Relativism About Truth

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Relativism About Truth Relativism About Truth by Peter Davson-Galle, B.A.(Hons.) (Adel.), M.A. (La T.) Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Tasmania, July, 1996. ,1,( I. lopky This thesis contains no material which has been accepted for a degree or diploma by the University of Tasmania or any other institution and to the best of my knowledge and belief no material previously published or written by another person except where due acknowledgment is made in the text of the thesis. II This thesis may be made available for loan and limited copying in accordance with the Copyright Act 1968. Abstract Broadly put, the thesis is an investigation of the possibility of articulating a coherent thesis of truth relativism within first, a host correspondence theory of truth and second, a host coherence theory of truth. The type of relativism addressed in the thesis is what is sometimes called 'framework relativism', that where truth is relativised to a framework of belief, conceptual scheme or something of that sort. A further restraint is that it is a global relativistic thesis which is sought, one that is relativistic about all truths. The thesis does not set itself the task of defending relativism but just that of seeking a coherent articulation of it. The work is in two sections. In the first, the host theory is the correspondence theory of truth. The result of that section's analysis is that, although what Chris Swoyer calls 'strong truth relativism' is not able to be given coherent articulation, what he calls 'weak truth relativism' is. The conception of weak correspondence relative truth that is explicated here is a three place relation of proposition, world (without "joints at which to carve") and categorial repertoire (of a type suggested by Jack Meiland). A global thesis in its terms proves coherently articulable and does not suffer from problems of self-inclusion. In the second section, the host theory is the coherence theory. Promising looking host though it seems, neither propositional nor doxastic web versions of the coherence theory prove to be able to permit either weak or strong global truth relativistic theses to be coherently articulated. The most promising looking coherence relativist candidate of those examined is a strong doxastic thesis developed by James Young. Like other coherence relativisms examined, Young's succumbs to the reflexitivity demands of a global thesis. Strong coherence theses also prove to have difficulty in having the same proposition true relative to one propositional/doxastic web and false relative to another. Weak variants have difficulty explicating the "appropriate alternativeness" of the categorial repertoire in terms of which some target proposition is to be ineffable. The results of investigation are contrary to conventional wisdom concerning relativism in that it proves to be the correspondence theory, not the coherence theory, within which it is easier to articulate global (though only weak) framework truth relativism. iv I wish to acknowledge the advice given to me by my supervisors, Dr. Edgar Sleinis and Prof. Bill Joske, and the helpful correspondence and conversations concerning various parts of the work that I have had with Jack Meiland, Jim Young, Steve Rappaport, Steve Edwards, Jack Smart, Howard Sankey, Henry Krips, Brian Ellis, Kathy Bohsted, Frank White and Harvey Siegel. I also wish to acknowledge the emotional support and forbearance of my spouse Chrissy and my daughters Jenny and Kathleen. V Table of Contents Page Introduction 1 SECTION ONE - CORRESPONDENCE TRUTH RELATIVISM Chapter One - The Correspondence Theory and Relativism 1 1 - Correspondence Truth 11 - Relative Truth and Reality 17 Chapter Two - Framework Relativisms with One World Realism 32 - Introduction 32 - Framework Relativisms 33 Chapter Three - Categorial Repertoire Weak Truth Relativism 46 - Introduction 46 - The Concept of Categorial repertoire Weak Truth Relativism 46 - The Thesis of Global Correspondence Weak Truth Relativism 56 Chapter Four - The Truth Status of Truth Relativism Itself 59 - Introduction 59 - Truth Relativism as Not Relatively True 60 - Truth Relativism as Relatively True 67 Chapter Five - Totally Incommensurable Conceptual Schemes 73 - Introduction 73 - The Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme 74 - Davidson's First Argument 76 - Davidson's Second Argument 81 Chapter Six - Alternative Categorial Webs 88 - Introduction 88 - Holism and Discretism 88 - Discretist Truth vehicle and Relativiser 91 - Appropriately Alternative W*s 92 vi Page - Discretist Truth vehicle and Holist Relativiser 99 - Holist Truth vehicle 107 - Summary 108 SECTION TWO - COHERENCE TRUTH RELATIVISM Chapter Seven - Truth Relativism within Non-realist Theories 109 - Introduction 109 - The Coherence Theory of Truth 110 - Global Coherentist Truth Relativism 113 - Global Strong Coherence Truth Relativism 114 - Examination of These Versions 117 - Propositional Relativism 118 - Doxastic Relativism 120 - Actual-strong Belief Relativism 121 - Possible-strong Belief Relativism 122 - Summary 123 Chapter Eight - Propositional Relativism 124 - Introduction 124 - Elaboration 124 - A Problem for Strong Relativism 129 - Possible-strong Propositional Relativism 138 Chapter