Hate Speech Law

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hate Speech Law Hate Speech Law Hate speech law can be found throughout the world. But it is also the subject of numerous principled arguments, both for and against. These principles invoke a host of morally relevant features (e.g., liberty, health, autonomy, security, non-subordination, the absence of oppression, human dignity, the discovery of truth, the acquisition of knowledge, self-realization, human excellence, civic dignity, cultural diversity and choice, recognition of cultural identity, intercultural dialogue, participation in democratic self-government, being subject only to legitimate rule) and practical considerations (e.g., effi- cacy, the least restrictive alternative, chilling effects). The book develops and then critically examines these various principled arguments. It also attempts to de-homogenize hate speech law into different clusters of laws/regulations/ codes that constrain uses of hate speech, so as to facilitate a more nuanced examination of the principled arguments. Finally, it argues that it is morally fitting for judicial and legislative judgments about the overall warrant of hate speech law to reflect principled compromise. Principled compromise is characterized not merely by compromise over matters of principled concern but also by compromise which is itself governed by ideals of moral duty or civic virtue (e.g., reciprocity, equality, mutual respect). Alexander Brown is Senior Lecturer in Contemporary Social and Political Theory at the University of East Anglia (UEA). He is the author of Ronald Dworkin’s Theory of Equality: Domestic and Global Perspectives (2009) and Personal Responsibility: Why It Matters (2009). Routledge Studies in Contemporary Philosophy For a full list of titles in this series, please visit www.routledge.com 30 Feminism, Psychoanalysis, and 39 Contrastivism in Philosophy Maternal Subjectivity Edited by Martijn Blaauw Alison Stone 40 Aesthetics After Metaphysics 31 Civility in Politics and Education From Mimesis to Metaphor Edited by Deborah S. Mower, Miguel de Beistegui Wade L. Robison 41 Foundations of Freedom 32 Philosophical Inquiry into Welfare-Based Arguments Pregnancy, Childbirth, and against Paternalism Mothering Simon R. Clarke Maternal Subjects Edited by Sheila Lintott and 42 Pittsburgh School of Maureen Sander-Staudt Philosophy Sellars, McDowell, Brandom 33 Authenticity as an Ethical Ideal Chauncey Maher Somogy Varga 43 Reference and Structure 34 The Philosophy of Curiosity in the Philosophy of Ilhan Inan Language A Defense of the Russellian 35 Self-Realization and Justice Orthodoxy A Liberal-Perfectionist Defense Arthur Sullivan of the Right to Freedom from Employment 44 Civic Virtue and the Julia Maskivker Sovereignty of Evil Derek Edyvane 36 Narrative Identity, Autonomy, and Mortality 45 Philosophy of Language and From Frankfurt and MacIntyre to Webs of Information Kierkegaard Heimir Geirsson John J. Davenport 46 Disagreement and 37 Contemporary Feminist Skepticism Pragmatism Edited by Diego E. Machuca Edited by Maurice Hamington and Celia Bardwell-Jones 47 Philosophy in Schools An Introduction for Philosophers 38 Morality, Self Knowledge, and and Teachers Human Suffering Edited by Sara Goering, An Essay on The Loss of Nicholas J. Shudak, and Thomas Confidence in the World E. Wartenberg Josep Corbi 48 A Philosophy of Material 58 Realism, Science, and Culture Pragmatism Action, Function, and Mind Edited by Kenneth R. Westphal Beth Preston 59 Evidentialism and Epistemic 49 A Philosophy of the Screenplay Justification Ted Nannicelli Kevin McCain 50 Race, Philosophy, and Film 60 Democracy in Contemporary Edited by Mary K. Bloodsworth- Confucian Philosophy Lugo and Dan Flory David Elstein 51 Knowledge, Virtue, and Action 61 Deleuze and Pragmatism Essays on Putting Epistemic Edited by Sean Bowden, Virtues to Work Simone Bignall, and Paul Patton Edited by Tim Henning and David P. Schweikard 62 Mind, Language and Subjectivity 52 The Ontology of