2 Group Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

2 Group Theory 2 Group Theory The theory of groups is a deep mathematical subject, one which will not receive a comprehensive treatment here. The goal will be motivation and overview. 2.1 Groups The question might first arise in elementary school. We learn of the laws of addition and multiplication, and we see a pattern; there can exist “operations” which input two numbers and output a third. The question attaches itself to the curious mind: what other operations exist, or could exist? Certainly, we could invent operations to our hearts' content, simply by assigning rules for combining numbers, tantamount to a multiplication table. If we want to assign 5 # 6 = 53, we are free to do so. The more nuanced question becomes: which operations are useful, or interesting? Are addition and multiplication chosen because they are the only interesting and useful operations, or are they simply the most interesting and useful? How do we define what is useful to us? Notice that the idea of composing two things to get a new thing isn't a concept devoted simply to numbers. For example, when we compose two rotations (by performing both in succession), the combination is a rotation. When we compose functions, the result is a function. When we multiply matrices, the result is a matrix. In the realm of physics, if a physical state or theory has a set of symmetries, we can compose two symmetries, and the result will be a symmetry. This question has a wide scope of answers. First, we abstract the problem to the realm of set theory. In this language, we study what is known as a law of composition. A law of composition is a map which combines two elements from a set to produce another element of the set: f : S×S S (2.1) ° = ∈ s1, s2 ⇢ s1 s2 s3 S (2.2) Thus, a law of composition has the property of closure; when we combine two elements from the set S, we remain in the set S. However, it is still a notion fairly devoid of structure. With such an unrestricted definition, it seems unlikely we have yet produced something useful. For example, let us invent a new operation, which we shall call the “turns into” operation, denoted “ti>”. The “turns into” operation will be defined as follows: a ti> b=b , for all b∈S (2.3) This is a bona fide law of composition, which is well-defined on any set S. The multiplication table would be quite simple to produce: ti> a b c ⋯ a a b c ⋯ b a b c ⋯ (2.4) c a b c ⋯ ⋮ ⋮ ⋮ ⋮ ⋱ As you can see, this composition law is a bit stubborn; it doesn't matter at all what the first element is. Eventually, we want the objects of study to actually be “compositions”, that is, we want the composed element “a ti> b” to somehow retain some of the information about how it is composed. For the case of the “turns into” operation, this is not possible. This will not be a satisfactory operation to be placed under the category of “group”. Examples Before we seek a formal definition, it is worthwhile to provide some useful examples for context and motivation. Later, when we have developed the definition, we will show that all of these examples indeed satisfy the group axioms. We start with the real numbers, with two possible composition laws: addition or multiplication. In the case of multiplication, it turns out that we need to restrict ourselves to the real numbers with zero removed: R* = R\{0}. We can sometimes form groups out of closed subsets of these spaces. For example, the positive real numbers R⁺ also form a group under multiplication, and the integers Z form a group under addition. We can even go further, looking at the group of integers modulo n. Given an integer n, any integer m can be written in the form m=anb , where0bn (2.5) In simpler language, b is the remainder when m is divided by n. We write m≡b mod n (2.6) meaning m and b are separated by a multiple of n. The set of integers modulo n contains n elements, in that there are n possible remainders when dividing by n. Note that they can add; it works exactly like addition in the integers, except that it wraps around at n: n≡0 mod n (2.7) Because addition on this set is cyclic, this group is known as the cyclic group of order n. It is denoted Zn. Problem 2.1 Show that addition of integers is preserved when looking at integers modulo n: ab=c ⇒ ab≡c mod n (2.8) also, show that multiplication is preserved: a⋅b=c ⇒ a⋅b≡c mod n (2.9) Problem 2.2 Given the results of Problem 2.1, we look at a specific example: 10≡1 mod 3 (2.10) meaning 10⋅a≡a mod 3 (2.11) and 10m ≡1 mod 3 (2.12) Use these facts to show that a number is divisible by three if and only if the sum of its digits is divisible by three. The symmetric group, Sn, is the set of permutations of n elements. We can compose permutations in the natural way; s3 =s2 ° s1 (2.13) is the permutation found by performing the permutation s₁ followed by s₂. As an example of a permutation group, the group S₃ might represent the six possible ways of rearranging three playing cards. The symmetric group is our first example of a group whose multiplication law is not commutative. The order of permutations is important: s2° s1≠s1 ° s2 (2.14) Figure 2.1 The symmetric group is not abelian; the order of