Aspects of Objectivity and Objective Reference in Kant's Transcendental Idealism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aspects of Objectivity and Objective Reference in Kant's Transcendental Idealism Aspects of Objectivity and Objective Reference in Kant’s Transcendental Idealism Matti Saarni Reports from the Department of Philosophy Vol. 46 ASPECTS OF OBJECTIVITY AND OBJECTIVE REFERENCE IN KANT’S TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM Matti Saarni f}t(t UNIVERSITY ~r~ OFTURKU Copyright © 2020 Matti Saarni SERIES EDITORS: Olli Koistinen Juha Räikkä Department of Philosophy University of Turku FI-20014 Turku Finland ISSN 1457-9332 ISBN 978-951-29-8187-8 (print) ISBN 978-951-29-8188-5 (pdf) Painosalama Oy, Turku 2020 KONE FOUNDATION Written by Matti Saarni Doctoral Programme of Social and Behavioural Sciences, University of Turku, Faculty of Social Sciences, Department of Philosophy, Contemporary History and Political Science Supervised by Professor Olli Koistinen University of Turku, Faculty of Social Sciences, Department of Philosophy, Contemporary History and Political Science Doctor Hemmo Laiho University of Turku, Faculty of Social Sciences, Department of Philosophy, Contemporary History and Political Science Reviewed by Associate Professor Marcel Quarfood University of Umeå Doctor Kari Väyrynen University of Oulu Opponent Doctor Marcel Quarfood University of Umeå Chairperson (custos) Professor Olli Koistinen Turun yliopiston laatujärjestelmän mukaisesti tämän julkaisun alkuperäisyys on tarkastettu Turnitin Originality Check -järjestelmällä. The originality of this dissertation has been checked in accordance with the University of Turku quality assurance system using the Turnitin Originality Check service. Acknowledgements There are infinitely many things without which this work would never have been possible. I try to be grateful. It has been a long, interesting, tiring, frustrating and rewarding project, and I could not have done it alone. I would like, therefore, to thank some of the people who have helped, supported, contributed, or otherwise just been there for this work, for me, and my family. First of all, I heartfeltly want to thank my advisors, Professor Olli Koistinen and Dr. Hemmo Laiho, for supporting, criticizing and guiding me and my work, and, finally, believing in it. This is not to say that I think they ‘bought’ everything I claim here, but rather to say that they take what I claim, and overall write, to be meaningful and important enough to stand as a doctoral dissertation on Kant and objectivity. In addition to Olli and Hemmo, I want to thank everyone at the Turku University Philosophy department/discipline. Often discussions in the coffee room or hallways lead to some insights. For countless reasons, I am deeply grateful to Valtteri Viljanen. All parts of the way. I am also very grateful to Markus Nikkarla, with whom I’ve had countless hours of discussions on the elements of Kant’s critical philosophy, and on other, perhaps even more important matters. I want to thank Joseph Almog for support, criticism, and many a valuable insight. I also want to thank Arto Repo, Tapio Korte, Sakari Ollitervo and Tuomas Tolonen for comments at various stages, and for many fruitful conversations on Kant and other matters. Along the years I have read and discussed Kant and other related philosophers in both formal seminars and informal reading groups with many people such as Peter Myrdal, Miika Hellevaara, Jaakko Vuori, Pirkko Holmberg and Tommi Hjelt, among others. Thanks, guys. This work has been funded mainly by the Kone Foundation, to whom I am grateful. I would also like to acknowledge having received grants from the University of Turku and the Finnish Cultural Foundation. Most of all I want to thank my extended family. My parents, and my parents- in-law – thank you so much. My relatives and friends who have shown interest and support. There is no doubt, however, that the utmost gratitude should go and does go to my wife and our children. I dedicate this work to Toivo, Eino, Lilja and Roosa. Abstract This study analyzes and lays out different aspects of Kant’s account of the concept of objectivity and objective reference in the broad view, as well as their conditions, to show the relevance of Kant’s view to contemporary philosophy, and to answer some of the criticisms expressed toward Kant, which criticisms often seem to be based on misguided readings of his doctrines. I aim to show that Kant’s philosophy is not – contrary to what is often claimed – overly subjectivistic with the expense of losing objectivity. Rather, his theory of objectivity and objective reference is both coherent and relevant as a philosophical theory today. Furthermore, Kant's account of objectivity, as well as subjectivity, is essential in understanding the origin and meaning of the modern concept of objectivity, which