The BIG SIGMAA News

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The BIG SIGMAA News The BIG SIGMAA News Volume 15, Number 2 Fall 2019 Business, Industry, and Government Special Interest Group of the Mathematical Association of America BIG Events at JMM in Denver Special points of In January, the Joint Mathe- Different Problems, Common Threads: Computing the diffi- interest: matics Meetings (the joint culty of Mathematical Problems, Karen Lange (Wellesley annual meeting of the Ameri- College) The Joint Mathematics can Mathematical Society and Meetings will be held January Mathematical Frameworks for Signal and Image Analysis the Mathematical Association (Colloquium Lectures), Ingrid Daubechies (Duke Universi- 15-18 in Denver . of America) returns to Denver ty) The BIG Contributed Paper after a long absence. (The meetings were last held in In Praise of Small Data: Statistical and Data Science Session will be held on Thurs- Denver in 1983). In addition (Josiah Willard Gibbs Lecture), Nancy Reid (University of day morning, January 16, to the sessions sponsored by Toronto) beginning at 8:00. the AMS and the MAA, there The Mathematics of Life: Making Diffusion Your Friend The BIG SIGMAA busi- will also be some sessions (SIAM Invited Address), James Keener (University of Utah) ness meeting will be held on sponsored by the Association for Women in Mathematics, Biomedical Data Sharing and Analysis at Scale, Bonnie Ber- Friday, January 17, at 4:30, the National Association of ger (Massachusetts Institute of Technology) with the reception following at Mathematicians, the Society of 5:15. A Numerical and Analytical Study of Dynamic Materials, Industrial and Applied Mathe- Suzanne Weekes (Worcester Polytechnic Institute) maticians, and the Association for Symbolic Logic. JMM claims to be the largest meet- 2020 meetings will be held esting sessions of shorter ing of mathematicians in the January 15–18. As always, talks. Several of the invited world; over 5,900 mathemati- there is an exciting lineup of talks might be of particular cians attended the meetings invited speakers and, of interest to BIG SIGMAA last January in Baltimore. The course, there are lots of inter- (Continued on page 3) Inside this New Officers in the BIG SIGMAA issue: The results are in, and the Lee University in Cleveland, mathematics majors of non- Michel Rolle 2 BIG SIGMAA has elected TN. Maher-Boulis received academic careers. During her three new officers who will her master’s and Ph.D. in tenure at Lee University she The Puzzle Corner 2 begin two-year terms at the pure mathematics, with a mi- developed a bachelor’s degree conclusion of the Joint Meet- nor in financial mathematics, with emphasis on actuarial A Limerick 4 ings in January. from Florida State University. sciences, created a mathemat- She is currently BIG SIG- ics internship program, se- A Winter Fig 4 The new Chair of the BIG MAA’s Secretary/Treasurer. cured formal partnerships SIGMAA is Caroline Maher- Caroline’s interests include with local businesses and in- The Puzzle Corner 4 Boulis. Dr. Maher-Boulis is a raising awareness among (Continued on page 3) Solution professor of mathematics at Page 2 The BIG SIGMAA News Michel Rolle (1652—1719) November 8, 2019 marks the three each number having seven digits. The which is ironic, since Rolle ‘s theorem hundredth anniversary of the death of public recognition of his achievement is essential for basic proofs in calculus. the French mathematician Michel led Jean-Baptiste Colbert, the control- He strove intently to demonstrate that Rolle, for whom Rolle’s Theorem is ler general of finance and secretary of calculus gave erroneous results and named. state for the navy under King Louis was based on unsound reasoning. He XIV, to reward Rolle with a pension, quarreled so vehemently on the sub- Rolle was born on April 21, 1652, in and it led François Michel le Tellier, ject that the Académie des Sciences Ambert, in central France. The son of Marquis de Louvois, the secretary of was forced to intervene on several a shopkeeper, Rolle received only an state for war, to employ Rolle to tutor occasions. He eventually, however, elementary education. He worked for his son in mathematics. Louvois also conceded that he was wrong. a time in Ambert as a transcriber for a arranged for Rolle to have an adminis- notary and then as an assistant to sev- While Rolle’s forte was always Dio- trative position in the Ministry of War, eral attorneys. In 1675 he moved to phantine analysis, his most important but Rolle disliked the work and soon Paris. A short time later he married, work was a book on the algebra of resigned. and children quickly followed. He equations, called Traité d’algèbre, pub- struggled to support his family on his In 1685 Rolle was elected to the lished in 1690. That book contains the meager wages. Despite his financial Académie