permutations matters. For example, if we have three playing cards, placed in the order J-Q-K, and we perform a cyclic permutation leading to K-J-Q, then switch the first two cards, we have J-K-Q. If we instead were to switch the first two cards first, Q-J-K, then perform the cyclic permutation, we have K-Q-J, not J-K-Q. A group whose multiplication law commutes, so that the order doesn't matter, is called “abelian”. The symmetric group is not abelian, for n > 2. Often times, we can define a group as “the set of symmetries of ____”. For example, the Klein Four group is the set of symmetries of a rectangle. There are two reflections and one 180° rotation which compose this group. The dihedral group Dn is the set of symmetries of a regular n-gon. There always exist n rotations and n reflections which map the n-gon to itself. Groups can also simply be specified by a multiplication table. For example, there is the quaternion group H given by the eight elements {±1, ±i, ±j, ±k}, with the rules i2 = j 2=k2=−1 (2.15) i⋅j=− j⋅i=k j⋅k=−k⋅j=i (2.16) k⋅i=−i⋅k= j these rules give us the following multiplication table: 1 −1 i −i j − j k −k 1 1 −1 i −i j − j k −k −1 −1 1 −i i − j j −k k i i −i −1 1 k −k − j j −i −i i 1 −1 −k k j − j (2.17) j j − j −k k −1 1 i −i − j − j j k −k 1 −1 −i i k k −k j − j −i i −1 1 −k −k k − j j i −i 1 −1 Clearly, the quaternions are another example of a nonabelian group. Matrix multiplication provides another group multiplication law. Specifically, the set of all invertible n × n matrices is a group, which we call the general linear group, GLnR. There are many subsets of GLnR which are also groups by themselves. As was hinted at previously, the set of spatial rotations and reflections (about a given point) forms a group, On, the set of rotations and reflections in n dimensions. In addition, there is Tn, the group of translations in n dimensions. It is possible to combine these groups, since the composition of a rotation with a translation is just the same rotation with its point of origin translated. This is known as the group of rigid transformations in n dimensions. It includes all spatial translations, and all rotations about all points. For an abstract example of a group, think of the set of bijective maps from a set to itself. The composition law is just given by composition of maps: hx= f ° g x= f g x (2.18) Group Axioms When we formulate the theory of groups, we will need additional structure that reflects our need to retain information about how an element is constructed out of other elements. When we compose two elements a · b = c, it should be possible to “re-separate” the element c into the combination “a · b”. For example, we can separate a translation of n- dimensional space into a series of n consecutive translations, one along each dimension. We can also separate any permutation into a series of two-element swaps. It is this concept which will motivate additional restrictions added to a set with a law of composition, making it worthy of being what we call a group. The property of being able to rewrite an element as a combination of constituent elements is primarily encapsulated in the notion of associativity. Say we take a combination of two elements, and wish to compose it with another element.
Recommended publications
  • The Mathematical Structure of the Aesthetic
    Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 12 June 2017 doi:10.20944/preprints201706.0055.v1 Peer-reviewed version available at Philosophies 2017, 2, 14; doi:10.3390/philosophies2030014 Article A New Kind of Aesthetics – The Mathematical Structure of the Aesthetic Akihiro Kubota 1,*, Hirokazu Hori 2, Makoto Naruse 3 and Fuminori Akiba 4 1 Art and Media Course, Department of Information Design, Tama Art University, 2-1723 Yarimizu, Hachioji, Tokyo 192-0394, Japan; [email protected] 2 Interdisciplinary Graduate School, University of Yamanashi, 4-3-11 Takeda, Kofu,Yamanashi 400-8511, Japan; [email protected] 3 Network System Research Institute, National Institute of Information and Communications Technology, 4-2-1 Nukui-kita, Koganei, Tokyo 184-8795, Japan; [email protected] 4 Philosophy of Information Group, Department of Systems and Social Informatics, Nagoya University, Furo-cho, Chikusa-ku, Nagoya, Aichi 464-8601, Japan; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +81-42-679-5634 Abstract: This paper proposes a new approach to investigation into the aesthetics. Specifically, it argues that it is possible to explain the aesthetic and its underlying dynamic relations with axiomatic structure (the octahedral axiom derived category) based on contemporary mathematics – namely, category theory – and through this argument suggests the possibility for discussion about the mathematical structure of the aesthetic. If there was a way to describe the structure of aesthetics with the language of mathematical structures and mathematical axioms – a language completely devoid of arbitrariness – then we would make possible a synthetical argument about the essential human activity of “the aesthetics”, and we would also gain a new method and viewpoint on the philosophy and meaning of the act of creating a work of art and artistic activities.