concept is crucial to science in general. In the beginning chapters I outline the most important philosophers and traditions which Kant was both using and criticizing. After this I show how Kant’s transcendental idealism along with its notion of a priori forms of intuition and a priori concepts of the understanding proved to be requirements for objective reference. The key of objective reference lies in the necessary agreement of the categories to the objects of experience. However, these formal conditions are not the only conditions of proper, actual objective reference, as we also need to materialize the forms and concepts by both senses and language, which offer us sensations and words for judgments. Thus I argue that a more full list of the conditions of objective reference in Kant’s case would consist of the purely formal conditions of experience, that is, the forms of intuition and the categories as the concepts of an object in general, and most of all the capacity to unite representations in the act of apperception, and what I have called the material or empirical conditions of objective reference, that is, our actual senses, as well as a language by which we can materialize judgments. This work hopefully contributes first of all to the study of Kant's theoretical philosophy. In addition, the work is related to such fields as philosophy of science and conceptual history, because of the historical role of the concept of objectivity. Furthermore, the study may prove relevant to discussions in philosophy of language, and finally the discussion concerning the interpretation of Kant's philosophy among the contemporary speculative realists. Tiivistelmä Tutkimus analysoi ja esittelee Kantin objektiivisuuden ja objektiivisen referenssin käsitteiden eri aspekteja ja ehtoja, ja pyrkii osoittamaan Kantin näkemyksen merkittävyyden nykyfilosofialle. Samalla tutkimus vastaa joihinkin Kantia vastaan esitettyihin kritiikkeihin, jotka usein perustuvat puutteellisille tai virheellisille tulkinnoille Kantin opeista. Pyrin näyttämään, ettei Kantin filosofiaa ole syytä pitää kaiken objektiivisuuden kadottavan subjektiivisuuden filosofian esikuvana, kuten valitettavan usein tunnutaan olettavan. Sen sijaan Kantin teoria objektiivisuudesta ja objektiivisesta referenssistä on sekä koherentti että merkityksellinen nykyajan filosofian ja tieteen kannalta. Lisäksi Kantin käsitys objektiivisuudesta ja subjektiivisuudesta on olennainen pyrittäessä ymmärtämään nykyaikaista objektiivisuuden käsitettä, joka on keskeinen tieteelle ylipäänsä. Ensimmäisissä luvuissa hahmottelen Kantin filosofista kontekstia suhteessa niihin filosofeihin ja oppeihin joita Kant itse sekä hydynsi että kritisoi. Tämän jälkeen osoitan miten Kantin oppi transsendentaalisesta idealismista, mukaan lukien sen keskeiset käsitteet intuition a priori -muodoista ja ymmärryksen a priori - käsitteista, onnistuu perustelemaan objektiivisen referenssin mahdollisuuden, jonka ydin on ymmärryksen peruskäsitteiden (kategorioiden) ja kokemuksen kohteiden (objektien) välisessä välttämättömässä yhteensopivuudessa. Nämä muodolliset a priori –ehdot eivät kuitenkaan yksinään riitä todelliseen objektiiviseen referenssiin, johon tarvitsemme mys empiirisiä elementtejä, kuten aisteja ja kieltä. Näin ollen väitän, että kattavampi luettelo objektiivisen referenssin edellytyksistä sisältää muodollisten a priori -elementtien (intuition ja ymmärryksen muodot) lisäksi myös materiaalisia, empiriisiä ehtoja, kuten aistit ja näiden tuottamat aistimukset, sekä kielen, jonka avulla arvostelmat on mahdollista materialisoida. Tutkimuksella on toivottavasti annettavaa useammalle kuin yhdelle filosofian tutkimuskentälle, mutta lähtkohtaisesti se kuuluu filosofian historian tutkimukseen ja Kantin teoreettisen filosofian tutkimukseen. Ty sivuaa myös sellaisia filosofian aloja kuin tieteenfilosofia ja käsitehistoria, ennen kaikkea objektiivisuuden käsitteen historiallisen merkittävyyden takia. Lisäksi työllä saattaa olla relevanssia kielifilosofialle sekä lukuisille Kantiin liittyville kiistoille tämänhetkisten spekulatiivisten realistien piirissä. Contents 1 Introduction ....................................................................................................... 11 1.1 Kant and the Problem of Objectivity ................................................................... 11 1.2 Kant and the Concept of Objectivity .................................................................. 14 1.3 General theme, Aims and Questions ................................................................... 16 1.4 The Structure and Content ................................................................................... 21 2 The Humean Problem and Experience ........................................................ 27 2.1 The Humean Problem ...........................................................................................
