Voting Squared: Quadratic Voting in Democratic Politics Eric A

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Voting Squared: Quadratic Voting in Democratic Politics Eric A University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Coase-Sandor Working Paper Series in Law and Coase-Sandor Institute for Law and Economics Economics 2014 Voting Squared: Quadratic Voting in Democratic Politics Eric A. Posner E. Glen Weyl Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/law_and_economics Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Eric Posner & E. Glen Weyl, "Voting Squared: Quadratic Voting in Democratic Politics" (Coase-Sandor Institute for Law & Economics Working Paper No. 657, 2014). This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Coase-Sandor Institute for Law and Economics at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Coase-Sandor Working Paper Series in Law and Economics by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CHICAGO COASE-SANDOR INSTITUTE FOR LAW AND ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER NO. 657 (2D SERIES) Voting Squared: Quadratic Voting in Democratic Politics Eric A. Posner and E. Glen Weyl THE LAW SCHOOL THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO February 2014 This paper can be downloaded without charge at: The University of Chicago, Institute for Law and Economics Working Paper Series Index: http://www.law.uchicago.edu/Lawecon/index.html and at the Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection. Voting Squared: Quadratic Voting in Democratic Politics Eric A. Posner & E. Glen Weyl1 February 14, 2014 Abstract. Conventional democratic institutions aggregate preferences poorly. The norm of one-person-one-vote with majority rule treats people fairly by giving everyone an equal chance to influence outcomes, but fails to give proportional weight to people whose interests in a social outcome are stronger than those of other people—a problem that leads to the familiar phenomenon of tyranny of the majority. Various institutions that have been tried or proposed over the years to correct this problem— including supermajority rule, weighted voting, cumulative voting, “mixed constitutions,” executive discretion, and judicially protected rights—all badly misfire in various ways, for example, by creating gridlock or corruption. This paper proposes a new form of political decision-making based on the theory of quadratic voting. It explains how quadratic voting solves the preference aggregation problem by giving proper weight to preferences of varying intensity, how it can be incorporated into political institutions, and why it should improve equity. Introduction Groups frequently make collective decisions through majority rule. Legislators pass bills by majority; shareholders make most corporate decisions by (share-weighted) majority rule, as do directors; clubs, university faculties, and civic associations typically use majority rule as well. The reason that they do so is not entirely clear. Majority rule seems fair—and certainly fairer than rule by one (dictatorship) or a minority—but it is not obviously fairer than rule by unanimity or consensus, or rule by a supermajority like two-thirds. Majority rule has some useful properties but it often fails to advance the good of the group. 1 Kirkland & Ellis Distinguished Service Professor, University of Chicago Law School; Assistant Professor of Economics, University of Chicago. Thanks to Fabrizio Cariani, Ben Laurence, Daryl Levinson, Jonathan Masur, Philip Pettit, Sparsha Saha, Adrian Vermeule, and participants at workshops at the University of Chicago Law School and St. John’s Law School, for helpful comments, and to Matthew Brincks, Siobhan Fabio, John Moynihan, Michael Olijnyk, Tim Rudnicki, and Robert Sandoval for research assistance. The basic problem with majority rule is well-known: majorities can disregard the legitimate interests of minorities. Imagine, for example, that a community is trying to decide whether to devote funds collected from taxes to build a park. A large minority, including elderly people and families with young children, would benefit greatly from a park; a bare majority doesn’t have strong views but on balance doesn’t want to spend the money. The majority can block the park even if the minority gains more from the park than the majority loses: there is no mechanism for ensuring that the majority takes into account the minority’s disproportionate interests. For example, if the minority consists of 10,000 people who value the park at $100 each, and the majority consists of 11,000 people who disvalue the park at $2 each, the majority prevails even though the park generates a net social product of $978,000. More troublesome examples are easy to imagine and occur throughout history. In politics, majority rule— unrestricted by constitutional protections—permits the majority to expropriate the property of the minority, throw them in jail, and deprive them of the franchise. Even when the majority respects basic rights, it may deprive minorities of benefits and privileges that are available to others. The most prominent example from recent years, which we discuss in some