des first published problems and minimal education, Sciences, but to a description in though, he studied algebra and Dio- very low-level Europe of the phantine analysis on his own. position; he re- Gaussian elimina- ceived no regular tion algorithm, Rolle’s fortune changed dramatically salary until 1699, which Rolle called in 1682 when he published an elegant when he was pro- the method of solution of a difficult, unsolved prob- moted to a sala- substitution. Some lem in Diophantine analysis that had ried position. This examples of the been posed by Jacques Ozanam; the was a distin- method had previ- problem was the following: guished post be- ously appeared in Find four numbers, the dif- cause of the 70 algebra books, and ference of any two being a members of the Isaac Newton had perfect square and the sum Academy, only 20 previously de- of the first three being a per- were paid. He scribed the meth- fect square. remained at the od in his lecture Académie for the notes, but New- Ozanam had stated that the smallest rest of his life. ton’s notes were of the four numbers would have at not published least 50 digits, but Rolle found four Rolle was one of numbers satisfying the conditions with the most vocal early critics of calculus, (Continued on page 4) The Puzzle Corner While walking down the street in an unfamiliar but friendly city with your host, you meet three men walking in the opposite direction--Abe, Bob, and Cal. Your host tells you that one is a farmer, one is a salesmen, and one is a debt collector. It being a friendly city, you stop to chat with the three men, asking them about their jobs. They respond as follows: Abe: Cal is a salesman but Bob is not a debt collector. Bob: Abe is a farmer but Cal is not a debt collector. Cal: Abe is a debt collector but Bob is not a salesman. Your host then remarks that only one of your new friends has told you the truth. What is each man's job? (solution on page 4) Volume 15, Number 2 Page 3 BIG Events at JMM in Denver (continued) (Continued from page 1) 4:15, followed by a reception. All BIG secondary education SIGMAA members are invited to at- A panel discussion on Friday members; see the inset. You can find tend the business meeting and the the details at the JMM website. reception. The reception will provide afternoon on actuarial science an opportunity to meet old friends education The BIG contributed paper session and to network with other BIG math- will be held on Thursday morning, The BIG Career Center in the ematicians. beginning at 8:00. Four speakers, from exhibits hall, a booth designed to industry, government, and academia, Other BIG events at the meeting in- provide BIG employers and BIG will talk about their experiences in clude the following activities. For job seekers a centrally-located applying mathematics to BIG prob- more information on these, go to the venue to network. lems. JMM website. We hope to see many of you in Den- The BIG SIGMAA business meeting A panel discussion on Wednesday ver. will be held on Friday afternoon at afternoon on data science post- New Officers in the BIG SIGMAA (continued) (Continued from page 1) sored project dealing with modeling Purdue University, the University of effective control strategies to mitigate Minnesota, and the University of dustries and supervised BIG projects the influence of frog skin diseases in Montana, after which he was an assis- with students. She is an experienced the ecosystem. He also had an oppor- tant professor at Bethany Lutheran grant manager having secured several tunity to work for projects sponsored College in Mankato, MN, and at grants from the Tennessee Higher by the Indian Space Research Organi- Clarkson University in Potsdam, NY, Education Commission, local busi- zation, where he used data mining where he won the university-wide nesses and industries and a 5-year techniques to analyze remote sensing Outstanding New Teacher award in grant from NSF in which she collabo- images. During his tenure at DSU, he 2010. Dr. Luttman then spent 7 years rates with ten other institutions. Her has mentored several students on their at the U.S. Department of Energy’s vision for BIG SIGMAA includes research projects coming directly from Nevada National Security Site as a creating more networking opportuni- Business, Industry, and Government scientist, personnel manager, and sci- ties and collaborating with MAA sec- Agencies through the MAA PICMath entific advisor to the National Nuclear tions to include BIG SIGMAA activi- program. At DSU, as a curriculum Security Administration, before mov- ties in their annual meetings. developer and program coordinator of ing to PNNL in spring 2019. He has the B.S. Applied and Computational served on the MAA Committee for The new Vice Chair for Programs is Mathematics degree, he has coordinat- Graduate Students, was a 2007 Project Vinodh Chellamuthu.