Recommended publications
  • Against 'Flat Ontologies'
    64 Ray Brassier Deleveling: Against ‘Flat Ontologies’ Ray Brassier is associate professor of philosophy at the American University of Beirut. What I am going to present today is a critical discussion of the 65 tenets of so-called ‘flat ontology’. The expression ‘flat onto- logy’ has a complicated genealogy. It was originally coined as a pejorative term for empiricist philosophies of science by Roy Bhaskar in his 1975 book, A Realist Theory of Science. By the late 1990s, it had begun to acquire a positive sense in discus- sions of the work of Deleuze and Guattari. But it only achieved widespread currency in the wake of Manual De Landa’s 2002 book about Deleuze, Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy. More recently, it has been championed by proponents of ‘ob- ject-oriented ontology’ and ‘new materialism’. It is its use by these theorists that I will be discussing today. I will begin by explaining the ‘four theses’ of flat onto- logy, as formulated by Levi Bryant. Bryant is a proponent of ‘object-oriented ontology’, a school of thought founded by Graham Harman. In his 2010 work The Democracy of Objects, Bryant encapsulates flat ontology in the following four theses: Thesis 1: “First, due to the split characteristic of all ob- jects, flat ontology rejects any ontology of transcendence or presence that privileges one sort of entity as the origin of all others and as fully present to itself.” Thesis 2: “Second, […] the world or the universe does not exist. […] [T]here is no super-object that gathers all other ob- jects together in a single, harmonious
    [Show full text]
  • Certificate for Approving the Dissertation
    MIAMI UNIVERSITY The Graduate School Certificate for Approving the Dissertation We hereby approve the Dissertation of Kevin J. Rutherford Candidate for the Degree: Doctor of Philosophy Director (Jason Palmeri) Reader (Michele Simmons) Reader (Heidi McKee) Reader (Kate Ronald) Graduate School Representative (Bo Brinkman) ABSTRACT PACK YOUR THINGS AND GO: BRINGING OBJECTS TO THE FORE IN RHETORIC AND COMPOSITION by Kevin J. Rutherford This dissertation project focuses on object-oriented rhetoric (OOR), a perspective that questions the traditional notions of rhetorical action as solely a human province. The project makes three major, interrelated claims: that OOR provides a unique and productive methodology to examine the inclusion of the non-human in rhetorical study; that to some extent, rhetoric has always been interested in the way nonhuman objects interact with humans; and that these claims have profound implications for our activities as teachers and scholars. Chapter one situates OOR within current scholarship in composition and rhetoric, arguing that it can serve as a useful methodology for the field despite rhetoric’s traditional focus on epistemology and human symbolic action. Chapter two examines rhetorical history to demonstrate that a view of rhetoric that includes nonhuman actors is not new, but has often been marginalized. Chapter three examines two videogames as sites of theory and practice for object-oriented rhetoric, specifically focusing on a sense of metaphor to understand the experience of nonhuman rhetors. Chapter four interrogates the network surrounding a review aggregation website to argue that, while some nonhumans may be unhelpful rhetorical collaborators, OOR can assist us in improving relationships with them.
