Read Book Tool-Being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Read Book Tool-Being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects TOOL-BEING: HEIDEGGER AND THE METAPHYSICS OF OBJECTS PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Graham Harman | 256 pages | 14 Aug 2002 | Open Court Publishing Co ,U.S. | 9780812694444 | English | Chicago, IL, United States Tool-being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects PDF Book Nietzsche and the Metaphysics of the Tragic. Footnotes to Plato. The Threefold Mathew Glenn rated it liked it Feb 28, I agree with other reviewers that Harman spends more time on critiquing others for misreading Heidegger, and fails to justify his claims that he is going beyond Heidegger. Lucas D. Very flowery ways of getting to not that flowery material. Cultural critic Steven Shaviro has criticized object-oriented ontology as too dismissive of process philosophy. This dual structure belongs to every entity, and is not a statement about the ups and downs of human activity. Editorial team. Stuart Elden - - Athlone Press. The God of Metaphysics. No trivia or quizzes yet. Linas gab rated it it was ok Sep 20, Skip to content. First, the Ontic Principle states that "there is no difference that does not make a difference". Similarly, concepts of difference predicated upon negation—that which objects are not or lack when placed in comparison with one another—are dismissed as arising only from the perspective of consciousness, rather than an ontological difference that affirms independent being. Towards Speculative Realism: Essays and Lectures. I make no appeal to any authority beyond the merits or flaws of the book itself. Learn how and when to remove these template messages. In Bryant's words, "if a difference is made, then the being is". This is why enthusiasts of Greek philosophy are often less excited by the commentaries of Heidegger than by those of Ross or Zeller or Jaeger or Leo Strauss, none of whom can equal his originality as a philosopher. In Tool-Being, Graham Harman departs from the present linguistic method of analytic and continental philosophy in desire of Heideggerian object- oriented examine into the key contours of items. Joad Mind, New Series, Vol. With Tool-Being , Harman takes a bewildering, and to his credit, original interpretive leap in his reading of early Heidegger, arguing that the conception of Dasein's non-thematic "background" comportment to beings-- Zuhandenheit , or ready-to-handness--is a brilliant kernel of thought surrounded by superfluity, and t The core idea sustaining OOO object-oriented ontology is so misguided that one has to wonder how it gained any parlance within contemporary philosophical circles in the first place. Kevin C rated it it was amazing May 25, Please help improve it by removing references to unreliable sources where they are used inappropriately. I cite Emmanuel Levinas for his dramatic sense of the strife between the visible and withdrawn faces of the things themselves, and praise Xavier Zubiri for insisting that the essence of any object must be incommensurable with all of its relations. Oct 19, Manraaj Nijjar rated it really liked it. According to Shaviro, the process philosophies of Alfred North Whitehead , Gilbert Simondon , and Gilles Deleuze account for how objects come into existence and endure over time, in contrast to the view that objects "are already there" taken by object-oriented approaches. Refining the Problem Just a moment while we sign you in to your Goodreads account. You know the saying: There's no time like the present Show description. Whatever Heidegger's intentions may have been, his theory of equipment applies to all entities : chisels, nuclear warheads, and sunflowers. A Second Axis 80 9. Accordingly, it is pointless to read Heidegger's analysis through the lenses of pragmatism. The concepts I have selected are: Dasein, being, time, truth, Ereignis, language, and technology. Indeed, I believe that some readers will find the argument of the book not only plausible, but exciting. Living and Nonliving Occasionalism. Tool-Being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects. Written in a colorful style, it will be of interest to anyone open to new trends in present-day philosophy. Sign in to use this feature. II : — Since I am concerned with a colder and more elusive theme, it seems better to keep explicit political questions in the background. Real objects are objects that withdraw from all experience, whereas sensual objects are those that exist only in experience. These are two very different ambitions. Graham Harman. The Being in Phenomena Ewa Justka rated it really liked it Feb 07, Tool-being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects Writer The belief seems to be that entities are the source of our philosophical problems, and that the solution is to retreat ever deeper into the conditions underlying these entities, into the very conditions of these conditions , and even back into the "clearing-opening play" in which these conditions of conditions e merge. Skip this one. On Heidegger on Logic. For