Nine - Possible-strong Actual-belief Relativism 142 - Introduction 142 - The Demands of Strong Relativism 143 - Sense Holism Revisited: Young's Views 145 - Truth, Belief and Coherence 151 - An Awkward Objection 160 vii Page Chapter Ten - Weak Truth Coherentism 163 - Introduction 163 - Weak Propositional Relativism 164 - Holistic Variation 164 - Experience as a Semantic Object 166 - Discretist Variation 171 - Weak Doxastic Relativism 172 - Summary 175 Chapter Eleven - Coherence Relativism and Standard Objections 177 - Introduction 177 - Self-refutation 179 - (a) Holistic Propositional Strong Relativism and Self-refutation 180 - (b) Doxastic Possible-strong Relativism and Self-refutation 184 - Weak Relativism 186 - The Meta-regress Objection 189 - Strong Relativism's Fate 191 - Weak Relativism 192 - Walker's Objection 193 - Summary 198 References 200 INTRODUCTION 'How Must Relativism Be Understood To Be Coherent?'.' Broadly put, and within some restraints, this thesis attempts to answer the question, a question which has not been answered totally in the literature and is one of continuing philosophical interest. Mark Okrent claims: Recently there has been a revival of philosophic interest in, and discussion of, "relativism". Debates concerning relativism, however, tend to have an odd air of unreality. It is odd that while most everyone wants to refute relativism, just about no one wants to be identified as a relativisit. There is even a tendency to use 'relativist' as an epithet of abuse. But, if relativism is universally acknowledged to be refuted, even self-refuting, then why is there so much discussion of it ...?' (1984, P. 341) Friedel Weinert puts it even more strongly: ...the modern age is marked by the renunciation of the possibility of the one true ontological statement about the world. The modern age has abandoned the search for Truth and has opened the door to the age of relativism. (1984, p382) Robert Nola remarks: Long an outcast from philosophy, relativism has, for most of this .century, found a home in the doctrines of most (but not all) sociologists of science, several historians of science and a handful of phiosophers of science. (1988, p.2) Yet, though he judges it to have only a handful of supporters and, remarks 'no matter how much philosophers are at odds with one another they seem, with only a few 1 I borrow the question's wording from the title of a recent paper by John Fox. (1992) 2 exceptions, to be united in their condemnation of relativism',2 Nola goes on to note that '... relativism exerts a strange fascination and a number of philosophers ... have found it instructive to come to terms with the ways they find it to be self-refuting or incoherent (if they find it so at all).' (1988, p. 1) Hilary Putnam is one such philosopher, remarking: I myself am fascinated by the different ways in which relativism is incoherent or self-contradictory. I think they are worth careful study by epistemologists ... because each of the refutations of relativism teaches us something important about knowledge. (1983, P. 288) Harvey Siegel remarks that his view was : ...relativism is an obvious non-starter, a position whose very statement requires logical contradiction and so self-refutation, and so a position not worthy of sustained philosophical attention ... But it became clear that such an out-of- hand rejection of relativism was too cavalier. For one thing, many highly regarded philosophers, working in a variety of areas 3 , embraced one or another form of relativism. For another, several philosophers took on the task of articulating and defending relativism, paying special attention to the problem of relativism's alleged incoherence. Most importantly, the last two- three decades have witnessed a striking emergence of relativism in the philosophy of science.4 (1987, p. xi) Olcrent complains: Contemporary discussions of relativism are confused ... (in part because) ... there is no clear understanding that there are a variety of senses in which one may talk of relativism and ... a theory which is relativist in one of these senses 2 Barry Barnes and David Bloor put the point even more extremely: '...in the academic world relativism is everywhere abominated...'. (1982, p. 21) 3 Though, if Nola is to be believed, not many in philosophy
Recommended publications
  • The Relativism of Blame and Williams' Relativism of Distance
    ABSTRACT: Bernard Williams is a sceptic about the objectivity of moral value, embracing instead a certain qualified moral relativism—the ‘relativism of distance’. His attitude to blame too is in part sceptical (he thought it often involved a certain ‘fantasy’). I will argue that the relativism of distance is unconvincing, even incoherent; but also that it is detachable from the rest of Williams’ moral philosophy. I will then go on to propose an entirely localized thesis I call the relativism of blame, which says that when an agent’s moral shortcomings by our lights are a matter of their living according to the moral thinking of their day, judgements of blame are out of order. Finally, I will propose a form of moral judgement we may sometimes quite properly direct towards historically distant agents when blame is inappropriate—moral-epistemic disappointment. Together these two proposals may help release us from the grip of the idea that moral appraisal always involves the potential applicability of blame, and so from a key source of the relativist idea that moral appraisal is inappropriate over distance. The Relativism of Blame and Williams’ Relativism of Distance Must I think of myself as visiting in judgement all the reaches of history? Of course, one can imagine oneself as Kant at the court of King Arthur, disapproving of its injustices, but exactly what grip does this get on one’s ethical or political thought?1 Bernard Williams famously argued for a distinctive brand of moral relativism, which he regarded as capturing the truth in relativism, and which he called the relativism of distance.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Coherence of Sartre's Defense of Existentialism Against The