    [Show full text]
  • 147 Levi R. Bryant. Onto-Cartography: an Ontology Of
    Philosophy in Review XXXVI (August 2016), no. 4 Levi R. Bryant. Onto-Cartography: An Ontology of Machines and Media. Edinburgh University Press 2014. 312 pp. $130.00 USD (Hardcover ISBN 9780748679966); $39.95 USD (Paperback ISBN 9780748679973). Levi Bryant characterizes himself as a fervent convert who has recently ‘awoken from [the] dogmatic slumbers’ of historical materialism to produce an anti-humanist political philosophy that dispenses with the ‘discursivism’ and anthropocentrism that has dominated Western philosophy for far too long (4). He has sought to displace the prevailing assumptions of cultural studies and critical theory by crafting a materialist metaphysics that decentralizes humanity and proposes a practice—onto- cartography—that demonstrates how the natural environment shapes our social relations. This new ontological framework, he argues, will allow us to develop more effective strategies for the estab- lishment of justice. The practice of onto-cartography presupposes what Bryant calls a machine-oriented ontol- ogy. Bryant proposes that ‘all beings’, ‘all entities, things, or objects are machines’ (18, 23). According to this model, being consists entirely of machines ‘at a variety of different levels of scale’, from galaxies and social institutions to subatomic particles (6). He broadly defines a machine as any system of operations that takes on inputs and transforms them to produce outputs. So, for example, a tree is a machine that absorbs sunlight and carbon dioxide and, through the process of photosyn- thesis, operates on those inputs to produce oxygen, its output. Moreover, all machines are enmeshed in a fabric of assemblages or a network of machines. An assemblage is a system of relations between ‘coupled’ machines in which particular machinic nodes shape the functioning and development of other machines within the field of relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Degruyter Opphil Opphil-2020-0105 314..334 ++
    Open Philosophy 2020; 3: 314–334 Object-Oriented Ontology and Its Critics Graham Harman* The Battle of Objects and Subjects: Concerning Sbriglia and Žižek’s Subject Lessons Anthology https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2020-0105 received April 8, 2020; accepted June 16, 2020 Abstract: This article mounts a defense of Object-Oriented Ontology (OOO) from various criticisms made in Russell Sbriglia and Slavoj Žižek’sco-edited anthology Subject Lessons. Along with Sbriglia and Žižek’s own Introduction to the volume, the article responds to the chapters by Todd McGowan, Adrian Johnston, and Molly Anne Rothenberg, the three in which my own version of OOO is most frequently discussed. Keywords: Ljubljana School, Object-Oriented Ontology, Slavoj Žižek, G. W. F. Hegel, Jacques Lacan, thing- in-itself, materialism, realism Russell Sbriglia and Slavoj Žižek’sco-edited collection Subject Lessons: Hegel, Lacan, and the Future of Materialism has long been awaited in circles devoted to Object-Oriented Ontology (OOO).¹ All twelve chapters in the anthology (eleven plus the editors’ Introduction) are written from the merciless Lacano- Hegelian standpoint that defines the Ljubljana School, one of the most fruitful trends in the continental philosophy of recent decades.² The Slovenian core of the group is here – Žižek, Mladen Dolar, and Alenka Zupančič – as are many of their most capable international allies (though Joan Copjec is keenly missed), along with some impressive younger voices. As a rule, the book is most impressive when making a positive case for what G. W. F. Hegel and Jacques Lacan still have to offer contemporary philosophy; all of the chapters are clearly written, and some are among the most lucid statements I have seen from the Ljubljana group.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem: the Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2013 The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze Ryan J. Johnson Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Johnson, R. (2013). The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/706 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College & Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Copyright by Ryan J. Johnson 2014 ii THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson Approved December 6, 2013 _______________________________ ______________________________ Daniel Selcer, Ph.D Kelly Arenson, Ph.D Associate Professor of Philosophy Assistant Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ______________________________ John Protevi, Ph.D Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ______________________________ ______________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Ronald Polansky, Ph.D. Dean, McAnulty College & Graduate Chair, Department of Philosophy School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Queer: Towards a Non-Standard Queer Theory1 Michael O’Rourke Independent Colleges, Dublin
    IDENTITIES journal for politics, gender and culture Quantum Queer: Towards a Non-Standard Queer Theory1 Michael O’Rourke Independent Colleges, Dublin Abstract: This essay looks at some potentially fruitful lines of correspondence between Laruelle’s non-philosophy and gender, feminist and queer theories. Drawing on the work of leading Laruelle scholars I seek to outline some highly tentative principles for a non-standard queer theory which would help us to think about democracy, the human, performativity, sexual difference and some other crucial questions for current queer theorizing. Keywords: Laruelle, queer theory, non-philosophy, flat ontology, the human, sexual difference, the stranger. Black Box The French non-philosopher François Laruelle writes that: Like an artisan, engineer, or designer, I am going to attempt to construct in front of you a so- called apparatus of photo-fiction … [I]t is an exercise in the construction of a theoretical object, and is thus transparent, but which will function more like a black box.2 This paper is my latest attempt to bring Laruelle’s non-philosophy and queer theory into productive conversation with each other.3 I am going to attempt to construct in front of you a so-called apparatus of queer-fiction, a theoretical object which will not seek to render either queer theory or non-philosophy transparent, but rather to allow them to function more like black boxes. With that disclaimer in place, it must be said that the aim of the present article will be to demonstrate that Laruelle’s non-philosophy has much to offer to queer theory, feminist thought and gender studies.