whatever the depth of his philosophical achievement, it seems to me that both he and his followers have an inflated sense of the legitimate scope of his thought. Trivia About Tool-Being: Heide When it comes to his main arguments I found him a little short. The best response to both kinds of charges is simply to move forward, trusting that all fair-minded readers will form a reasoned verdict of their own. I regard as irrelevant the question of whether Heidegger meant to grant the prominence to tool-being that it receives in this book. Sign in Create an account. Philosophy of religion. Reversal: Broken Tools 44 5. In chapter 3 , I make use of the results of the first chapter to sketch the outlines of an object-oriented philosophy. I hold that this can be done on a "local" level without strange and arbitrary invocations of a hidden God. Heidegger on Objects and Things. Matthew David Segall has argued that object-oriented philosophers should explore the theological and anthropological implications of their ideas in order to avoid "slipping into the nihilism of some speculative realists, where human values are a fluke in an uncaring and fundamentally entropic universe". The tool-analysis is read as the triumph either of practical activity over theoretical abstraction, or of the network of linguistic signs over the ever unpopular "things in themselves. And 'buffered' means that [real objects] do not fuse into [sensual objects], nor [sensual objects] into their sensual neighbors, since all are held at bay through unknown firewalls sustaining the privacy of each. Although I will argue that H eidegger's philosophy is compatible with a discussion of numerous concrete themes, I also claim that none of these themes can actually be found in his writings. Kant, Heidegger, and the Circularity of Transcendental Inquiry. Hence, the tool-analysis is far more encompassing than the famed analytic of Dasein. Retrieved 10 September Cultural critic Steven Shaviro has criticized object-oriented ontology as too dismissive of process philosophy. Coupling Heidegger's tool-analysis with the phenomenological insights of Edmund Husserl , Harman introduces two types of objects: real objects and sensual objects. Paperback , pages. Jessica Wincek rated it really liked it Dec 17, Causation, says Harman, is always vicarious, asymmetrical, and buffered:. Additionally, Bryant has proposed the concept of 'wilderness ontology' to explain the philosophical pluralization of agency away from human privilege. It achieves this by undermining from the outset any possible presence of tool- beings. Since I am concerned with a colder and more elusive theme, it seems better to keep explicit political questions in the background. Tool-Being is q Harman occupies an interesting place in the Speculative Realism canon for me, in that I find his chief ideas to be rather bland compared with Meillassoux, Brassier, Negarestani, etc. Read e-book online Metaphysics and the philosophy of science : new essays PDF. Graham Harman - - Zero Books. Martin Heidegger in Continental Philosophy. This book was a joy and frustration to me. An editor has expressed concern that this article may have a number of irrelevant citations. Remember me Forgot password? Alien Phenomenology. Sincerity characterizes the absorption of a real object by a sensual object, in a manner that "takes seriously" the sensual object without containing or being contiguous to it. Heidegger could have escaped this perpetual collapse into a repetitive dualism o nly by developing his metabole: the sketchily proposed Umschlag "metontology," a theory of the or turnabout between an object's infrastructural depth and its sparkling exterior contours. Footnotes to Plato. Finally, no relation represents the typical condition of reality, since real objects are incapable of direct interaction and are limited in their causal influence upon and relation to other objects. Not Pragmatism Reference 24 3. Graham Harman - - Cosmos and History 6 1 Lucas D. Levi Bryant began what he describes as "a very intense philosophical email exchange" with Harman, over the course of which Bryant became convinced of the credibility of object-oriented thought. The two becomes a four; reality is made up of quadrants. Theory 56 7. The Life of Objects. Tool-being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects Reviews Google Books no proxy Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server Configure custom proxy use this if your affiliation does not provide a proxy. Alma P rated it it was ok Nov 25, Fractured Politics. The Structure of Objects. Certainly, Heidegger deals yet another mortal wound to metaphysics of the old-fashioned kind, the kind that is slapped and pummeled still further by Derrida, Wittgenstein, and others. The dominant theme in recent books on Heidegger has been that of "the political": or in franker terms, Nazism. Skip to content. Retrieved 15 September The Being in Phenomena Ewa Justka rated it really liked it Feb 07, Timothy Morton became involved with object-oriented ontology after his ecological writings were favorably compared with the movement's ideas.