    Untitled 7/12/05 3:41 PM On the Coherence of Sartre’s Defense of Existentialism Against the Essentialist Charge of Ethical Relativism in His “Existentialism and Humanism” Brad Cherry I.Introduction Although its slim volume may suggest otherwise, Jean-Paul Sartre’s “Existentialism and Humanism” treats a wealth of existentialist themes. Indeed, within its pages, Sartre characterizes many of the hallmarks of existentialist thought, including subjectivity, freedom, responsibility, anguish, forlornness, despair, and so on. Perhaps most importantly, however, Sartre’s “Existentialism and Humanism” occasions a defense of existentialism against its most frequently dealt criticisms, particularly the essentialist charge that existentialism necessarily gives rise to ethical relativism. And while this defense may seem convincing at first, in many places, it also seems to abandon, for the sake of its project, the fundamental commitments of existentialism, at least as Sartre understands them. Thus, in this essay, I critically examine the coherence of Sartre’s defense of existentialism against the essentialist charge of ethical relativism. To the extent that that defense relies largely upon his espousal of an existentialist ethics, I examine, in particular, whether that ethics coheres with the fundamental commitments of existentialism as he understands them. Following this examination, I conclude that (a) the fundamental commitments of existentialism preclude Sartre from coherently positing objectively valid normative ethical statements, that (b) because he nonetheless posits such statements in his espousal of an existentialist ethics, his defense of existentialism against the essentialist charge of ethical relativism breaks down, and finally, that (c) although this incoherence presents a substantial problem for Sartre, one may still defend his attempt to espouse an existentialist ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Relativism
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Publications and Research New York City College of Technology 2020 The Incoherence of Moral Relativism Carlo Alvaro CUNY New York City College of Technology How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/ny_pubs/583 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] 1 The Incoherence of Moral Relativism Abstract This paper is a response to Park Seungbae’s article, “Defence of Cultural Relativism”. Some of the typical criticisms of moral relativism are the following: moral relativism is erroneously committed to the principle of tolerance, which is a universal principle; there are a number of objective moral rules; a moral relativist must admit that Hitler was right, which is absurd; a moral relativist must deny, in the face of evidence, that moral progress is possible; and, since every individual belongs to multiple cultures at once, the concept of moral relativism is vague. Park argues that such contentions do not affect moral relativism and that the moral relativist may respond that the value of tolerance, Hitler’s actions, and the concept of culture are themselves relative. In what follows, I show that Park’s adroit strategy is unsuccessful. Consequently, moral relativism is incoherent. Keywords: Moral relativism; moral absolutism; objectivity; tolerance; moral progress 2 The Incoherence of Moral Relativism Moral relativism is a meta-ethical theory according to which moral values and duties are relative to a culture and do not exist independently of a culture.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory Reflections: Linguistic Determinism/Relativism
    Theory Reflections: Linguistic Determinism/Relativism The Theory The theory of linguistic determinism and relativity presents a two-sided phenomenon: Does the specific language (and culture) we are exposed to in childhood determine, in fact, how we perceive the world, how we think, and how we express ourselves? If this is so, then, it must also be the case that each language (and the culture it represents) necessarily provides its speakers with a specific and differing view of that same world, a different way of thinking, and a different way of expressing. This notion is related to a parallel issue that has existed throughout the centuries—are there also universal absolutes that transcend all linguistic (and cultural) particulars? Recent research suggests there may be elements of both. Linguistic determinism came to the attention of linguists and anthropologists during the 1930s, prompted by the work of Benjamin Lee Whorf. Using prevailing linguistic approaches of his time, Whorf, who studied indigenous languages, found surprising contrasts with European tongues in terms of how they reflected and spoke about reality (e.g., how they segment the time continuum, construct lexical hierarchies and, in short, encode a different view of the world, or Weltanschauung). The Whorf-Sapir hypothesis, as it came to be known (Sapir was his teacher), gained increasing attention and prompted the notion of language determinism/relativity. In other words, the language we are born to has a direct effect upon how we conceptualize, think, interact, and express—a direct relationship between human language and human thinking This notion has remained at the center of a debate for more than half a century.