Theories of Consciousness: an Introduction and Assessment/William Seager

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Theories of Consciousness: an Introduction and Assessment/William Seager THEORIES OF CONSCIOUSNESS “This is a fine book, a fascinating set of discussions of an extremely interesting area.” John Leslie, University of Guelph “This is an excellent survey of recent theories of consciousness.” Barry Loewer, Rutgers University The most remarkable fact about the universe is that certain parts of it are conscious. Somehow nature has managed to pull the rabbit of experience out of a hat made of mere matter. Theories of Consciousness explores a number of ways to understand consciousness and its place in the physical world. Spectacularly diverse, the spectrum of theories ranges from those that identify consciousness with particular brain processes to those that seemingly deny that consciousness even exists. The attempt to understand consciousness is only as old as the scientific revolution. As William Seager shows, Descartes can be seen as the pioneer of this project and some aspects of his position still set the stage and the agenda for modern work. His views vividly illustrate the problem of explaining the physical ‘generation’ of consciousness and point to the fundamental importance of – or perhaps reveal the basic error in – an appeal to the notion of mental representation. After addressing Descartes, Seager considers theories that identify certain particular elements of conscious experience (the so-called qualia) with ‘vector codes’ within abstract spaces defined by neural networks. From there, Seager proceeds to HOT theory, which regards consciousness as the product of higher order thoughts about mental states. The influential and provocative views of Daniel Dennett are closely examined. Theories of Consciousness devotes a lot of attention to the new representational theory of consciousness and the special problems created by the phenomena of conscious thought, which lead to the conclusions that representation is indeed essential to consciousness but that an internalist account of representation is required. In his final chapter, Seager explores more speculative terrain: the idea that consciousness might somehow be a fundamental feature of the universe, perhaps ubiquitous and maybe linked to bizarre features of quantum physics. Theories of Consciousness serves both to introduce a wide array of approaches to consciousness as well as advance debate via a detailed critique of them. Philosophy students, researchers with a particular interest in cognitive science and anyone who has wondered how consciousness fits into a scientific view of the world will find this book an illuminating and fascinating read. William Seager is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Toronto at Scarborough. He is the author of Metaphysics of Consciousness (Routledge, 1991). PHILOSOPHICAL ISSUES IN SCIENCE Edited by W. H. Newton-Smith Balliol College, Oxford REAL HISTORY Martin Bunzl BRUTE SCIENCE Hugh LaFollette and Niall Shanks LIVING IN A TECHNOLOGICAL CULTURE Mary Tiles and Hans Oberdick THE RATIONAL AND THE SOCIAL James Robert Brown THE NATURE OF THE DISEASE Lawrie Reznek THE PHILOSOPHICAL DEFENCE OF PSYCHIATRY Lawrie Reznek INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION Peter Lipton TIME, SPACE AND PHILOSOPHY Christopher Ray MATHEMATICS AND THE IMAGE OF REASON Mary Tiles EVIL OR ILL? Lawrie Reznek THE ETHICS OF SCIENCE An Introduction David B. Resnik PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS An Introduction to a World of Proofs and Pictures James Robert Brown THEORIES OF CONSCIOUSNESS An introduction and assessment William Seager THEORIES OF CONSCIOUSNESS An introduction and assessment William Seager London and New York First published 1999 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2002. Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 © 1999 William Seager All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloging in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Seager, William, 1952– Theories of Consciousness: an introduction and assessment/William Seager. p. cm. – (Philosophical issues in science) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Consciousness 2. Mind and body. I. Title. II. Series B808.9.S4 1999 128–dc21 98–34492 CIP ISBN 0–415–18393–6 (hbk) ISBN 0–415–18394–4 (pbk) ISBN 0-203-05307-9 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-203-21654-7 (Glassbook Format) TO MY PARENTS CONTENTS Acknowledgements viii Preface ix 1 Themes From Descartes 1 2 Identity Theories and the Generation Problem 33 3 HOT Theory: The Mentalistic Reduction of Consciousness 60 4 Dennett I: Everything You Thought You Knew About Experience is Wrong 85 5 Dennett II: Consciousness Fictionalized 107 6 Representational Theories of Consciousness, Part I 132 7 Representational Theories of Consciousness, Part II 153 8 Conscious Intentionality and the Anti-Cartesian