Psychology Minimal Content and the Theory Questioning Foundations in the of Thought Philosophy of Mind Nicholas Georgalis Linda A.W. Brakel 63 Believing Against the 53 Pragmatism, Law, and Evidence Language Agency and the Ethics of Edited by Graham Hubbs and Belief Douglas Lind Miriam Schleifer McCormick 54 Contemporary Dualism 64 The Essence of the Self A Defense In Defense of the Simple View of Edited by Andrea Lavazza and Personal Identity Howard M. Robinson Geoffrey Madell 55 Reframing the Intercultural 65 Personal Autonomy and Social Dialogue on Human Rights Oppression A Philosophical Approach Philosophical Perspectives Jeffrey Flynn Edited by Marina A.L. Oshana 56 How History Matters to 66 Domination and Global Philosophy Political Justice Reconsidering Philosophy’s Past Conceptual, Historical, and After Positivism Institutional Perspectives Robert C. Scharff Edited by Barbara Buckinx, Jonathan Trejo-Mathys, and 57 The Affordable Care Act Timothy Waligore Decision Philosophical and Legal Implications 67 Hate Speech Law Edited by Fritz Allhoff and Mark A Philosophical Examination Hall Alexander Brown Hate Speech Law A Philosophical Examination Alexander Brown First published 2015 by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 and by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2015 Taylor & Francis The right of Alexander Brown to be identified as author of this work has been asserted by him/her in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. The Open Access version of this book, available at www.taylorfrancis.com, has been made available under a Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial-No Derivatives 4.0 license. Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Brown, Alexander, 1974 December 27- author. Hate speech law : a philosophical examination / Alex Brown. pages cm. — (Routledge studies in contemporary philosophy ; 67) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Hate speech—Law and legislation. 2. Hate speech—Philosophy. I. Title. K5210.B76 2015 345′.02501—dc23 2014040617 ISBN: 978-0-415-88547-8 (hbk) ISBN: 978-1-315-71489-9 (ebk) Typeset in Sabon by Apex CoVantage, LLC For Adriana Contents Table of Cases xi Acknowledgments xv 1 Introduction 1 2 Ten Clusters of Laws/Regulations/Codes That Constrain Uses of Hate Speech 19 2.1 Group Defamation 19 2.2 Negative Stereotyping or Stigmatization 21 2.3 The Expression of Hatred 23 2.4 Incitement to Hatred 26 2.5 Threats to Public Order 28 2.6 Denying, etc. Acts of Mass Cruelty, Violence, or Genocide 29 2.7 Dignitary Crimes or Torts 30 2.8 Violations of Civil or Human Rights 33 2.9 Expression-Oriented Hate Crimes 35 2.10 Time, Place, and Manner Restrictions 38 3 Principles of Basic Morality 49 3.1 Health 49 3.2 Autonomy 58 3.3 Security 66 3.4 Non-Subordination 75 3.5 The Absence of Oppression 86 3.6 Human Dignity 91 4 Principles of Personal Development 106 4.1 The Discovery of Truth 106 4.2 The Acquisition of Knowledge 116 4.3 Self-Realization 120 4.4 Human Excellence 127 x Contents 5 Principles of Civic Morality 142 5.1 Civic Dignity 142 5.2 Assurance 148 5.3 Eligibility 152 6 Principles of Cultural Diversity 160 6.1 Culture 161 6.2 Misrecognition 166 6.3 Cultural Specifi city 174 6.4 Intercultural Dialogue 180 7 Principles of Political Morality 187 7.1 Democratic Self-Government 187 7.2 Political Legitimacy 201 7.3 Citizens as Legal Subjects 209 8 Principles of Balance 218 8.1 Rights-Based Balancing 218 8.2 Interests-Based Balancing 222 9 Principia Juris 239 9.1 Pressing Social Need 239 9.2 Effi cacy 242 9.3 The Least Restrictive Alternative 251 9.4 The Avoidance of Unintended Consequences for Free Speech 263 9.5 Neutrality 269 10 Toward a Theory of Principled Compromise 276 10.1 Why Overall Warrant Should Be Neither about Lexical Priorities among Principles nor Balancing between Principles 277 10.2 Overall Warrant as Compromise over Principles 281 10.3 Conjunction Compromise 284 10.4 Substitution Compromise 285 10.5 A Detailed Illustration: The Principle of Neutrality 287 