numerical detail below, is the claim that the majority of Americans in various states unfairly deny the legal benefits of marriage to same-sex couples. The possibility that the majority may disregard the interests of the minority has a well-known label: it is “tyranny of the majority.”2 But what is wrong with tyranny of the majority? One could argue that tyranny of the majority is just a negative label for “democracy,” a label wielded by special interests, privileged groups, and others who fear majority rule. If all citizens are equal, what could be fairer than allowing the majority of them to determine policy, either directly or through representatives?3 2 The concept of tyranny of the majority is as old as majority rule, as will be discussed; early users of the phrase include John Adams, Alexis de Tocqueville, who popularized it, and John Stuart Mill, among others. John Adams, A Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States of America, Vol. 3, reprinted in The Works of John Adams 6 (Charles Francis Adams ed. 1851) (1788); Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America (Arthur Goldhammer trans., Penguin Putnam 2004) (1835); John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (David Bromwich & George Kateb eds., Yale University Press 2003) (1859). Many formulations of it exist, of course, e.g.: Thomas Paine, Dissertations on Government; the Affairs of the Bank; and Paper Money (1786) (“despotism may be more effectually acted by many over a few than by one man over all”). 3 A number of theorems illustrate the attractive features of majority rule but show that it achieves good social outcomes only under narrow conditions. See, e.g., Howard R. Bowen, The Interpretation of Voting in the Allocation of Economic Resources, 27 Q. J. Econ. 58 (1943); Kenneth O. May, A Set of Independent Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Simple Majority Decisions, 20 Econometrica 680 (1952); Douglas W. Rae, Decision-Rules and Individual Values in Constitutional Choice, 63 Amer. Pol. Sci. Rev. 40 (1969); Michael J. Taylor, Proof of a 2 But there are good reasons to be worried about tyranny of the majority. The first reason is that, as noted, majority rule, unless constrained to prevent tyranny of the majority, will not necessarily advance the public good. Majority rule can lead to the systematic transfer of wealth or resources from a minority to the majority. From the standpoint of the public interest, such systematic transfers are sometimes justified (for example, transfers from rich to poor), but they need not be, and nothing about majority rule guarantees that such transfers will promote public well-being. The transfers may go from one morally arbitrary group to another—for example, election winners to election losers, or poorer people to wealthier people, or black people to white people. Often these transfers incur substantial waste both administratively and in separating goods from the owners that most value them.4 Moreover, because the harm from being trapped in a minority is so great, people will struggle to form coalitions that constitute a majority—a high-stakes game that consumes time and resources that could be more productively spent elsewhere. There are actually two distinct problems here that are often merged together. In the United States, tyranny of the majority usually refers to the systematic and repeated use of the political process by a relatively stable majority (such as white people) to pass legislation that benefits it at the expense of a “discrete and insular” minority (such as black people).5 It is sometimes thought that majority rule is less troublesome when groups “take turns” playing a role in the majority. For example, if whites and Latinos outvote African-Americans on a bill proposed this year, but then African-Americans have a chance to form a coalition with Latinos to outvote whites next year, and so on, one might believe that “tyranny of the majority” does not take place. But whatever label one uses, majority rule is still not optimal. The reason is that if the white-Latino coalition inefficiently expropriates from African-Americans in year 1 by using inefficient legislation that reduces public welfare, and the black-Latino coalition does the Theorem on Majority Rule, 14 Beh. Sci. 228 (1969); Ted C. Bergstrom, When Does Majority Rule Supply Public Goods Efficiently?, 81 Scand. J. of Econ. 216 (1979). The large literature on voting rules is surveyed in Dennis C. Mueller, Public Choice III (2003); Kenneth A. Shepsle, Analyzing Politics (2d. ed. 2010); and other volumes. Lurking in the background is Arrow’s theorem, which proves that under relatively broad conditions, no voting system can produce outcomes that are both Pareto-efficient and non-dictatorial. Arrow’s theorem assumes ordinal preferences; the quadratic voting system we discuss below does not. 4 There are countless historical examples of the violent transfer of resources from a minority group to the majority; the expropriation of assets of Jewish citizens by the Nazi government in Germany is the canonical example, See Constance Harris, The Way Jews Lived: Five Hundred Years of Printed Words and Images 328 (2009).
