, for a way of working whereby we can perhaps once again become worthy of venturing a confrontation with real philosophy in its core.
    [Show full text]