10.6 The Ethics of Compromise 297 10.7 Two Possible Objections 306 11 Conclusion 316 References 321 Index 347 Table of Cases Australia Bryant v. Queensland Newspaper Pty Ltd. 25 Eatock v. Bolt 25, 165, 184, 272 Jones v. Toben 48 Brazil Case of Diane Soares da Costa 32 Canada Bou Malhab v. Diffusion Métromedia CMR Inc. 237 Canada (Human Rights Commission) v. Taylor 11–12, 186, 271–2, 275 Edmonton Journal v. Alberta (Attorney General) 282 Mugesera v. Canada (Minister of Citizenship and Immigration) 28 Ortenberg v. Plamondon 31 R. v. Keegstra 11–12, 110, 138, 147, 164, 184, 186, 223–4, 244, 257, 266, 271–2, 274–5, 310 R. v. Oakes 18, 271–2 R. v. Zündel 97, 197, 216, 265 Saskatchewan (Human Rights Commission) v. Whatcott 93, 197, 216, 265, 272, 280 Singer v. Iwasyk and Pennywise Food Ltd. 34 China Case of Chen and Wang 31 Committee on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination (CERD) TBB-Turkish Union in Berlin/Brandenburg v. Germany 24 European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) Aksu v. Turkey 11, 35, 47, 235 Appleby and Others v. United Kingdom 275 xii Table of Cases Balsytė-Lideikienė v. Lithuania 12, 45, 271, 275 Féret v. Belgium 12, 271–2, 275 Garaudy v. France 12, 46 Glimmerveen and Hagenbeek v. Netherlands 37 Handyside v. United Kingdom 243, 270, 275 Jersild v. Denmark 11 Mouvement Raelien Suisse v. Switzerland 275 Nilsen and Johnsen v. Norway 18 Peta Deutschland v. Germany 272 Refah Partisi (The Welfare Party) and Others v. Turkey 197 Ricci v. Italy 272 Soulas and others v. France 12, 270, 272, 275 Vejdeland and Others v. Sweden 11–12, 43, 66, 100, 145, 158, 271–2, 275 Willem v. France 12 X v. Federal Republic of Germany 171 Germany Case of the Fraudulent Asylum Seeker Poem 156 Case of Guenter Deckert 97, 219 Case of Kruzifi x-Urteil 286 Case of National Democratic Party of Germany (or ‘Auschwitz Lie’) 146, 219, 286 Case of Germar Rudolf 96, 219 Case of Ernst Zündel 98, 219, 249 Hungary Case of György Nagy 135–6 International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda Nahimana, Barayagwiza, Ngeze v.
Recommended publications
  • Cyber Bullying and Victimization: Psychosocial Characteristics of Bullies, Victims, and Bully/ Victims Delia Carroll Campfield the University of Montana
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Theses, Dissertations, Professional Papers Graduate School 2008 Cyber Bullying and Victimization: Psychosocial Characteristics of Bullies, Victims, and Bully/ Victims Delia Carroll Campfield The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Recommended Citation Campfield, Delia Carroll, "Cyber Bullying and Victimization: Psychosocial Characteristics of Bullies, Victims, and Bully/Victims" (2008). Theses, Dissertations, Professional Papers. Paper 288. This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses, Dissertations, Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CYBER BULLYING AND VICTIMIZATION: PSYCHOSOCIAL CHARACTERISTICS OF BULLIES, VICTIMS, AND BULLY/VICTIMS By Delia Carroll Campfield Master of Arts, The University of Montana, Missoula, Montana, 2006 Dissertation presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Psychology, Clinical The University of Montana Missoula, MT Official Graduation: Summer, 2008 Approved by: Dr. David A. Strobel, Dean Graduate School Dr. Christine Fiore, Chair Department of Psychology Dr. Greg Machek Department of Psychology Dr. Margaret Beebe-Frakenberger Department of Psychology Dr. Darrell Stolle Department of Curriculum and Instruction Dr. Danette Wollersheim Licensed Clinical Psychologist Campfield, Delia, Ph.D. Summer 2008 Clinical Psychology Cyber Bullying and Victimization: Psychosocial Characteristics of Bullies, Victims, and Bully/Victims Chairperson: Dr. Christine Fiore This study explored cyber bullying and victimization. The use of technology as a vehicle for peer victimization is increasing and is associated with a risk of psychosocial maladjustment (Finkelhor, et al., 2000; Wolak, et al., 2006; Ybarra & Mitchell, 2004a, 2004b).