    [Show full text]
  • The Speculative Turn Continental Materialism and Realism
    The Speculative Turn Continental Materialism and Realism Edited by Levi Bryant, Nick Srnicek and Graham Harman Open Access Statement – Please Read This book is Open Access. This work is not simply an electronic book; it is the open access version of a work that exists in a number of forms, the traditional printed form being one of them. Copyright Notice This work is ‘Open Access’, published under a creative commons license which means that you are free to copy, distribute, display, and perform the work as long as you clearly attribute the work to the authors, that you do not use this work for any commercial gain in any form and that you in no way alter, transform or build on the work outside of its use in normal aca- demic scholarship without express permission of the author and the publisher of this volume. Furthermore, for any reuse or distribution, you must make clear to others the license terms of this work. For more information see the details of the creative commons licence at this website: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/2.5/ This means that you can: • read and store this document free of charge • distribute it for personal use free of charge • print sections of the work for personal use • read or perform parts of the work in a context where no financial transactions take place However, you cannot: • gain financially from the work in anyway • sell the work or seek monies in relation to the distribution of the work • use the work in any commercial activity of any kind • profit a third party indirectly via use or distribution
    [Show full text]
  • An Interview with Levi Bryant
    Anarchist Developments in Cultural Studies ISSN: 1923-5615 2013.2: Ontological Anarché: Beyond Materialism and Idealism An Interview with Levi Bryant Christos Stergiou CS: How would you describe the differences between your ontol- ogy and other object-oriented ontologies? LB: As we use the term, object-oriented ontology (OOO) refers to any ontological position that affirms the mind-independent exist- ence of substances, entities, or objects. In this regard, ontologies as diverse as Aristotle’s, Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz’s, Alfred North Whitehead’s, Jane Bennett’s, Bruno Latour’s, etc., are ob- ject-oriented ontologies. Among these ontologies, of course, you have differences and disagreements. Whitehead, for example, holds that actual occasions (his name for substance) are constituted by their relations to other actual occasions and eternal objects. Addition- ally, he argues that actual occasions are processes. Graham Har- man’s object-oriented philosophy (OOP), by contrast, argues that objects are withdrawn from their relations and possess abiding essences. There is thus a debate here in object-oriented ontology as to what a substance is. In the past I referred to my ontology as “onticology,” while these days I refer to it as machine-oriented ontology (MOO). I argue that every entity or substance is a machine. Machines are defined by their operations or powers (capacities). Following Ian Bogost, I define an operation as an activity that takes one or more inputs and performs a transformation on it, producing an output. For example, in photosynthesis a tree takes sunlight, water, and carbon dioxide, performs operations on these materials, and pro- duces outputs in the form of cells, energy, oxygen, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Questions for Levi Bryant, Author of Onto-Cartography
    Onto- Cartography – Author Q&A Page | 1 Onto-Cartography An Ontology of Machines and Media By Levi Bryant Part of the Speculative Realism series Author Q&A with Levi Bryant Asked by Graham Harman, Speculative Realism series editor Graham – Let’s start with your title, Onto-Cartography. You have always been remarkable among continental philosophy authors for the vast range of disciplines in which you read. To what extent does onto-cartography imply a turn to geography? Are you using the term in a geographical sense, or in some other sense? Levi – While I think geography is of the utmost importance in the social sciences – in the book I describe it as the queen of the social sciences – Onto-Cartography isn’t a philosophy of geography. ‘Cartography’ signifies ‘map’. There are a variety of different types of maps, some geographical, others not. For example, Marx gives us a map of how capitalism functions and is structured, while Foucault gives us maps of how knowledge is structured in particular time periods in works like The Order of Things. The discipline of anatomy can be thought as a map of how bodies are configured. By contrast, the term ‘onto’, from the Greek, refers to ‘things’ or what I call ‘machines’. In Onto-Cartography I’m interested in developing a technique for mapping relations between expressive or semiotic machines and corporeal or material machines so as to investigate the gravity or power they exercise over us so that we might devise strategies for escaping oppressive worlds. I’d like to know how we might achieve escape velocity from these assemblages of words and things.