    [Show full text]
  • Structure” of Physics: a Case Study∗ (Journal of Philosophy 106 (2009): 57–88)
    The “Structure” of Physics: A Case Study∗ (Journal of Philosophy 106 (2009): 57–88) Jill North We are used to talking about the “structure” posited by a given theory of physics. We say that relativity is a theory about spacetime structure. Special relativity posits one spacetime structure; different models of general relativity posit different spacetime structures. We also talk of the “existence” of these structures. Special relativity says that the world’s spacetime structure is Minkowskian: it posits that this spacetime structure exists. Understanding structure in this sense seems important for understand- ing what physics is telling us about the world. But it is not immediately obvious just what this structure is, or what we mean by the existence of one structure, rather than another. The idea of mathematical structure is relatively straightforward. There is geometric structure, topological structure, algebraic structure, and so forth. Mathematical structure tells us how abstract mathematical objects t together to form different types of mathematical spaces. Insofar as we understand mathematical objects, we can understand mathematical structure. Of course, what to say about the nature of mathematical objects is not easy. But there seems to be no further problem for understanding mathematical structure. ∗For comments and discussion, I am extremely grateful to David Albert, Frank Arntzenius, Gordon Belot, Josh Brown, Adam Elga, Branden Fitelson, Peter Forrest, Hans Halvorson, Oliver Davis Johns, James Ladyman, David Malament, Oliver Pooley, Brad Skow, TedSider, Rich Thomason, Jason Turner, Dmitri Tymoczko, the philosophy faculty at Yale, audience members at The University of Michigan in fall 2006, and in 2007 at the Paci c APA, the Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and Mind Association, and the Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference.
    [Show full text]
  • Group Theory
    Appendix A Group Theory This appendix is a survey of only those topics in group theory that are needed to understand the composition of symmetry transformations and its consequences for fundamental physics. It is intended to be self-contained and covers those topics that are needed to follow the main text. Although in the end this appendix became quite long, a thorough understanding of group theory is possible only by consulting the appropriate literature in addition to this appendix. In order that this book not become too lengthy, proofs of theorems were largely omitted; again I refer to other monographs. From its very title, the book by H. Georgi [211] is the most appropriate if particle physics is the primary focus of interest. The book by G. Costa and G. Fogli [102] is written in the same spirit. Both books also cover the necessary group theory for grand unification ideas. A very comprehensive but also rather dense treatment is given by [428]. Still a classic is [254]; it contains more about the treatment of dynamical symmetries in quantum mechanics. A.1 Basics A.1.1 Definitions: Algebraic Structures From the structureless notion of a set, one can successively generate more and more algebraic structures. Those that play a prominent role in physics are defined in the following. Group A group G is a set with elements gi and an operation ◦ (called group multiplication) with the properties that (i) the operation is closed: gi ◦ g j ∈ G, (ii) a neutral element g0 ∈ G exists such that gi ◦ g0 = g0 ◦ gi = gi , (iii) for every gi exists an −1 ∈ ◦ −1 = = −1 ◦ inverse element gi G such that gi gi g0 gi gi , (iv) the operation is associative: gi ◦ (g j ◦ gk) = (gi ◦ g j ) ◦ gk.