Recommended publications
  • Arxiv:1812.00226V2 [Math.HO] 11 Feb 2019 2010 EBI’ ELFUDDFCIN N THEIR and FICTIONS WELL-FOUNDED LEIBNIZ’S ..Bso W Prahs5 Approaches Two on Bos 130 1.2
    LEIBNIZ’S WELL-FOUNDED FICTIONS AND THEIR INTERPRETATIONS JACQUES BAIR, PIOTR BLASZCZYK, ROBERT ELY, PETER HEINIG, AND MIKHAIL G. KATZ Abstract. Leibniz used the term fiction in conjunction with in- finitesimals. What kind of fictions they were exactly is a subject of scholarly dispute. The position of Bos and Mancosu contrasts with that of Ishiguro and Arthur. Leibniz’s own views, expressed in his published articles and correspondence, led Bos to distinguish between two methods in Leibniz’s work: (A) one exploiting clas- sical ‘exhaustion’ arguments, and (B) one exploiting inassignable infinitesimals together with a law of continuity. Of particular interest is evidence stemming from Leibniz’s work Nouveaux Essais sur l’Entendement Humain as well as from his correspondence with Arnauld, Bignon, Dagincourt, Des Bosses, and Varignon. A careful examination of the evidence leads us to the opposite conclusion from Arthur’s. We analyze a hitherto unnoticed objection of Rolle’s concern- ing the lack of justification for extending axioms and operations in geometry and analysis from the ordinary domain to that of infini- tesimal calculus, and reactions to it by Saurin and Leibniz. A newly released 1705 manuscript by Leibniz (Puisque des per- sonnes. ) currently in the process of digitalisation, sheds light on the nature of Leibnizian inassignable infinitesimals. In a pair of 1695 texts Leibniz made it clear that his incompa- rable magnitudes violate Euclid’s Definition V.4, a.k.a. the Archi- medean property, corroborating the non-Archimedean construal of the Leibnizian calculus. Keywords: Archimedean property; assignable vs inassignable quantity; Euclid’s Definition V.4; infinitesimal; law of continuity; arXiv:1812.00226v2 [math.HO] 11 Feb 2019 law of homogeneity; logical fiction; Nouveaux Essais; pure fiction; quantifier-assisted paraphrase; syncategorematic; transfer princi- ple; Arnauld; Bignon; Des Bosses; Rolle; Saurin; Varignon Contents 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Hermeneutics of the Differential Calculus in Eighteenth- Century Europe
    Hermeneutics of the differential calculus in eighteenth- century Europe: from the Analyse des infiniment petits by L’Hôpital (1696) to the Traité élémentaire de calcul différentiel et de calcul intégral by Lacroix (1802)12 Mónica Blanco Abellán Departament de Matemàtica Aplicada III Universitat Politècnica de Catalunya In the history of mathematics it has not been unusual to assume that the communication of mathematical knowledge among countries flowed without constraints, partly because mathematics has often been considered as “universal knowledge”. Schubring,3 however, does not agree with this view and prefers referring to the basic units of communication, which enable the common understanding of knowledge. The basic unit should be constituted by a common language and a common culture, both interacting within a common national or state context. Insofar this interaction occurs within a national educational system, communication is here potentially possible. Consequently Schubring proposes comparative analysis of textbooks as a means to examine the differences between countries with regard to style, meaning and epistemology, since they emerge from a specific educational context. Taking Schubring’s views as starting point, the aim of this paper is to analyze and compare the mathematical development of the differential calculus in France, Germany, Italy and Britain through a number of specific works on the subject, and within their corresponding educational systems. The paper opens with an outline of the institutional framework of mathematical education in these countries. In order to assess the mathematical development of the works to be analyzed, the paper proceeds with a sketch of the epistelomogical aspects of the differential calculus in the eighteenth century.