Recommended publications
  • Unpopular Policies and the Theory of Representative Democracy Pierre Salmon
    Unpopular policies and the theory of representative democracy Pierre Salmon To cite this version: Pierre Salmon. Unpopular policies and the theory of representative democracy. [Research Report] Laboratoire d’analyse et de techniques économiques(LATEC). 1991, 25 p., ref. bib. : 2 p. hal- 01526994 HAL Id: hal-01526994 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01526994 Submitted on 23 May 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. LABORATOIRE D'ANALYSE ET DE TECHNIQUES ÉCONOMIQUES UMR 5601 CNRS DOCUMENT DE TRAVAIL �I CENTRE NATIONAL DE LA RECHERCHE I SCIENTIFIQUE '1 UNIVERSITE DE BOURGOGNE Pôle d'Economie et de Gestion 2, boulevard Gabriel - 21000 DIJON - Tél. 03 80 3954 30 - Fax 03 80 39 54 43 ISSN : 1260-8556 9102 UNPOPULAR POLICIES AND THE THEORY OF REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY Pierre SALMON* May 1991 Université de Bourgogne * I am grateful to the participants of the Fourth Villa Colombella Seminar, especially Ron Wintrobe, to Alain Wolfelsperger and to an anonymous referee for their helpful comments. The errors and shortcomings that remain are solely my responsability. INTRODUCTION: IS MOB RULE OUR IDEAL OF REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY? Their platforms reflect concern with enhancing the probability of being elected, but some candidates often, or all candidates occasionally, voluntarily adept stances that reduce that probability.
    [Show full text]
  • Preventing Mob Rule
    In a democracy, the people rule. This means that if a majority of HANDOUT: the public demands a law or public policy, elected leaders have an obligation to seriously consider that demand. However, sometimes the majority demands a law or public policy Preventing that could trample the rights of minorities. The phenomena of the majority wanting to trample the rights of a minority is also known as Mob Rule: ochlocracy, or mob rule. Passing a Law To keep ochlocracy at bay, liberal democracies spread power amongst several institutions. The separate powers of the Senate, the House of Commons, and even the Queen illustrate how the power to create and enact laws is spread amongst different institutions in Canada. Each institution can act as a check on the power of the others. By having power spread across institutions, the law-creation process can be more reasoned and less mob-like. There are more opportunities to consider positions, consult experts, and ask questions. This helps temper emotions, protect minority rights, and promote reason when creating laws. The Path to Creating a Law In Canada, the federal government cannot simply declare a law, without a debate and without that law being subjected to reviews and consideration. The rule of law requires that there are open and established processes to guide the creation of laws. The process below outlines the steps to creating most federal laws in Canada. The process for creating laws at the provincial level is similar, except that there is no Senate review of provincial laws. Three Readings When a proposed law—also known as a bill—is first introduced in the House of Commons, it must pass a series of three votes.
    [Show full text]
  • Spooked by the Demos: Aristotle's Conception of the Good Citizenry
    Problematique Issue 11 (Spring) 2007 Bell: Spooked by the Demos Spooked by the Demos: Aristotle’s Conception of the Good Citizenry Against the Mob Colleen Bell This article addresses two aspects of Aristotle’s The Politics.1 The first concerns his conception of the good citizenry and the second concerns the character that he attributes to a politically active demos. At times, Aristotle refers to this latter category as the ‘mob’ which serves as the citizenry’s disruptive counterpart.2 I explore how the ideas of rationality, virtue and excellence are used to characterize the good citizenry, while the mob, driven by passion, moral depravity and irrationality, is represented as its alterity. The relationship between the good citizenry and the mob, I argue, is critical to the image that Aristotle casts of the best possible constitution; one designed to be largely invulnerable to revolution and to the formation of an active, democratic polity. His awareness of the potential for the demos to transform into a form of ‘mob rule’ leads him to compromise the ideal constitution, composed of a wholly ‘rational’ and ‘virtuous’ citizenry, by extending citizenship rights to a limited and select portion of the demos in order to minimize the likelihood of mob driven revolution. Aristotle provides the classical account of the citizen as one who has both the knowledge, and the ability to rule and be ruled. 3 Key is the idea that while ‘man’ is distinguished by reason, not all ‘men’ posses sufficient reason to warrant citizenship. 4 In holding that not all of humanity has the capacity to rule, essential to his conception of the good citizen is the willful exclusion of women, slaves, immigrants, and children from both political subjectivity and participation.