Catastrophe 178 9 Consciousness, Information and Panpsychism 216 Notes 253 Bibliography 283 Index of Names 296 Subject Index 300 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Most of this book was written while on a sabbatical leave from the University of Toronto and my thanks go to my university for continuing to support the notion of a research leave. Some of the book has appeared before. A small part of chapter 3 was published in Analysis as ‘Dretske on Hot Theories of Consciousness’ (Seager 1994). The bulk of chapter 4 originally appeared in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research as ‘The Elimination of Experience’ (Seager 1993a); a version of the minimalist explication of Dennett’s four-fold characterization of qualia also appeared in my previous book, Metaphysics of Consciousness (Seager 1991a). I give it here again for the convenience of the reader. A earlier version of a good part of chapter 5 can be found in Inquiry as ‘Verificationism, Scepticism and Consciousness’ (Seager 1993b). Parts of chapters 6 and 7 were published in a critical notice of Fred Dretske’s Naturalizing the Mind in the Canadian Journal of Philosophy (Seager 1997). An early version of chapter 9 was published in the Journal of Consciousness Studies (Seager 1995) and some of my ‘A Note on the Quantum Eraser’ (Seager 1996) from Philosophy of Science has been interpolated into chapter 9 as well. I would like to thank the many people who have discussed this material with me. My students at the University of Toronto have been an invaluable help. The philosophers at Dalhousie University have suffered over the years through almost the whole manuscript, always providing an enthusiastically critical outlook on the work. Early versions of chapter 8 were presented at a conference, Conscience et Intentionalité, held at the Université du Québec à Montréal in 1995, organized by Denis Fissette, to a conference on Consciousness in Humans and Animals, held at the Centre for Process Studies in Claremont in 1994 and organized by David Griffin, and to the meetings of the Canadian Philosophical Association in Calgary also in 1994. A preliminary version of chapter 5 was presented to the Toronto Cognitive Science Society in 1993. My thanks to the organizers and participants of all these events. Finally, I would like most of all to thank Christine, Emma, Tessa and Ned for being there. viii PREFACE Recently there has been a tremendous surge of interest in the problem of consciousness. Though it has always lurked in the vicinity, for years there was little or no mention of consciousness as such in either the philosophical or scientific literature. Now books and articles are flowing in an ever widening stream. This is strange. Hasn’t the mind–body problem always been about consciousness? There is no mind–body problem without the dream of a complete physical science, a dream first clearly entertained by Descartes who then had no choice but to invent the modern mind–body problem. And for Descartes, the mind–body problem is the problem of consciousness for there is, according to his understanding of the mind, nothing else for the mind to be. It is consciousness that sits square across the advancing path of the scientific world view. I doubt that Descartes, were he to admit the possibility of unconscious mentality, would think that it posed any serious challenge to a materialist view of the world. I think it was the growth of psychology as a potential and then actual science that forced upon us the idea that there could be a generalized mind–body problem, of which the problem of consciousness would be but one aspect. Scientific psychology both posited and seemed to require unconscious processes that were in their essential features very like the more familiar conscious mental processes of perception, inference and cognition. And far from retreating, the contemporary science of psychology, along with the upstart sciences of artificial intelligence and cognitive science, has shown ever more reliance upon the hypothesis of non- conscious mental processes. Thus, just as psychology carved out a problem- domain independent of consciousness so the philosophy of mind saw its task redirected on to a mind–body problem whose focus was on the mental processes appropriate to the new problem space (especially the problems of mental representation and the nature of cognition). Is it an unworthy suspicion that the absence of consciousness was not unwelcome? Then it came to seem that perhaps consciousness could be relegated and confined to one esoteric and increasingly baroque scholastic corner of the mind– body problem which has come to be known as the ‘problem of qualia’. What are qualia? They are the particular experienced features of consciousness: the redness of the perceived or imagined poppy, the sound of an orchestra playing in your dreams, the smell of burnt toast (perhaps as evoked by direct neural stimulation as in the famous experiments of Wilder Penfield).