    [Show full text]
  • Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences
    Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences Editorial Board J.Z. Buchwald J. Lu¨tzen G.J. Toomer Advisory Board P.J. Davis T. Hawkins A.E. Shapiro D. Whiteside Gert Schubring Conflicts between Generalization, Rigor, and Intuition Number Concepts Underlying the Development of Analysis in 17–19th Century France and Germany With 21 Illustrations Gert Schubring Institut fu¨r Didaktik der Mathematik Universita¨t Bielefeld Universita¨tstraße 25 D-33615 Bielefeld Germany [email protected] Sources and Studies Editor: Jed Buchwald Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences 228-77 California Institute of Technology Pasadena, CA 91125 USA Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Schubring, Gert. Conflicts between generalization, rigor, and intuition / Gert Schubring. p. cm. — (Sources and studies in the history of mathematics and physical sciences) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-387-22836-5 (acid-free paper) 1. Mathematical analysis—History—18th century. 2. Mathematical analysis—History—19th century. 3. Numbers, Negative—History. 4. Calculus—History. I. Title. II. Series. QA300.S377 2005 515′.09—dc22 2004058918 ISBN-10: 0-387-22836-5 ISBN-13: 978-0387-22836-5 Printed on acid-free paper. © 2005 Springer Science+Business Media, Inc. All rights reserved. This work may not be translated or copied in whole or in part without the written permission of the publisher (Springer Science+Business Media, Inc., 233 Spring St., New York, NY 10013, USA), except for brief excerpts in connection with reviews or scholarly analysis. Use in connection with any form of information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, com- puter software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed is for- bidden.
    [Show full text]
  • Berkeley Bibliography
    Berkeley Bibliography (1979-2019) Abad, Juan Vázques. “Observaciones sobre la noción de causa en el opusculo sobre el movimiento de Berkeley.” Analisis Filosofico 6 (1986): 35-44. Abelove, H. “George Berkeley’s Attitude to John Wesley: the Evidence of a Lost Letter.” Harvard Theological Review 70 (1977): 175-76. Ablondi, Fred. “Berkeley, Archetypes, and Errors.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (2005): 493- 504. _____. “Absolute Beginners: Learning Philosophy by Learning Descartes and Berkeley.” Metascience 19 (2010): 385-89. _____. “On the Ghosts of Departed Quantities.” Metascience 21 (2012): 681-83. _____. “Hutcheson, Perception, and the Sceptic’s Challenge.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (2012): 269-81. Ackel, Helen. Über den Prozess der menschlichen Erkenntnis bei John Locke und George Berkeley. München und Ravensburg: Grin, 2008. Adamczykowa, Izabella. “The Role of the Subject in the Cognitive Process after George Berkeley: Passive for Active Subject?” Annales Universitatis Mariae Curie Sklodowska, Sectio 1 Philosophia-Sociologia 6 (1981): 43-57. Adar, Einat. “From Irish Philosophy to Irish Theatre: The Blind (Wo)Man Made to See.” Estudios Irlandeses 12 (2017): 1-11. Addyman, David and Feldman, Matthew. “Samuel Beckett, Wilhelm Windelband, and the Interwar ‘Philosophy Notes’.” Modernism/Modernity 18 (2011): 755-70. Agassi, Joseph. “The Future of Berkeley’s Instrumentalism.” International Studies in Philosophy 7 (1975), 167-78. Aichele, Alexander. “Ich Denke Was, Was Du Nicht Denkst, Und Das Ist Rot. John Locke Und George Berkeley Über Abstrakte Ideen Und Kants Logischer Abstraktionismus.” Kant- Studien 103 (2012): 25-46. Airaksinen, Timo. “Berkeley and the Justification of Beliefs [Abstract].” Berkeley Newsletter 8 (1985), 9.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Calculus
    History of Calculus Let’s start with the definition of mathematics and calculus. Mathematics – from the Greek knowledge, study learning. Is the study of quantity, structure, space and change. Calculus (Latin, calculus, a small stone used for counting) is a branch of mathematics focused on limits, functions, derivatives, integrals, and infinite series. Is the mathematics of instantaneous rates of change – how rapidly is some particular quantity changing at this very instant? Calculus has two main branches. Differential calculus provides methods for calculating rates of change and it has many geometric applications, in particular finding tangents to curves. Integral calculus does the opposite: give the rates of chance of some quantity, it specifies the quantity itself. Geometric applications of integral calculus include the computation of areas and volumes. Perhaps the most significant is this unexpected connection between two apparently unrelated classical geometric questions: finding tangents to a curve and finding areas. Why do we have to learn mathematics? Where mathematics came from? Mathematics came from our imagination; it is a complete invention of the human brain. With the invention of mathematics we create science. Mathematics makes up human, because it’s a distinction that we have from all others animals in the animal’s kingdom. The important of mathematics and science is so great that no person living in the twentieth century can claim to be educated if they are unaware of the modern vision of the physical universe and the history of the magnificent concepts that it embodies. Science is not rigid. Dogmas are rigid. We should understand that science is the business of measuring things.