    [Show full text]
  • The (Homo)Morphism Concept: Didactic Transposition, Meta-Discourse and Thematisation Thomas Hausberger
    The (homo)morphism concept: didactic transposition, meta-discourse and thematisation Thomas Hausberger To cite this version: Thomas Hausberger. The (homo)morphism concept: didactic transposition, meta-discourse and the- matisation. International Journal of Research in Undergraduate Mathematics Education, Springer, 2017, 3 (3), pp.417-443. 10.1007/s40753-017-0052-7. hal-01408419 HAL Id: hal-01408419 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01408419 Submitted on 20 Feb 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) The (homo)morphism concept: didactic transposition, meta-discourse and thematisation Thomas Hausberger Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract This article focuses on the didactic transposition of the homomor- phism concept and on the elaboration and evaluation of an activity dedicated to the teaching of this fundamental concept in Abstract Algebra. It does not restrict to Group Theory but on the contrary raises the issue of the teaching and learning of algebraic structuralism, thus bridging Group and Ring Theo- ries and highlighting the phenomenon of thematisation. Emphasis is made on epistemological analysis and its interaction with didactics. The rationale of the isomorphism and homomorphism concepts is discussed, in particular through a textbook analysis focusing on the meta-discourse that mathematicians offer to illuminate the concepts.
    [Show full text]
  • The Design and Validation of a Group Theory Concept Inventory
    Portland State University PDXScholar Dissertations and Theses Dissertations and Theses Summer 8-10-2015 The Design and Validation of a Group Theory Concept Inventory Kathleen Mary Melhuish Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/open_access_etds Part of the Algebra Commons, Higher Education Commons, and the Science and Mathematics Education Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Melhuish, Kathleen Mary, "The Design and Validation of a Group Theory Concept Inventory" (2015). Dissertations and Theses. Paper 2490. https://doi.org/10.15760/etd.2487 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. The Design and Validation of a Group Theory Concept Inventory by Kathleen Mary Melhuish A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Mathematics Education Dissertation Committee: Sean Larsen, Chair John Caughman Samuel Cook Andrea Goforth Portland State University 2015 © 2015 Kathleen Mary Melhuish Abstract Within undergraduate mathematics education, there are few validated instruments designed for large-scale usage. The Group Concept Inventory (GCI) was created as an instrument to evaluate student conceptions related to introductory group theory topics. The inventory was created in three phases: domain analysis, question creation, and field-testing. The domain analysis phase included using an expert protocol to arrive at the topics to be assessed, analyzing curriculum, and reviewing literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Structure, Isomorphism and Symmetry We Want to Give a General Definition
    Structure, Isomorphism and Symmetry We want to give a general definition of what is meant by a (mathematical) structure that will cover most of the structures that you will meet. It is in this setting that we will define what is meant by isomorphism and symmetry. We begin with the simplest type of structure, that of an internal structure on a set. Definition 1 (Internal Structure). An internal structure on a set A is any element of A or of any set that can be obtained from A by means of Cartesian products and the power set operation, e.g., A £ A, }(A), A £ }(A), }((A £ A) £ A),... Example 1 (An Element of A). a 2 A Example 2 (A Relation on A). R ⊆ A £ A =) R 2 }(A £ A). Example 3 (A Binary Operation on A). p : A £ A ! A =) p 2 }((A £ A) £ A). To define an external structure on a set A (e.g. a vector space structure) we introduce a second set K. The elements of K or of those sets which can be obtained from K and A by means of Cartesian products and the power set operation and which is not an internal structure on A are called K-structures on A. Definition 2 (K-Structure). A K-structure on a set A is any element of K or of those sets which can be obtained from K and A by means of Cartesian products and the power set operation and which is not an internal structure on A. Example 4 (External Operation on A).