Recommended publications
  • A Perspective on the Mind-Body Problem, with Particular Reference to the Philosophy of Spinoza
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by SAS-SPACE 1 A PERSPECTIVE ON THE MIND-BODY PROBLEM, WITH PARTICULAR REFERENCE TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA MARGARET GULLAN-WHUR A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Faculty of Arts, University of London Department of Philosophy University College London May 1996 2 ABSTRACT Spinoza's thesis of non-reductive monism was conceived in critical response to earlier dualist and materialist theories of mind. He rejects dualism with respect to both God- Nature and mind-body, yet his principles mark off the mental as severely as is possible without forfeiting monism, showing his awareness that monism (attribute identity) threatens mental irreducibility. The constraints Spinoza imposes in order to preserve mental irreducibility and to make human beings partial expressions of one thinking and extended substance produce a tension between mental autonomy and mind-body identity. However, I propose that while this remains a serious philosophical problem, some degree of tension must persist in any non-reductive monism which succeeds in giving the mental a weighting equal to the physical, and that Spinoza's sensitivity to this requirement is instructive. I argue, on the other hand, that Spinoza's theory of mind is irrevocably damaged by his turning of the traditional Mind of God into the Mind of the Whole of Nature in so far as he extrapolates from this Mind of God-or-Nature to finite minds. In characterising finite minds as partial expressions of "God's" infinite intellect I believe Spinoza becomes caught between his unorthodox conception of God's Mind as all-inclusive and a retained conception of the Mind of God as all truths.
    [Show full text]
  • University Name
    PHIL 11001: INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY (FALL 2019, T/TH 2:15-3:30PM) PROFESSOR: David Pereplyotchik EMAIL: [email protected] and [email protected] OFFICE PHONE: 330.672.0270 OFFICE LOCATION: Bowman Hall, 320, Room N PRIMARY OFFICE HOURS: Wednesday, 1-6pm (see below for more options) GRADUATE ASSISTANT: Hope Seo, [email protected] OFFICE HOURS: Tues/Thurs, 10:30-12pm, Bowman Hall, Room 208 READINGS: I will distribute ALL of the readings via Google Drive and/or email. Many of them will come from the following books, which you can purchase (but only if you want to). 1. Peg Tittle, What If….? Collected Thought Experiments in Philosophy 2. Julian Baggini, The Pig That Wants to be Eaten and 99 Other Thought Experiments 3. Daniel Dennett, Intuition Pumps and Other Tools for Thinking 4. Douglas Hofstadter, Dan Dennett (eds.), The Mind’s I: Fantasies and Reflections on Self and Soul 5. David Wallace-Wells, The Uninhabitable Earth: Life After Warming Course Description: This course will focus on introductory readings concerning a variety of philosophical topics, including the meaning of life, the role of religion in society, the attempts to justify religious belief, the nature of the conscious mind and its relationship to the physical body, the possibility of artificial intelligence, the value of political equality, and the philosophical implications of recent findings in the sciences, especially physics, biology, and psychology. Kent Core: This course may be used to satisfy a Kent Core requirement. The Kent Core as a whole is intended to broaden intellectual perspectives, foster ethical and humanitarian values, and prepare students for responsible citizenship and productive careers.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings Is a Comprehensive Anthology That Includes Classic and Contemporary Readings from Leading Philosophers