    [Show full text]
  • Governance in Decentralized Networks
    Governance in decentralized networks Risto Karjalainen* May 21, 2020 Abstract. Effective, legitimate and transparent governance is paramount for the long-term viability of decentralized networks. If the aim is to design such a governance model, it is useful to be aware of the history of decision making paradigms and the relevant previous research. Towards such ends, this paper is a survey of different governance models, the thinking behind such models, and new tools and structures which are made possible by decentralized blockchain technology. Governance mechanisms in the wider civil society are reviewed, including structures and processes in private and non-profit governance, open-source development, and self-managed organisations. The alternative ways to aggregate preferences, resolve conflicts, and manage resources in the decentralized space are explored, including the possibility of encoding governance rules as automatically executed computer programs where humans or other entities interact via a protocol. Keywords: Blockchain technology, decentralization, decentralized autonomous organizations, distributed ledger technology, governance, peer-to-peer networks, smart contracts. 1. Introduction This paper is a survey of governance models in decentralized networks, and specifically in networks which make use of blockchain technology. There are good reasons why governance in decentralized networks is a topic of considerable interest at present. Some of these reasons are ideological. We live in an era where detailed information about private individuals is being collected and traded, in many cases without the knowledge or consent of the individuals involved. Decentralized technology is seen as a tool which can help protect people against invasions of privacy. Decentralization can also be viewed as a reaction against the overreach by state and industry.
    [Show full text]
  • A Measure of Detachment: Richard Hofstadter and the Progressive Historians
    A MEASURE OF DETACHMENT: RICHARD HOFSTADTER AND THE PROGRESSIVE HISTORIANS A Thesis Submitted to the Temple University Graduate Board In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree MASTER OF ARTS By Wiliiam McGeehan May 2018 Thesis Approvals: Harvey Neptune, Department of History Andrew Isenberg, Department of History ABSTRACT This thesis argues that Richard Hofstadter's innovations in historical method arose as a critical response to the Progressive historians, particularly to Charles Beard. Hofstadter's first two books were demonstrations of the inadequacy of Progressive methodology, while his third book (the Age of Reform) showed the potential of his new way of writing history. i TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ABSTRACT.......................................................................................................................i CHAPTER 1. A MEASURE OF DETACHMENT..........................................................................1 2. SOCIAL DARWINISM IN AMERICAN THOUGHT………………………………………………26 3. THE AMERICAN POLITICAL TRADITION…………………………………………………………..52 4. THE AGE OF REFORM…………………………………………………………………………………….100 5. CONCLUSION…………………………………………………………………………………………………139 BIBLIOGRAPHY…………………………………………………………………………………………………………..144 CHAPTER ONE A MEASURE OF DETACHMENT Great thinkers often spend their early years in rebellion against the teachers from whom they have learned the most. Freud would say they live out a form of the Oedipal archetype, that son must murder his father at least a little bit if he is ever to become his own man.
    [Show full text]
  • Preventing Mob Rule
    There are many ways that ochlocracy, or the rule of the mob, is HANDOUT: curtailed in Canada. Requiring that legislation be approved by the House of Commons, the Senate, and even the Queen is one of the protections we have against mob rule. The review of proposed legislation by specialised committees of both the House of Commons Preventing and the Senate is another way that we try to ensure that our laws Mob Rule: The respect reason and uphold minority rights. Yet another way that Canada’s liberal democracy is designed to Courts and uphold the values of reason and protect minority rights is our constitution. The Constitution Act and the Charter of Rights and the Charter Freedoms are the highest laws in the country. They spell out what the government has the authority to do, and codify the rights and of Rights and freedoms of all Canadians. When questions arise as to whether or not the government is Freedoms respecting the constitution or the Charter, the courts may be asked to decide. Courts are independent of government. They have the power to rule on whether or not legislation respects the constitution and the Charter. If a court determines that some aspect of a law is contrary to the constitution or the Charter, the non-conforming parts of the law will be of no force or effect. Tyranny of the Judiciary? The power of the courts to rule on whether or not laws are constitutionally valid has led some people to suggest that there is a “tyranny” of the judiciary.
    [Show full text]
  • We Have a Representative Constitutional Republic and NOT a Democracy for a Reason
    To whom it may concern- We have a representative constitutional republic and NOT a democracy for a reason. A democracy is a popularity contest, it's mob rule, it's 51% of the population bossing around the other 49%. The founding fathers gave us a representative constitutional republic because they believed some rights were intrinsic to the person and could not be removed, no matter how many people agreed to take them away. The right to keep and bear arms as valued second only to the right to free speech and freedom of religion. Senate Bill 978 and it's amendment will largely destroy our right to keep and bear arms in this state. In addition, and much more seriously, the way SB978 is being forced upon the people of Oregon is a circus, an absolute farce. An embarrassment. A perversion of the power given to elected officials. Spitting upon the Constitution, both of the USA as a whole and of Oregon. Every government employee or political office holder who swore an oath to uphold the Constitution of both the USA and of Oregon should be ashamed to be a part of this process. The way SB978 and it's amendment were introduced and modified was done specifically to avoid public knowledge and interference. A law that requires secrecy and subversion to pass doesn't deserve to see the light of day. This is not the way a government by the people, of the people, and for the people works, this is how a totalitarian dictatorship works. The elected representatives of Oregon have lost their way, and I am looking forward to the voting box showing them the door.