    [Show full text]
  • ONTO-CARTOGRAPHY, OR ONTO-NOSTALGIA Notes on Levi Bryant's ONTO-CARTOGRAPHY by Terence Blake
    ONTO-CARTOGRAPHY, OR ONTO-NOSTALGIA notes on Levi Bryant's ONTO-CARTOGRAPHY by Terence Blake 1) POST-MONIST THOUGHT vs "HARD AND CONVINCING " REALISM During the post-structuralist period (Deleuze, Lyotard, Serres, but also Feyerabend and Rorty) it was widely thought that monism had been thoroughly refuted and discredited. However, recent developments in the last decade have shown that the refutations were insufficient, as the discredit of monism began to fade and a new form of monist ontology, in both scientistic and nonscientistic variants, came to light and began to spread. Post-structuralism was seen as insufficient to prevent the rise of these new forms of monism, loosely grouped together under the rubric of "speculative realism". The post-structuralists' positive valuation of "speculation" as conceptual investigation and experimentation was considered by some to be in danger of founding a new idealism, called by some "constructivism" and by others "correlationism", enshrining the omnipotence of language, society, or individual and/or collective thought to the detriment of empirical reality. Certain thinkers saw themselves as invested with the mission of reinstating "realism" and subordinating the free play of metaphysical speculation to the hard and convincing real state of affairs. "Hard and convincing" realism represents a return to a grasp on reality by turning post- structuralist critique against itself. A key figure in this monist regression was Alain Badiou, who tried to synthesize both pluralism and monism under the aegis of an ontological realism allied to an adulterated scientism. The conceptual situation became pathological under Badiousian regenting, and it was only a matter of time before a strange new malady appeared, or an old malady in mutated form.
    [Show full text]
  • BETWEEN GRAHAM HARMAN and the DELEUZO-WHITEHEADIAN AXIS Adrian Ivakhiv
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 19 • 2014 • 65-78 BEATNIK BROTHERS? BETWEEN GRAHAM HARMAN AND THE DELEUZO-WHITEHEADIAN AXIS Adrian Ivakhiv INTRODUCTION Recent years have seen a surge of interest among Deleuzian and post-Deleuzian theorists in the metaphysical writings of Alfred North Whitehead. To many, there is a natural affinity between Deleuze and Whitehead, one that is continuous with a line of other thinkers—from Spinoza and Bruno to Bergson, Peirce, James, Simondon, Tarde, Serres, Stengers, and Latour—who are unified by an interest in process, affectivity, and a dynamic and relational ontology.1 Responding to this interest, Graham Harman has argued that these thinkers are falsely allied in a “beatnik brotherhood” of “process philosophers” or “philosophers of immanence.”2 At heart, he counters, their philosophies are radically different. This article examines what is at stake in this debate between Harman and the Deleuzo-Whiteheadians. Ex- amining a series of recent writings by Harman, I will show that Harman overdraws the differences between Whitehead and Deleuze in order to privilege the radical distinction between objects and relations that is at the heart of his own object-oriented ontology (OOO). I will examine some affinities and differences between Har- man’s account of objects and Whitehead’s account of actual occasions, and suggest that the two are not as far apart as Harman makes them appear. The key difference between them, and therefore the central stake in the debate between object-oriented and process-relational ontologies, concerns their respective understandings of temporality. In comparing Harman’s object-oriented ontology with the process-relational metaphysics of Whitehead (and, by extension, Deleuze), this article intends to contribute to a debate that has transpired in what has been called the “speculative realist blogosphere” since at least 2009.
    [Show full text]
  • Object Oriented Ontology, Art and Art-Writing
    After The Passions: Object Oriented Ontology, Art and Art-writing PRUE GIBSON DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF NEW SOUTH WALES 2014 Originality Statement I hereby declare that this submission is my own work and to the best of my knowledge it contains no materials previously published or written by another person, or substantial proportions of material which have been accepted for the award of any other degree or diploma at UNSW or any other educational institution, except where due acknowledgement is made in the thesis. Any contribution made to the research by others, with whom I have worked at UNSW or elsewhere, is explicitly acknowledged in the thesis. I also declare that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work, except to the extent that assistance from others in the project’s design and conception or in style, presentation and linguistic expression is acknowledged. Signed: Dated: i Acknowledgements My supervisor Professor Stephen Muecke welcomed me into academic life and has supported me ever since. He introduced me to Speculative Realism and Object Oriented Ontology and slowed my usual cracking pace to a more considered and cautious speed. Each time I felt I had discovered something new about writing, I realised Stephen had led me there. I have often tried to emulate his mentoring method for my own students: without judgement, enthusiastic and twinkle-eyed. Through the second half of the thesis process, my co-supervisor Professor Edward Scheer jumped in and demanded evidence, structured argument and accountability. This was the perfect timing for a rigorous edit.
    [Show full text]