    11 111 PHILOSOPHY OF MIND 11 11 Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings is a comprehensive anthology that includes classic and contemporary readings from leading philosophers. Addressing most major topics within the philosophy of mind, O’Connor and Robb have carefully chosen articles under the following headings: • Substance Dualism and Idealism • Materialism • Mind and Representation 111 • Consciousness Articles by the following thinkers are included: Zimmerman Swinburne Lowe Robinson 11 Smart Kripke Zuboff Lewis Putnam Block Chalmers Fodor Dretske Searle Davidson Dennett Churchland Levine McGinn Jackson Carruthers Harman Hasker Lockwood Unger Kim 111 Each section is prefaced by an introductory essay written by the editors, which aims to guide the student gently into the topic. The book is highly accessible and provides a broad-ranging exploration of the subject including discussion of leading philosophers in the field. Ideal for any philosophy student, this book will prove essential reading for any philosophy of mind course. Timothy O’Connor is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Indiana University. He is editor of Agents, Causes, and Events: Essays on Indeterminism and Free Will (1995) and author of Persons and Causes: The Metaphysics of Free Will (2000). 111 David Robb is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Davidson College. He is the author of several articles on metaphysics and the philosophy of mind. 11 Routledge Contemporary Readings in Philosophy Series Editor: Paul K. Moser, Loyola University of Chicago Routledge Contemporary Readings in Philosophy is a major new series of philosophy anthologies aimed at undergraduate students taking core philos- ophy disciplines. It is also a companion series to the highly successful Routledge Contemporary Introductions to Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Experience of Philosophy
    Contents Preface Vtl Part I: Beginning Philosophy 1. Plato, The Trial of Socrates 2 2. Stanley Milgram, Obedience to Authority 23 3. Jiddu Krishnamurti, The Function ofEducation 30 4. Bertrand Russell, The Value of Philosophy 34 Part II: Where and When 5. Edwin Abbott, Flatland 40 6. Daniel Kolak and David Goloff, The Incredible Shrinking Zeno 57 7. Daniel Dennett, Where Am I? 71 8. Albert Einstein, On the Idea ofTime in Physics 80 9. Kadri Vihvelin, Time Travel: The Rules of the Road 84 Part III: Who 10. Daniel Kolak, Descartes among the Ruins 96 ll. Buddha, On Having No Self 104 12. D. E. Harding, On Having No Head 107 13. René Descartes, On Self and Substance 111 14. John Locke, Personal Identity 120 15. David Hume, Personal Identity 128 16. Thomas Reid, Critique ofLocke and Hume on BehalfofCommon Sense 131 17. Raymond Martin, Personal Identity from Plato to Padit 139 18. Char10tte Perkins Gilman, The Yellow Wallpaper 155 19. AdamjLinda Parascandola, Trans or Me? 168 lil iv CONTENTS Part IV: Preedom 20. Baron Holbach, The Illusion ofFree Will 176 21. David Hume, Liberty and Necessity 182 22. William James, The Dilemma of Determinism 194 23. G. E. Moore, Free Will 201 24. Richard Taylor, Freedom and Determinism 209 25. Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism and Human Freedom 219 Part V: J(nowledge 26. Plato, Knowledge 226 27. René Descartes, Meditations 250 28. John Locke, Where Our 1deas Come From 259 29. George Berkeley, To Be ls to Be Perceived 263 30. Bertrand Russell, Perception, Knowledge, and 1nduction 268 31.