    [Show full text]
  • How Structure Sense for Algebraic Expressions Or Equations Is Related to Structure Sense for Abstract Algebra
    Mathematics Education Research Journal 2008, Vol. 20, No. 2, 93-104 How Structure Sense for Algebraic Expressions or Equations is Related to Structure Sense for Abstract Algebra Jarmila Novotná Maureen Hoch Charles University, Czech Republic Tel Aviv University, Israel Many students have difficulties with basic algebraic concepts at high school and at university. In this paper two levels of algebraic structure sense are defined: for high school algebra and for university algebra. We suggest that high school algebra structure sense components are sub-components of some university algebra structure sense components, and that several components of university algebra structure sense are analogies of high school algebra structure sense components. We present a theoretical argument for these hypotheses, with some examples. We recommend emphasizing structure sense in high school algebra in the hope of easing students’ paths in university algebra. The cooperation of the authors in the domain of structure sense originated at a scientific conference where they each presented the results of their research in their own countries: Israel and the Czech Republic. Their findings clearly show that they are dealing with similar situations, concepts, obstacles, and so on, at two different levels—high school and university. In their classrooms, high school teachers are dismayed by students’ inability to apply basic algebraic techniques in contexts different from those they have experienced. Many students who arrive in high school with excellent grades in mathematics from the junior-high school prove to be poor at algebraic manipulations. Even students who succeed well in 10th grade algebra show disappointing results later on, because of the algebra.
    [Show full text]
  • Set (Mathematics) from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    Set (mathematics) From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia A set in mathematics is a collection of well defined and distinct objects, considered as an object in its own right. Sets are one of the most fundamental concepts in mathematics. Developed at the end of the 19th century, set theory is now a ubiquitous part of mathematics, and can be used as a foundation from which nearly all of mathematics can be derived. In mathematics education, elementary topics such as Venn diagrams are taught at a young age, while more advanced concepts are taught as part of a university degree. Contents The intersection of two sets is made up of the objects contained in 1 Definition both sets, shown in a Venn 2 Describing sets diagram. 3 Membership 3.1 Subsets 3.2 Power sets 4 Cardinality 5 Special sets 6 Basic operations 6.1 Unions 6.2 Intersections 6.3 Complements 6.4 Cartesian product 7 Applications 8 Axiomatic set theory 9 Principle of inclusion and exclusion 10 See also 11 Notes 12 References 13 External links Definition A set is a well defined collection of objects. Georg Cantor, the founder of set theory, gave the following definition of a set at the beginning of his Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre:[1] A set is a gathering together into a whole of definite, distinct objects of our perception [Anschauung] and of our thought – which are called elements of the set. The elements or members of a set can be anything: numbers, people, letters of the alphabet, other sets, and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • 2. Duality in Mathematical Structure by Tadashi OHKUMA Departmentof Mathematics,Tokyo Institute of Technology,Tokyo (Comm
    6 [Vol. 34, 2. Duality in Mathematical Structure By Tadashi OHKUMA Departmentof Mathematics,Tokyo Institute of Technology,Tokyo (Comm. by Z. SUETUNA,M.J,A., Jan. 13, 1958) 1. In many representation theorems of different branches of ab- stract mathematics, for example, representation of ordered sets by cuts, that of lattices by sets of ideals, the conjugate spaces of Banach spaces, or the duality of groups, there seem to appear some similar concep- tions. In order to deal with those representation theorems simultane- ously, we made an attempt to set up a concept of a universal mathe- matical structure, in which the main role is played by some selected applications of a system to a system, which we call homomorphisms, but they may be continuous mappings in topological spaces, order- preserving mappings in ordered sets or linear operators in linear spaces. The definitions of our structure and some results of them will be stated in this note, but we omit the detail of proofs which, as well as the applications to individual specialized systems, will be published elsewhere. 2. Let be a family of sets. A set in is called a system. If X and Z are systems and Z C X, then Z is called a subsystem of X. We assume that, to each pair of systems X and Y, a family Hom (X, Y) of applications which map X into Y is distinguished. An application co in Hom (X, Y) is called a homomorphism of X in Y. Further we assume that those homomorphisms and the family satisfy the following axioms which fall into five groups (A)-(E).