    [Show full text]
  • Gallois Galois
    GALLOIS GALOIS Individual works include Grundzfige der schlesischen geometer with Michel Rolle and Pierre Varignon . He Klinratologie (Breslau, 1857); Uher die Verbesserung der stated his intention of publishing a critical translation Plan eten elem en te (Breslau, 1858) ; Uber eine Bestimmung of Pappus, but nothing came of this project . Instead, der Sonnenparallaxe arts korrespondierenden Beohachtungen he stimulated the quarrel between his two colleagues des Planeten Flora (Breslau, 1875) ; and Mitteilungen der concerning differential calculus and impeded its set- Koniglichen Universitdts-Stern warte Breslau fiber hier hisher tlement until 1706 . gewonnene Resultate fur die geographischen and klimato- Despite this negative attitude, the consequences of logischen Ortsverhdltnisse (Breslau, 1879). If . SECONDARY LITERATURE . Works on Galle and his which might have been disastrous, Gallois deserves work are W . Foerster, "J . G. Galle," in Vierteljahrsschrift recognition by historians of science for his activities der Astronornischen Gesellschaft, 46 (1911), 17-22 ; and D . as a publicist. Although he wrote somewhat fancifully Wattenberg, J. G. Galle (Leipzig, 1963). and with little concern for coherence, he was of H . C . FREILSLEBEN service in his time as a disseminator of ideas and his work is still valuable as an historical source . GALLOIS, JEAN (b. Paris, France, 11 June 1632 ; d. Paris, 19 April 1707), history of science. The son of a counsel to the Parlement of Paris, BIBLIOGRAPHY Gallois seems to have distinguished himself in that city around 1664 by the breadth of his learning, I . ORIGINAL WORKS . Gallois's translations and other works include Traduction latine du traite de paix des by his knowledge of Hebrew and of both living and Pyrenees (Paris, 1659) ; Breviannn Colhertinum (Paris, classical languages, by his interest in the sciences, and 1679) : "Extrait du livre intitule : Observations physiques et by a genuine literary talent .