    [Show full text]
  • Democracy's Untold Story: What World History Textbooks Neglect. INSTITUTION American Federation of Teachers, Washington, D.C.; Columbia Univ., New York, N.Y
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 313 268 SO 018 637 AUTHOR Gagnon, Paul TITLE Democracy's Untold Story: What World History Textbooks Neglect. INSTITUTION American Federation of Teachers, Washington, D.C.; Columbia Univ., New York, N.Y. Teachers College.; Freedom House, Inc., New York, N.Y. SPONS AGENCY California State Dept. of Education, Sacramento. Bureau of Adult Education.; Department of Education, Washington, DC. PUB DATE 87 NOTE 133p.; For related documents, see SO 019 821, SO 020 352, and EJ 357 591. Prepared in conjunction with the Education for Democracy Project. AVAILABLE FROMEducation for Democracy Project, American Federation of Teachers, 555 New Jersey Ave., NW, Washington, DC 20001 ($4.98). PUB TYPE Books (010) Viewpoints (120) EDRS PRICE MF01/PC06 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS Content Analysis; *Democracy; *Democratic Values; High Schools; Instructional Materials; Social Studies; *Textbook Content; Textbook Evaluation; *World History ABSTRACT Content weakness in textbooks is a major obstacle to effective social studies teaching. Chapters 1-3 of this book provide the Education for Democracy Project's Statement of Principles, a consideration of history's role as the core of social studies education, and the role of textbooks in teaching world history. Chapters 4-14 examine five selected world history textbooks in terms of included information about and treatment of:(1) the purpose of history instruction;(2) the Greek legacy; (3) Rome's fall and legacy;(4) Judaism's and Christianity's basic ideas; (5) the Middle Ages as a source of representative government; (6) the 17th century English Parliament;(7) ideas from the Enlightenment; (8) the American and French Revolutions; (9) major ideas of the 19th century; (10) nation-states, nationalism, and imperialism; (11) World War I; (12) totalitarianism; (13) U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Positionality-Weighted Aggregation Methods for Cumulative Voting
    International Journal of Social Science Studies Vol. 9, No. 2; March 2021 ISSN 2324-8033 E-ISSN 2324-8041 Published by Redfame Publishing URL: http://ijsss.redfame.com Positionality-Weighted Aggregation Methods for Cumulative Voting Takeshi Kato1, Yasuhiro Asa1 & Misa Owa1 1 Hitachi Kyoto University Laboratory, Open Innovation Institute, Kyoto University, Kyoto, Japan Correspondence: Takeshi Kato, Hitachi Kyoto University Laboratory, Open Innovation Institute, Kyoto University, Kyoto 606-8501, Japan. Received: January 7, 2021 Accepted: February 15, 2021 Available online: February 23, 2021 doi:10.11114/ijsss.v9i2.5171 URL: https://doi.org/10.11114/ijsss.v9i2.5171 Abstract Respecting minority opinions is vital in solving social problems. However, minority opinions are often ignored in general majority rules. To build consensus on pluralistic values and make social choices that consider minority opinions, we propose aggregation methods that give weighting to the minority's positionality on cardinal cumulative voting. Based on quadratic and linear voting, we formulated three weighted aggregation methods that differ in the ratio of votes to cumulative points and the weighting of the minority to all members, and assuming that the distributions of votes follow normal distributions, we calculated the frequency distributions of the aggregation results. We found that minority opinions are more likely to be reflected proportionately to the average of the distribution in two of the above three methods. This implies that Sen and Gotoh's idea of considering the social position of unfortunate people on ordinal ranking in the welfare economics, was illustrated by weighting the minority's positionality on cardinal voting. In addition, it is possible to visualize the number and positionality of the minority from the analysis of the aggregation results.