Recommended publications
  • Against 'Flat Ontologies'
    64 Ray Brassier Deleveling: Against ‘Flat Ontologies’ Ray Brassier is associate professor of philosophy at the American University of Beirut. What I am going to present today is a critical discussion of the 65 tenets of so-called ‘flat ontology’. The expression ‘flat onto- logy’ has a complicated genealogy. It was originally coined as a pejorative term for empiricist philosophies of science by Roy Bhaskar in his 1975 book, A Realist Theory of Science. By the late 1990s, it had begun to acquire a positive sense in discus- sions of the work of Deleuze and Guattari. But it only achieved widespread currency in the wake of Manual De Landa’s 2002 book about Deleuze, Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy. More recently, it has been championed by proponents of ‘ob- ject-oriented ontology’ and ‘new materialism’. It is its use by these theorists that I will be discussing today. I will begin by explaining the ‘four theses’ of flat onto- logy, as formulated by Levi Bryant. Bryant is a proponent of ‘object-oriented ontology’, a school of thought founded by Graham Harman. In his 2010 work The Democracy of Objects, Bryant encapsulates flat ontology in the following four theses: Thesis 1: “First, due to the split characteristic of all ob- jects, flat ontology rejects any ontology of transcendence or presence that privileges one sort of entity as the origin of all others and as fully present to itself.” Thesis 2: “Second, […] the world or the universe does not exist. […] [T]here is no super-object that gathers all other ob- jects together in a single, harmonious
    [Show full text]
  • Certificate for Approving the Dissertation
    MIAMI UNIVERSITY The Graduate School Certificate for Approving the Dissertation We hereby approve the Dissertation of Kevin J. Rutherford Candidate for the Degree: Doctor of Philosophy Director (Jason Palmeri) Reader (Michele Simmons) Reader (Heidi McKee) Reader (Kate Ronald) Graduate School Representative (Bo Brinkman) ABSTRACT PACK YOUR THINGS AND GO: BRINGING OBJECTS TO THE FORE IN RHETORIC AND COMPOSITION by Kevin J. Rutherford This dissertation project focuses on object-oriented rhetoric (OOR), a perspective that questions the traditional notions of rhetorical action as solely a human province. The project makes three major, interrelated claims: that OOR provides a unique and productive methodology to examine the inclusion of the non-human in rhetorical study; that to some extent, rhetoric has always been interested in the way nonhuman objects interact with humans; and that these claims have profound implications for our activities as teachers and scholars. Chapter one situates OOR within current scholarship in composition and rhetoric, arguing that it can serve as a useful methodology for the field despite rhetoric’s traditional focus on epistemology and human symbolic action. Chapter two examines rhetorical history to demonstrate that a view of rhetoric that includes nonhuman actors is not new, but has often been marginalized. Chapter three examines two videogames as sites of theory and practice for object-oriented rhetoric, specifically focusing on a sense of metaphor to understand the experience of nonhuman rhetors. Chapter four interrogates the network surrounding a review aggregation website to argue that, while some nonhumans may be unhelpful rhetorical collaborators, OOR can assist us in improving relationships with them.
    [Show full text]
  • 147 Levi R. Bryant. Onto-Cartography: an Ontology Of
    Philosophy in Review XXXVI (August 2016), no. 4 Levi R. Bryant. Onto-Cartography: An Ontology of Machines and Media. Edinburgh University Press 2014. 312 pp. $130.00 USD (Hardcover ISBN 9780748679966); $39.95 USD (Paperback ISBN 9780748679973). Levi Bryant characterizes himself as a fervent convert who has recently ‘awoken from [the] dogmatic slumbers’ of historical materialism to produce an anti-humanist political philosophy that dispenses with the ‘discursivism’ and anthropocentrism that has dominated Western philosophy for far too long (4). He has sought to displace the prevailing assumptions of cultural studies and critical theory by crafting a materialist metaphysics that decentralizes humanity and proposes a practice—onto- cartography—that demonstrates how the natural environment shapes our social relations. This new ontological framework, he argues, will allow us to develop more effective strategies for the estab- lishment of justice. The practice of onto-cartography presupposes what Bryant calls a machine-oriented ontol- ogy. Bryant proposes that ‘all beings’, ‘all entities, things, or objects are machines’ (18, 23). According to this model, being consists entirely of machines ‘at a variety of different levels of scale’, from galaxies and social institutions to subatomic particles (6). He broadly defines a machine as any system of operations that takes on inputs and transforms them to produce outputs. So, for example, a tree is a machine that absorbs sunlight and carbon dioxide and, through the process of photosyn- thesis, operates on those inputs to produce oxygen, its output. Moreover, all machines are enmeshed in a fabric of assemblages or a network of machines. An assemblage is a system of relations between ‘coupled’ machines in which particular machinic nodes shape the functioning and development of other machines within the field of relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Degruyter Opphil Opphil-2020-0105 314..334 ++