    [Show full text]
  • A Calendar of Mathematical Dates January
    A CALENDAR OF MATHEMATICAL DATES V. Frederick Rickey Department of Mathematical Sciences United States Military Academy West Point, NY 10996-1786 USA Email: fred-rickey @ usma.edu JANUARY 1 January 4713 B.C. This is Julian day 1 and begins at noon Greenwich or Universal Time (U.T.). It provides a convenient way to keep track of the number of days between events. Noon, January 1, 1984, begins Julian Day 2,445,336. For the use of the Chinese remainder theorem in determining this date, see American Journal of Physics, 49(1981), 658{661. 46 B.C. The first day of the first year of the Julian calendar. It remained in effect until October 4, 1582. The previous year, \the last year of confusion," was the longest year on record|it contained 445 days. [Encyclopedia Brittanica, 13th edition, vol. 4, p. 990] 1618 La Salle's expedition reached the present site of Peoria, Illinois, birthplace of the author of this calendar. 1800 Cauchy's father was elected Secretary of the Senate in France. The young Cauchy used a corner of his father's office in Luxembourg Palace for his own desk. LaGrange and Laplace frequently stopped in on business and so took an interest in the boys mathematical talent. One day, in the presence of numerous dignitaries, Lagrange pointed to the young Cauchy and said \You see that little young man? Well! He will supplant all of us in so far as we are mathematicians." [E. T. Bell, Men of Mathematics, p. 274] 1801 Giuseppe Piazzi (1746{1826) discovered the first asteroid, Ceres, but lost it in the sun 41 days later, after only a few observations.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1210.7750V1 [Math.HO] 29 Oct 2012 Tsml Ehdo Aiaadmnm;Rfato;Selslaw
    ALMOST EQUAL: THE METHOD OF ADEQUALITY FROM DIOPHANTUS TO FERMAT AND BEYOND MIKHAIL G. KATZ, DAVID M. SCHAPS, AND STEVEN SHNIDER Abstract. We analyze some of the main approaches in the liter- ature to the method of ‘adequality’ with which Fermat approached the problems of the calculus, as well as its source in the παρισoτης´ of Diophantus, and propose a novel reading thereof. Adequality is a crucial step in Fermat’s method of finding max- ima, minima, tangents, and solving other problems that a mod- ern mathematician would solve using infinitesimal calculus. The method is presented in a series of short articles in Fermat’s col- lected works [66, p. 133-172]. We show that at least some of the manifestations of adequality amount to variational techniques ex- ploiting a small, or infinitesimal, variation e. Fermat’s treatment of geometric and physical applications sug- gests that an aspect of approximation is inherent in adequality, as well as an aspect of smallness on the part of e. We question the rel- evance to understanding Fermat of 19th century dictionary defini- tions of παρισoτης´ and adaequare, cited by Breger, and take issue with his interpretation of adequality, including his novel reading of Diophantus, and his hypothesis concerning alleged tampering with Fermat’s texts by Carcavy. We argue that Fermat relied on Bachet’s reading of Diophantus. Diophantus coined the term παρισoτης´ for mathematical pur- poses and used it to refer to the way in which 1321/711 is ap- proximately equal to 11/6. Bachet performed a semantic calque in passing from pariso¯o to adaequo.
    [Show full text]
  • Sources in the Development of Mathematics
    This page intentionally left blank Sources in the Development of Mathematics The discovery of infinite products by Wallis and infinite series by Newton marked the beginning of the modern mathematical era. The use of series allowed Newton to find the area under a curve defined by any algebraic equation, an achievement completely beyond the earlier methods of Torricelli, Fermat, and Pascal. The work of Newton and his contemporaries, including Leibniz and the Bernoullis, was concentrated in math- ematical analysis and physics. Euler’s prodigious mathematical accomplishments dramatically extended the scope of series and products to algebra, combinatorics, and number theory. Series and products proved pivotal in the work of Gauss, Abel, and Jacobi in elliptic functions; in Boole and Lagrange’s operator calculus; and in Cayley, Sylvester, and Hilbert’s invariant theory. Series and products still play a critical role in the mathematics of today. Consider the conjectures of Langlands, including that of Shimura-Taniyama, leading to Wiles’s proof of Fermat’s last theorem. Drawing on the original work of mathematicians from Europe, Asia, and America, Ranjan Roy discusses many facets of the discovery and use of infinite series and products. He gives context and motivation for these discoveries, including original notation and diagrams when practical. He presents multiple derivations for many important theorems and formulas and provides interesting exercises, supplementing the results of each chapter. Roy deals with numerous results, theorems, and methods used by students, mathematicians, engineers, and physicists. Moreover, since he presents original math- ematical insights often omitted from textbooks, his work may be very helpful to mathematics teachers and researchers.