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Relativism.Indb
    Richard Schantz, Markus Seidel The Problem of Relativism in the Sociology of (Scientific) Knowledge P h i l o s o p h i s c h e A n a l y s e P h i l o s o p h i c a l A n a l y s i s Herausgegeben von / Edited by Herbert Hochberg • Rafael Hüntelmann • Christian Kanzian Richard Schantz • Erwin Tegtmeier Band 43 / Volume 43 Richard Schantz, Markus Seidel The Problem of Relativism in the Sociology of (Scientific) Knowledge Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de. North and South America by Transaction Books Rutgers University Piscataway, NJ 08854-8042 [email protected] United Kingdom, Ireland, Iceland, Turkey, Malta, Portugal by Gazelle Books Services Limited White Cross Mills Hightown LANCASTER, LA1 4XS [email protected] Livraison pour la France et la Belgique: Librairie Philosophique J.Vrin 6, place de la Sorbonne; F-75005 PARIS Tel. +33 (0)1 43 54 03 47; Fax +33 (0)1 43 54 48 18 www.vrin.fr 2011 ontos verlag P.O. Box 15 41, D-63133 Heusenstamm www.ontosverlag.com ISBN 978-3-86838-126-9 2011 No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in retrieval systems or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed
    [Show full text]
  • May 03 CI.Qxd
    Philosophy of Chemistry by Eric Scerri Of course, the field of compu- hen I push my hand down onto my desk it tational quantum chemistry, does not generally pass through the which Dirac and other pioneers Wwooden surface. Why not? From the per- of quantum mechanics inadver- spective of physics perhaps it ought to, since we are tently started, has been increas- told that the atoms that make up all materials consist ingly fruitful in modern mostly of empty space. Here is a similar question that chemistry. But this activity has is put in a more sophisticated fashion. In modern certainly not replaced the kind of physics any body is described as a superposition of chemistry in which most practitioners are engaged. many wavefunctions, all of which stretch out to infin- Indeed, chemists far outnumber scientists in all other ity in principle. How is it then that the person I am fields of science. According to some indicators, such as talking to across my desk appears to be located in one the numbers of articles published per year, chemistry particular place? may even outnumber all the other fields of science put together. If there is any sense in which chemistry can The general answer to both such questions is that be said to have been reduced then it can equally be although the physics of microscopic objects essen- said to be in a high state of "oxidation" regarding cur- tially governs all of matter, one must also appeal to rent academic and industrial productivity. the laws of chemistry, material science, biology, and Starting in the early 1990s a group of philosophers other sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Causes As Explanations: a Critique*
    JAEGWON KIM CAUSES AS EXPLANATIONS: A CRITIQUE* Causes certainly are connected with effects; but this is because our theories connect them, not because the world is held together by cosmic glue. 1 Norwood Russell Hanson ABSTRACT. This paper offers a critique of the view that causation can be analyzed in terms of explanation. In particular, the following points are argued: (1) a genuine explanatory analysis of causation must make use of a fully epistemological-psychological notion of explanation; (2) it is unlikely that the relatively clear-cut structure of the causal relation can be captured by the relatively unstructured relation of explanation; (3) the explanatory relation does not always parallel the direction of causation; (4) certain difficulties arise for any attempt to construct a nonrelativistic relation of caus- ation from the essentially relativistic relation of explanation; and (5) to analyze causation as explanation is to embrace a form of "causal idealism", the view that causal connec- tions are not among the objective features of the world. The paper closes with a brief discussion of the contrast between the two fundamentally opposed viewpoints about causality, namely causal idealism and causal realism. It is little more than a truism to say that causes explain their effects, or that to ask for the cause of an event is to ask for an explanation of why or how the event occurred. This close association between causation and explanation is amply mirrored in language: we answer 'why'-questions with 'becuase'- statements, and surely there is more than an orthographic resemblance between 'cause' and 'because'. The association is also ancient: it goes back to Aristotle, who characterized true, scientific knowledge as knowledge of the 'why' of things, that is, knowledge of the cause that makes a thing what it is and not something else.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Relativism by Matt Slick by CARM (Christian Apologetics & Research Ministry)