    Open Philosophy 2020; 3: 314–334 Object-Oriented Ontology and Its Critics Graham Harman* The Battle of Objects and Subjects: Concerning Sbriglia and Žižek’s Subject Lessons Anthology https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2020-0105 received April 8, 2020; accepted June 16, 2020 Abstract: This article mounts a defense of Object-Oriented Ontology (OOO) from various criticisms made in Russell Sbriglia and Slavoj Žižek’sco-edited anthology Subject Lessons. Along with Sbriglia and Žižek’s own Introduction to the volume, the article responds to the chapters by Todd McGowan, Adrian Johnston, and Molly Anne Rothenberg, the three in which my own version of OOO is most frequently discussed. Keywords: Ljubljana School, Object-Oriented Ontology, Slavoj Žižek, G. W. F. Hegel, Jacques Lacan, thing- in-itself, materialism, realism Russell Sbriglia and Slavoj Žižek’sco-edited collection Subject Lessons: Hegel, Lacan, and the Future of Materialism has long been awaited in circles devoted to Object-Oriented Ontology (OOO).¹ All twelve chapters in the anthology (eleven plus the editors’ Introduction) are written from the merciless Lacano- Hegelian standpoint that defines the Ljubljana School, one of the most fruitful trends in the continental philosophy of recent decades.² The Slovenian core of the group is here – Žižek, Mladen Dolar, and Alenka Zupančič – as are many of their most capable international allies (though Joan Copjec is keenly missed), along with some impressive younger voices. As a rule, the book is most impressive when making a positive case for what G. W. F. Hegel and Jacques Lacan still have to offer contemporary philosophy; all of the chapters are clearly written, and some are among the most lucid statements I have seen from the Ljubljana group.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem: the Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2013 The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze Ryan J. Johnson Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Johnson, R. (2013). The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/706 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College & Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Copyright by Ryan J. Johnson 2014 ii THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson Approved December 6, 2013 _______________________________ ______________________________ Daniel Selcer, Ph.D Kelly Arenson, Ph.D Associate Professor of Philosophy Assistant Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ______________________________ John Protevi, Ph.D Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ______________________________ ______________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Ronald Polansky, Ph.D. Dean, McAnulty College & Graduate Chair, Department of Philosophy School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Queer: Towards a Non-Standard Queer Theory1 Michael O’Rourke Independent Colleges, Dublin
    IDENTITIES journal for politics, gender and culture Quantum Queer: Towards a Non-Standard Queer Theory1 Michael O’Rourke Independent Colleges, Dublin Abstract: This essay looks at some potentially fruitful lines of correspondence between Laruelle’s non-philosophy and gender, feminist and queer theories. Drawing on the work of leading Laruelle scholars I seek to outline some highly tentative principles for a non-standard queer theory which would help us to think about democracy, the human, performativity, sexual difference and some other crucial questions for current queer theorizing. Keywords: Laruelle, queer theory, non-philosophy, flat ontology, the human, sexual difference, the stranger. Black Box The French non-philosopher François Laruelle writes that: Like an artisan, engineer, or designer, I am going to attempt to construct in front of you a so- called apparatus of photo-fiction … [I]t is an exercise in the construction of a theoretical object, and is thus transparent, but which will function more like a black box.2 This paper is my latest attempt to bring Laruelle’s non-philosophy and queer theory into productive conversation with each other.3 I am going to attempt to construct in front of you a so-called apparatus of queer-fiction, a theoretical object which will not seek to render either queer theory or non-philosophy transparent, but rather to allow them to function more like black boxes. With that disclaimer in place, it must be said that the aim of the present article will be to demonstrate that Laruelle’s non-philosophy has much to offer to queer theory, feminist thought and gender studies.