    [Show full text]
  • INTERPRETER§ a Journal of Mormon Scripture
    INTERPRETER§ A Journal of Mormon Scripture Volume 29 • 2018 The Interpreter Foundation Orem, Utah The Interpreter Foundation Chairman and President Contributing Editors Daniel C. Peterson Robert S. Boylan John M. Butler Vice Presidents James E. Faulconer Jeffrey M. Bradshaw Kristine Wardle Frederickson Daniel Oswald Benjamin I. Huff Noel B. Reynolds Jennifer C. Lane Allen Wyatt David J. Larsen Donald W. Parry Executive Board Ugo A. Perego Kevin Christensen Stephen D. Ricks Steven T. Densley, Jr. G. Bruce Schaalje Brant A. Gardner Andrew C. Smith Jeff Lindsay John A. Tvedtnes Louis C. Midgley Sidney B. Unrau George L. Mitton Stephen T. Whitlock Gregory L. Smith Lynne Hilton Wilson Ed Snow Mark Alan Wright Tanya Spackman Ted Vaggalis Donor Relations Jann E. Campbell Board of Editors Matthew L. Bowen Treasurer David M. Calabro Kent Flack Craig L. Foster Taylor Halverson Production Editor & Designers Ralph C. Hancock Kelsey Fairbanks Avery Benjamin L. McGuire Timothy Guymon Tyler R. Moulton Alan Sikes Martin S. Tanner Bryan J. Thomas Gordon C. Thomasson A. Keith Thompson John S. Thompson Bruce F. Webster The Interpreter Foundation Editorial Consultants Media & Technology Merrie Kay Ames Scott Dunaway Starla Butler Richard Flygare Kasen Christensen Brad Haymond Jolie Griffin Steve Metcalf Don Norton Tyler R. Moulton Kaitlin Cooper Swift Tom Pittman Stephen Swift Russell D. Richins Jennifer Tonks Alan Sikes Elizabeth Wyatt S. Hales Swift Victor Worth © 2018 The Interpreter Foundation. A 501(c)(3) nonprofit organization. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ or send a letter to Creative Commons, 444 Castro Street, Suite 900, Mountain View, California, 94041, USA.
    [Show full text]
  • Help Yourself • * ¢ Ψ ? †
    Help Yourself • * ¢ Ψ ? † CASPAR ADDYMAN Copyleft 2013 Caspar Addyman This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/ In other words, help yourself. Except those bits copyright the philosophers © 2003 ISBN: 1475199465 ISBN-13: 978-1475199468 This book will change your life. But only in subtle and insidious ways that you may never notice. ~ With a guide to the meaning of life, the universe and everything, thrown in at no extra cost. For Ailsa, who wrote the bit about the horse. PROLOGUE THE FOOL ON THE HILL • A man stood on a hill. He looked up at the stars and tried to remember what on earth he was doing here. Why had he climbed this hill? Such memory lapses happened to him all the time when going from the living room to the kitchen, but this was the first time one had happened at the top of a big hill. It was a big hill. He was out of breath. Perhaps, he reflected, this was not the first time it had happened. After all, his memory was evidently less than reliable. There was no fridge at the top of the hill, so he did not think he had come to get something out of it. There was no kettle to put on and nothing on which to put it. There were none of the makings of a cheese salad sandwich. It seemed increasingly unlikely that applying the insights of his previous kitchen-based amnesia was going to help here.
    [Show full text]
  • A Perspective on the Mind-Body Problem, with Particular Reference To
    A PERSPECTIVE ON THE MIND-BODY PROBLEM, WITH PARTICULAR REFERENCE TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA MARGARET GULLAN-WHUR A^ Thesis Submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Faculty of Arts, University of London Department of Philosophy University College London May 1996 ProQuest Number: 10045683 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. uest. ProQuest 10045683 Published by ProQuest LLC(2016). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 ABSTRACT Spinoza's thesis of non-reductive monism was conceived in critical re'^pcnse to earlier dualist and materialist theories of mind. He rejects dualism with respect to both f jO 1-Nature and mind-body, yet his principles mark off the mental as severely as is possible without forfeiting monism, showing his awareness that monism (attribute identity) threatens mental irreducibility. The constraints Spinoza imposes in order to preserve mental irreducibility and to make human beings partial expressions of one thinking and extended substance produce a tension between mental autonomy and mind-body identity. However, I propose that while this remains a serious philosophical problem, some degree of tension must persist in any non-reductive monism which succeeds in giving the mental a weighting equal to the physical, and that Spinoza's sensitivity to this requirement is instructive.
    [Show full text]