    Ethical Relativism by Matt Slick By CARM (Christian Apologetics & Research Ministry) Ethical relativism is the position that there are no moral absolutes, no moral right and wrongs. Instead, right and wrong are based on social norms. Such could be the case with "situational ethics," which is a category of ethical relativism. At any rate, ethical relativism would mean that our morals have evolved, that they have changed over time, and that they are not absolute. One advantage of ethical relativism is that it allows for a wide variety of cultures and practices. It also allows people to adapt ethically as the culture, knowledge, and technology change in society. This is a good and valid form of relativism. The disadvantage of ethical relativism is that truth, right and wrong, and justice are all relative. Just because a group of people think that something is right does not make it so. Slavery is a good example of this. Two hundred years ago in America, slavery was the norm and morally acceptable. Now it is not. Relativism also does not allow for the existence of an absolute set of ethics. Logically, if there are no absolute ethics, then there can be no Divine Absolute Ethics Giver. Requiring an absolute set of ethics implies an Absolute Ethics Giver, which can easily be extrapolated as being God. This would be opposed to ethical relativism. Therefore, ethical relativism would not support the idea of an absolute God, and it would exclude religious systems based upon absolute morals; that is, it would be absolute in its condemnation of absolute ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • Objective, Multiplistic, and Relative Truth in Developmental Psychology and Legal Education, 62 Tul
    John Marshall Law School The John Marshall Institutional Repository Faculty Scholarship 1-1-1988 Objective, Multiplistic, and Relative Truth in Developmental Psychology and Legal Education, 62 Tul. L. Rev. 1237 (1988) Paul T. Wangerin John Marshall Law School Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.jmls.edu/facpubs Part of the Legal Education Commons Recommended Citation Paul T. Wangerin, Objective, Multiplistic, and Relative Truth in Developmental Psychology and Legal Education, 62 Tul. L. Rev. 1237 (1988). http://repository.jmls.edu/facpubs/274 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The oJ hn Marshall Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of The oJ hn Marshall Institutional Repository. OBJECTIVE, MULTIPLISTIC, AND RELATIVE TRUTH IN DEVELOPMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY AND LEGAL EDUCATION PAUL T. WANGERIN* INTRODUCTION Two thousand years ago, Protagoras, a teacher of lawyers, began what has since become one of the most enduring and pain- ful philosophic debates in western civilization. "Man is the mea- sure of all things," Protagoras insisted, arguing that everything is relative.1 Since nothing in nature is fixed and certain, Protag- oras urged, human beings must create their own meanings and truths. Plato claimed otherwise.2 Some things, Plato argued, are fixed and certain. Truth itself has an objective meaning which does not vary from time to time or from place to place. * Associate Professor of Law, John Marshall Law School. Many people have read this article and have made helpful comments. My principal debt in this context is to psychologists William Perry, Jane Loevinger, Patricia King, and Norma Haan.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Relativism Explained
    Moral Relativism Explained Gilbert Harman 1 What Is Moral Relativism? According to moral relativism, there is not a single true morality. There are a variety of possible moralities or moral frames of reference, and whether something is morally right or wrong, good or bad, just or unjust, etc. is a relative matter—relative to one or another morality or moral frame of reference. Something can be morally right relative to one moral frame of reference and 1 morally wrong relative to another. It is useful to compare moral relativism to other kinds of 2 relativism. One possible comparison is with motion relativism. There is no such thing as absolute motion or absolute rest. Whether something is moving or at rest is relative to a spatio- temporal frame of reference. Something may be at rest in one such frame of reference and moving in another. There is no such thing as absolute motion and absolute rest, but we can make do with relative motion and rest. Similarly, moral relativism is the view that, although there is no such thing as absolute right and wrong, we can make do with relative right and wrong. 3 Paul Boghossian suggests a different comparison. When people decided that there were no witches and no such thing as witchcraft, they did not become relativists about witches; they gave up their beliefs about witches. It would have been a mistake for them to conclude that witchcraft is a relative matter, so that someone could be a witch in relation to one witch framework but not in relation to another.