    [Show full text]
  • The Speculative Turn Continental Materialism and Realism
    The Speculative Turn Continental Materialism and Realism Edited by Levi Bryant, Nick Srnicek and Graham Harman Open Access Statement – Please Read This book is Open Access. This work is not simply an electronic book; it is the open access version of a work that exists in a number of forms, the traditional printed form being one of them. Copyright Notice This work is ‘Open Access’, published under a creative commons license which means that you are free to copy, distribute, display, and perform the work as long as you clearly attribute the work to the authors, that you do not use this work for any commercial gain in any form and that you in no way alter, transform or build on the work outside of its use in normal aca- demic scholarship without express permission of the author and the publisher of this volume. Furthermore, for any reuse or distribution, you must make clear to others the license terms of this work. For more information see the details of the creative commons licence at this website: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/2.5/ This means that you can: • read and store this document free of charge • distribute it for personal use free of charge • print sections of the work for personal use • read or perform parts of the work in a context where no financial transactions take place However, you cannot: • gain financially from the work in anyway • sell the work or seek monies in relation to the distribution of the work • use the work in any commercial activity of any kind • profit a third party indirectly via use or distribution
    [Show full text]
  • An Interview with Levi Bryant
    Anarchist Developments in Cultural Studies ISSN: 1923-5615 2013.2: Ontological Anarché: Beyond Materialism and Idealism An Interview with Levi Bryant Christos Stergiou CS: How would you describe the differences between your ontol- ogy and other object-oriented ontologies? LB: As we use the term, object-oriented ontology (OOO) refers to any ontological position that affirms the mind-independent exist- ence of substances, entities, or objects. In this regard, ontologies as diverse as Aristotle’s, Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz’s, Alfred North Whitehead’s, Jane Bennett’s, Bruno Latour’s, etc., are ob- ject-oriented ontologies. Among these ontologies, of course, you have differences and disagreements. Whitehead, for example, holds that actual occasions (his name for substance) are constituted by their relations to other actual occasions and eternal objects. Addition- ally, he argues that actual occasions are processes. Graham Har- man’s object-oriented philosophy (OOP), by contrast, argues that objects are withdrawn from their relations and possess abiding essences. There is thus a debate here in object-oriented ontology as to what a substance is. In the past I referred to my ontology as “onticology,” while these days I refer to it as machine-oriented ontology (MOO). I argue that every entity or substance is a machine. Machines are defined by their operations or powers (capacities). Following Ian Bogost, I define an operation as an activity that takes one or more inputs and performs a transformation on it, producing an output. For example, in photosynthesis a tree takes sunlight, water, and carbon dioxide, performs operations on these materials, and pro- duces outputs in the form of cells, energy, oxygen, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Questions for Levi Bryant, Author of Onto-Cartography
    Onto- Cartography – Author Q&A Page | 1 Onto-Cartography An Ontology of Machines and Media By Levi Bryant Part of the Speculative Realism series Author Q&A with Levi Bryant Asked by Graham Harman, Speculative Realism series editor Graham – Let’s start with your title, Onto-Cartography. You have always been remarkable among continental philosophy authors for the vast range of disciplines in which you read. To what extent does onto-cartography imply a turn to geography? Are you using the term in a geographical sense, or in some other sense? Levi – While I think geography is of the utmost importance in the social sciences – in the book I describe it as the queen of the social sciences – Onto-Cartography isn’t a philosophy of geography. ‘Cartography’ signifies ‘map’. There are a variety of different types of maps, some geographical, others not. For example, Marx gives us a map of how capitalism functions and is structured, while Foucault gives us maps of how knowledge is structured in particular time periods in works like The Order of Things. The discipline of anatomy can be thought as a map of how bodies are configured. By contrast, the term ‘onto’, from the Greek, refers to ‘things’ or what I call ‘machines’. In Onto-Cartography I’m interested in developing a technique for mapping relations between expressive or semiotic machines and corporeal or material machines so as to investigate the gravity or power they exercise over us so that we might devise strategies for escaping oppressive worlds. I’d like to know how we might achieve escape velocity from these assemblages of words and things.