    [Show full text]
  • A Transatlantic Perspective on Blockchain Voting Systems
    Stanford – Vienna Transatlantic Technology Law Forum A joint initiative of Stanford Law School and the University of Vienna School of Law TTLF Working Papers No. 49 The Limits of Blockchain Democracy: A Transatlantic Perspective on Blockchain Voting Systems Yoan Hermstrüwer 2020 TTLF Working Papers Editors: Siegfried Fina, Mark Lemley, and Roland Vogl About the TTLF Working Papers TTLF’s Working Paper Series presents original research on technology-related and business-related law and policy issues of the European Union and the US. The objective of TTLF’s Working Paper Series is to share “work in progress”. The authors of the papers are solely responsible for the content of their contributions and may use the citation standards of their home country. The TTLF Working Papers can be found at http://ttlf.stanford.edu. Please also visit this website to learn more about TTLF’s mission and activities. If you should have any questions regarding the TTLF’s Working Paper Series, please contact Vienna Law Professor Siegfried Fina, Stanford Law Professor Mark Lemley or Stanford LST Executive Director Roland Vogl at the Stanford-Vienna Transatlantic Technology Law Forum http://ttlf.stanford.edu Stanford Law School University of Vienna School of Law Crown Quadrangle Department of Business Law 559 Nathan Abbott Way Schottenbastei 10-16 Stanford, CA 94305-8610 1010 Vienna, Austria About the Author Yoan Hermstrüwer is a Senior Research Fellow at the Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods in Bonn, Germany. Prior to his academic career, he passed the First State Exam (J.D. equivalent) and the Second State Exam (bar exam equivalent).
    [Show full text]
  • Quadratic Voting and the Public Good: Introduction by Eric A
    Quadratic Voting and the Public Good: Introduction By Eric A. Posner1 and E. Glen Weyl2 Abstract: This introduction to the Public Choice special issue on “Quadratic Voting and the Public Good” provides an opinionated narrative summary of the contents and surveys the broader literature related to Quadratic Voting (QV). QV is a voting rule, proposed by one of us (Weyl, 2012; Lalley and Weyl, 2016) building off earlier work by Groves and Ledyard (1977) and Hylland and Zeckhauser (1980), where individuals buy as many votes as they wish by paying the square of the votes they buy using some currency. An appreciation of the history of research in the field suggests that QV is uniquely practically relevant compared to the other approximately Pareto-efficient mechanisms economists have proposed for collective decisions on public goods. However, it faces a number of sociological and ethical concerns regarding how a political system organized around QV would achieve the efficiency aims stated in abstract theory and whether the pure aggregate income-maximizing definition of efficiency QV optimizes in its simplest form is desirable. The papers in this volume flesh out and formalize these concerns, but also provide important responses in two ways: by suggesting domains where they are unlikely to be applicable (primarily related to survey research of various kinds) and versions of QV (using an artificial currency) that maintain many of QV’s benefits while diffusing the most important critiques. Together this work suggests both a practical path for applying QV in the near-term and a series of research questions that would have to be addressed to broaden its application.
    [Show full text]
  • Participant Biographies
    PARTICIPANT BIOGRAPHIES John Asker John Asker is a Professor of Economics at UCLA. His research covers topics related to antitrust policy, cartel behavior, vertical restraints, auction design, firm-level productivity and the effects of industry subsidies. To investigate these issues he employs a mix of theoretical and empirical methods. His papers have been published in journals such as the American Economic Review, the RAND Journal of Economics, the Journal of Public Economics and the Journal of Political Economy. He is also Co-editor of American Economic Journal: Microeconomics and a Research Associate at the National Bureau of Economic Research. He holds a Ph.D. from Harvard University and a B.Ec(Hons) from the Australian National University. Laurence Baker Laurence Baker is chief of Health Services Research at Stanford University, a professor of health research and policy, and a CHP/PCOR fellow. He is an economist interested in the organization and economic performance of the U.S. healthcare system. His research focuses on the effects of managed care on the healthcare system; the effects of regulation on healthcare markets; the determinants and effects of technological change in medicine; the culture of patient safety in U.S. hospitals; physicians' incomes and career choices; and how the Internet and e-mail influence healthcare delivery and outcomes. He received his BA from Calvin College, and his MA and PhD in economics from Princeton University. Seventh Annual Federal Trade Commission Microeconomics Conference | October 16-17, 2014 Dirk Bergemann Dirk Bergemann, is the Douglass and Marian Campbell Professor of Economics at Yale University. Dirk received his B.A.
    [Show full text]