    [Show full text]
  • Motives of Pinker's Criticism of Whorfian
    Sławomir Wacewicz LANGUAGE AND THINKING: MOTIVES OF PINKER’S CRITICISM OF WHORFIAN LINGUISTIC RELATIVISM In The Language Instinct (1995 [1994], henceforth: TLI), a book that despite its popular character has become virtually a classic in discussions concerning the innateness of language, Steven Pinker attacks the broadly understood “Whorfian” standpoint according to which human thinking is influenced in fundamental ways by one’s native language. Due to the status of the author and popularity of the book, it is an influential voice in the ongoing debate on the mutual relation between language and “thought.” Rather than joining this debate, in the present text I would like to examine the construction and integrity of Pinker’s argumentation in TLI. I suggest that this author’s attack on broadly understood interdependence of language and thought is motivated by his general theoretical commitments, rather than by independent evidence. 1. Introduction and the reconstruction of Pinker’s initial position The best way of reconstructing Steven Pinker’s initial position is by situating his views in the general spectrum of approaches present in contemporary Cognitive Science. Pinker’s principal commitments appear to be evolutionary, which is visible in his popular reception, where he is recognised as an evolutionary psychologist much more readily than as a linguist or psycholinguist. Such a theoretical inclination often goes together with two general views: nativism and modularism; views that are separable, but related and mutually supporting. Steven Pinker is an advocate for both nativism and modularism with respect to language, as well as to cognition in general. In crudest terms, nativism is a view according to which human knowledge (or, more generally, the content of the human mind) is in some vital part innate.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue Theory, Relativism and Survival
    International Journal of Social Science and Humanity, Vol. 3, No. 4, July 2013 Virtue Theory, Relativism and Survival Joseph Grcic there can be no objective or universal knowledge in any Abstract—Virtue theory claims that moral virtues define the human endeavor including ethics. moral person. Moral relativism claims there are no necessary Metaethical relativism is the claim that moral concepts universal moral values-this theory is not rationally sustainable have meaning only within a given cultural framework. Any as a theory of ethics. The necessary functions of social order two different normative systems are incommensurable and and existence require certain moral virtues. There are six main universal moral virtues: wisdom, courage, justice, humanity, one cannot be rationally judged to be superior to the other. temperance, and transcendence. Societies cannot function Relativism in the extreme form conflicts with the fact that efficiently without these core virtues. there are similarities in moral virtues found across all stable cultures. These virtues and values are a function of the Index terms—Moral relativism, social structure, virtue universality of human nature, human needs and the common theory. problems societies must solve to survive. The differences that do exist in moral norms are limited and arise due to different social and historical contexts, ideologies and belief I. INTRODUCTION systems which shape moral norms to some degree. But The realm of ethics seems to be one of the most these differences are secondary when compared to the larger conflicted and uncertain in philosophy and in human history. common foundation of core values based on the common This conflict would be tolerable if it did not have practical problems which must be solved for communities to survive.
    [Show full text]