    [Show full text]
  • ONTO-CARTOGRAPHY, OR ONTO-NOSTALGIA Notes on Levi Bryant's ONTO-CARTOGRAPHY by Terence Blake
    ONTO-CARTOGRAPHY, OR ONTO-NOSTALGIA notes on Levi Bryant's ONTO-CARTOGRAPHY by Terence Blake 1) POST-MONIST THOUGHT vs "HARD AND CONVINCING " REALISM During the post-structuralist period (Deleuze, Lyotard, Serres, but also Feyerabend and Rorty) it was widely thought that monism had been thoroughly refuted and discredited. However, recent developments in the last decade have shown that the refutations were insufficient, as the discredit of monism began to fade and a new form of monist ontology, in both scientistic and nonscientistic variants, came to light and began to spread. Post-structuralism was seen as insufficient to prevent the rise of these new forms of monism, loosely grouped together under the rubric of "speculative realism". The post-structuralists' positive valuation of "speculation" as conceptual investigation and experimentation was considered by some to be in danger of founding a new idealism, called by some "constructivism" and by others "correlationism", enshrining the omnipotence of language, society, or individual and/or collective thought to the detriment of empirical reality. Certain thinkers saw themselves as invested with the mission of reinstating "realism" and subordinating the free play of metaphysical speculation to the hard and convincing real state of affairs. "Hard and convincing" realism represents a return to a grasp on reality by turning post- structuralist critique against itself. A key figure in this monist regression was Alain Badiou, who tried to synthesize both pluralism and monism under the aegis of an ontological realism allied to an adulterated scientism. The conceptual situation became pathological under Badiousian regenting, and it was only a matter of time before a strange new malady appeared, or an old malady in mutated form.
    [Show full text]
  • BETWEEN GRAHAM HARMAN and the DELEUZO-WHITEHEADIAN AXIS Adrian Ivakhiv
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 19 • 2014 • 65-78 BEATNIK BROTHERS? BETWEEN GRAHAM HARMAN AND THE DELEUZO-WHITEHEADIAN AXIS Adrian Ivakhiv INTRODUCTION Recent years have seen a surge of interest among Deleuzian and post-Deleuzian theorists in the metaphysical writings of Alfred North Whitehead. To many, there is a natural affinity between Deleuze and Whitehead, one that is continuous with a line of other thinkers—from Spinoza and Bruno to Bergson, Peirce, James, Simondon, Tarde, Serres, Stengers, and Latour—who are unified by an interest in process, affectivity, and a dynamic and relational ontology.1 Responding to this interest, Graham Harman has argued that these thinkers are falsely allied in a “beatnik brotherhood” of “process philosophers” or “philosophers of immanence.”2 At heart, he counters, their philosophies are radically different. This article examines what is at stake in this debate between Harman and the Deleuzo-Whiteheadians. Ex- amining a series of recent writings by Harman, I will show that Harman overdraws the differences between Whitehead and Deleuze in order to privilege the radical distinction between objects and relations that is at the heart of his own object-oriented ontology (OOO). I will examine some affinities and differences between Har- man’s account of objects and Whitehead’s account of actual occasions, and suggest that the two are not as far apart as Harman makes them appear. The key difference between them, and therefore the central stake in the debate between object-oriented and process-relational ontologies, concerns their respective understandings of temporality. In comparing Harman’s object-oriented ontology with the process-relational metaphysics of Whitehead (and, by extension, Deleuze), this article intends to contribute to a debate that has transpired in what has been called the “speculative realist blogosphere” since at least 2009.
    [Show full text]
  • Object Oriented Ontology, Art and Art-Writing
    After The Passions: Object Oriented Ontology, Art and Art-writing PRUE GIBSON DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF NEW SOUTH WALES 2014 Originality Statement I hereby declare that this submission is my own work and to the best of my knowledge it contains no materials previously published or written by another person, or substantial proportions of material which have been accepted for the award of any other degree or diploma at UNSW or any other educational institution, except where due acknowledgement is made in the thesis. Any contribution made to the research by others, with whom I have worked at UNSW or elsewhere, is explicitly acknowledged in the thesis. I also declare that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work, except to the extent that assistance from others in the project’s design and conception or in style, presentation and linguistic expression is acknowledged. Signed: Dated: i Acknowledgements My supervisor Professor Stephen Muecke welcomed me into academic life and has supported me ever since. He introduced me to Speculative Realism and Object Oriented Ontology and slowed my usual cracking pace to a more considered and cautious speed. Each time I felt I had discovered something new about writing, I realised Stephen had led me there. I have often tried to emulate his mentoring method for my own students: without judgement, enthusiastic and twinkle-eyed. Through the second half of the thesis process, my co-supervisor Professor Edward Scheer jumped in and demanded evidence, structured argument and accountability. This was the perfect timing for a rigorous edit.
    [Show full text]