    [Show full text]
  • Diffeomorphic Density Registration
    DIFFEOMORPHIC DENSITY REGISTRATION MARTIN BAUER, SARANG JOSHI, AND KLAS MODIN Abstract. In this book chapter we study the Riemannian Geometry of the density registration problem: Given two densities (not necessarily probability densities) defined on a smooth finite dimensional manifold find a diffeomorphism which transforms one to the other. This problem is motivated by the medical imaging application of track- ing organ motion due to respiration in Thoracic CT imaging where the fundamental physical property of conservation of mass naturally leads to modeling CT attenuation as a density. We will study the intimate link between the Riemannian metrics on the space of diffeomorphisms and those on the space of densities. We finally develop novel computationally efficient algorithms and demonstrate there applicability for registering RCCT thoracic imaging. Contents 1. Introduction1 2. Diffeomorphisms and densities2 2.1. α-actions.4 3. Diffeomorphic Density registration5 4. Density registration in the LDDMM-framework6 5. Optimal Information Transport7 5.1. Application: random sampling from non-uniform distribution 10 6. A gradient flow approach 12 6.1. Thoracic Density Registration 16 Acknowledgements 20 References 21 1. Introduction Over the last decade image registration has received intense interest, both with re- spect to medical imaging applications as well to the mathematical foundations of the general problem of estimating a transformation that brings two or more given medical images into a common coordinate system [18, 22, 41, 27, 39,2,1, 13]. In this chapter arXiv:1807.05505v2 [math.OC] 23 Jul 2018 we focus on a subclass of registration problems which term as density registration. The primary difference between density registration and general image registration is in how Date: July 24, 2018.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Structures from Hilbert to Bourbaki: the Evolution of an Image of Mathematics Leo Corry, Tel-Aviv University
    Mathematical Structures from Hilbert to Bourbaki: The Evolution of an Image of Mathematics Leo Corry, Tel-Aviv University The notion of a mathematical structure is a most pervasive and central one in twentieth- century mathematics. Over several decades of this century, many mathematical disciplines, particularly those belonging to the “pure” realm, developed under the conception that the aim of research is the elucidation of certain structures associated with them. At certain periods of time, especially from the 1950s to the 1970s, it was not uncommon in universities around the world to conceive the ideal professional formation of young mathematicians in terms of a gradual mastering of the various structures that were considered to embody the hard-core of mathematics. Two important points of reference for understanding the development of twentieth century mathematics in general pertain the ideas of David Hilbert, on the one hand, and of the Bourbaki group, on the other hand. This is also true, in particular, for the development of the conception of mathematics as a science of structures. In the present article I explain how, and to what extent, the idea of a mathematical structure appears in the works of Hilbert and of Bourbaki. My presentation will be based on defining the idea of a mathematical structure as a classical example of an image of mathematics. This image appeared for the first time in its full-fledged conception in 1930, in van der Waerden’s classical book Moderne Algebra. In the work of David Hilbert we will find many of the basic building blocks from which van der Waerden’s presentation came to be built.
    [Show full text]
  • Exotic Smoothness and Physics
    Exotic Smoothness and Physics Carl H. Brans Physics Department Loyola University New Orleans, LA 70118 e-mail:BRANS @ MUSIC.LOYNO.EDU March 29, 1994 Abstract The essential role played by differentiable structures in physics is reviewed in light of recent mathematical discoveries that topologically trivial space-time models, especially the simplest one, R4, possess a rich multiplicity of such structures, no two of which are diffeomorphic to each other and thus to the standard one. This means that physics has available to it a new panoply of structures available for space-time models. These can be thought of as source of new global, but not properly topological, features. This paper reviews some background differential topology together with a discussion of the role which a differentiable structure necessarily plays in the statement of any physical theory, recalling that diffeomorphisms are at the heart of the principle of general relativity. Some of the history of the discovery of exotic, i.e., non-standard, differentiable structures is reviewed. Some new results suggesting the spatial localization of such exotic structures are described and speculations are made on the possible opportunities that such structures present for the further development of physical theories. To be published in Journal of Mathematical Physics. arXiv:gr-qc/9405010v1 4 May 1994 1 Introduction Almost all modern physical theories are stated in terms of fields over a smooth manifold, typically involving differential equations for these fields. Obviously the mechanism underlying the notion of differentiation in a space-time model is indispensable for physics. However, the essentially local nature of differentiation has led us to assume that the mathematics underlying calculus as applied to physics is trivial and unique.
    [Show full text]