    [Show full text]
  • Berkeley Bibliography
    Berkeley Bibliography (1979-2011) Abad, Juan Vázques. “Observaciones sobre la noción de causa en el opusculo sobre el movimiento de Berkeley.” Analisis Filosofico 6 (1986): 35-44. Abelove, H. “George Berkeley’s Attitude to John Wesley: the Evidence of a Lost Letter.” Harvard Theological Review 70 (1977): 175-76. Ablondi, Fred. “Berkeley, Archetypes, and Errors.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (2005): 493- 504. _____. “Absolute Beginners: Learning Philosophy by Learning Descartes and Berkeley.” Metascience 19 (2010): 385-89. Ackel, Helen. Über den Prozess der menschlichen Erkenntnis bei John Locke und George Berkeley. München und Ravensburg: Grin, 2008. Adamczykowa, Izabella. “The Role of the Subject in the Cognitive Process after George Berkeley: Passive for Active Subject?” Annales Universitatis Mariae Curie Sklodowska, Sectio 1 Philosophia-Sociologia 6 (1981): 43-57. Agassi, Joseph. “The Future of Berkeley’s Instrumentalism.” International Studies in Philosophy 7 (1975), 167-78. Airaksinen, Timo. “Berkeley and the Justification of Beliefs [Abstract].” Berkeley Newsletter 8 (1985), 9. _____. “Berkeley and the Justification of Beliefs.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (1987), 235-56. _____. “The Chain and the Animal: Idealism in Berkeley’s Siris.” In Gersh and Moran (2006), 224- 43. _____. “The Path of Fire: The Meaning and Interpretation of Berkeley’s Siris.” In Daniel, New Interpretations (2007), 261-81. _____. “Berkeley and Newton on Gravity in Siris.” In Parigi (2010b), 87-106. _____. “Active Principles and Trinities in Berkeley’s Siris.” Revue Philosophique de la France et de l’Ėtranger 135 (2010): 57-70. _____. “Rhetoric and Corpuscularism in Berkeley’s Siris.” History of European Ideas 37 (2011): 23-34.
    [Show full text]
  • One of Berkeley’S Arguments on Compensating Errors in The
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Available online at www.sciencedirect.com Historia Mathematica 38 (2011) 219–231 www.elsevier.com/locate/yhmat One of Berkeley’s arguments on compensating errors in the calculus Kirsti Andersen * Department of Sciences Studies, Aarhus University, C.F. Moellers Allé 8, Building 1110, DK 8000 Aarhus, Denmark Abstract This paper addresses three questions related to George Berkeley’s theory of compensating errors in the calculus published in 1734. The first is how did Berkeley conceive of Leibnizian differentials? The second and most central question concerns Berkeley’s procedure which consisted in identifying two quantities as errors and proving that they are equal. The question is how was this possible? The answer is that this was not possible, because in his calculations Berkeley misguided himself by employing a result equivalent to what he wished to prove. In 1797 Lazare Carnot published the expression “a compensation of errors” in an attempt to explain why the calculus functions. The third question is: did Carnot by this expression mean the same as Berkeley? Ó 2010 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Riassunto Questo articolo affronta tre domande concernenti la teoria di Berkeley sulla compensazione degli errori nel calcolo pubblicata nel 1734. La prima è, come concepiva Berkeley i differenziali leibniziani? La seconda domanda, quella più importante, concerne la procedura di Berkeley consistente nell’identificare due quantità come errori per poi provare che esse sono uguali. La domanda è, come è possibile questo? La risposta è che ciò non è possibile dato che nei suoi calcoli Berkeley si ingannò utilizzando un risultato equivalente a quello che voleva provare.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Thesis
    This electronic thesis or dissertation has been downloaded from the King’s Research Portal at https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/ Berkeley’s Analyst Rigour and Rhetoric Moriarty, Clare Marie Awarding institution: King's College London The copyright of this thesis rests with the author and no quotation from it or information derived from it may be published without proper acknowledgement. END USER LICENCE AGREEMENT Unless another licence is stated on the immediately following page this work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International licence. https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ You are free to copy, distribute and transmit the work Under the following conditions: Attribution: You must attribute the work in the manner specified by the author (but not in any way that suggests that they endorse you or your use of the work). Non Commercial: You may not use this work for commercial purposes. No Derivative Works - You may not alter, transform, or build upon this work. Any of these conditions can be waived if you receive permission from the author. Your fair dealings and other rights are in no way affected by the above. Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 26. Sep. 2021 Berkeley’s Analyst: Rigour and Rhetoric Clare Marie Moriarty A Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy July 2018 Abstract of the Dissertation This thesis argues for a new interpretation of The Analyst based on Berkeley’s mature theory of meaning and its role in his views on religion and mathematics.
    [Show full text]