    [Show full text]
  • Crime Prevention Guide
    CRIME PREVENTION GUIDE MURDER & ASSAULT Most murder and assault victims know their attackers. Many times, the people involved in the incident are drunk or on drugs. Murder or assault can also be the result of another crime such as burglary or robbery. The victim is killed when he or she resists. Other murders or assaults happen because of some seemingly trivial confrontation that turns violent because of anger, irrational thinking, alcohol or drugs. • If you think you are in danger, go to a safe place, then call police. • Do not touch anything. • While waiting for police, you should write down the license plate numbers of any vehicles leaving the crime scene. • Make a note of any suspicious people you see in the area. • When police arrive, they will search for evidence and ask you to provide any information you may have. • If you have additional information after the officers leave, call the Criminal Investigation Division at (972) 625-1887. Investigating officers will ask victims and witnesses for details of the incident. Correct information is extremely important because it can help in making a speedy arrest and determine what charges should be filed. When the initial investigation is completed, the officer will write a report and send it to the Criminal Investigation Division. The Division will review the case, contact the victim and witnesses, file charges if possible and do everything within reason to arrest the suspect. PREVENTION • Avoid high-crime areas when possible. • If you have to travel in dangerous areas, remain alert to your surroundings. Watch for strangers who may approach you without apparent reason.
    [Show full text]
  • " Ht Tr H" : Trtp Nd N Nd Tnf P Rhtn Th
    ht "ht Trh": trtp nd n ndtn f Pr ht n th .. nnl Ntz, tth r Minnesota Review, Number 47, Fall 1996 (New Series), pp. 57-72 (Article) Pblhd b D nvrt Pr For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/mnr/summary/v047/47.newitz.html Access provided by Middlebury College (11 Dec 2015 16:54 GMT) Annalee Newitz and Matthew Wray What is "White Trash"? Stereotypes and Economic Conditions of Poor Whites in the U.S. "White trash" is, in many ways, the white Other. When we think about race in the U.S., oftentimes we find ourselves constrained by cat- egories we've inherited from a kind of essentialist multiculturalism, or what we call "vulgar multiculturalism."^ Vulgar multiculturalism holds that racial and ethic groups are "authentically" and essentially differ- ent from each other, and that racism is a one-way street: it proceeds out of whiteness to subjugate non-whiteness, so that all racists are white and all victims of racism are non-white. Critical multiculturalism, as it has been articulated by theorists such as those in the Chicago Cultural Studies Group, is one example of a multiculturalism which tries to com- plicate and trouble the dogmatic ways vulgar multiculturalism has un- derstood race, gender, and class identities. "White trash" identity is one we believe a critical multiculturalism should address in order to further its project of re-examining the relationships between identity and social power. Unlike the "whiteness" of vulgar multiculturalism, the whiteness of "white trash" signals something other than privilege and social power.
    [Show full text]
  • Statement by Alice Wairimu Nderitu, United Nations Special Adviser on the Prevention of Genocide, on the Continued Deterioration of the Situation in Ethiopia
    UNITED NATIONS PRESS RELEASE For immediate release Statement by Alice Wairimu Nderitu, United Nations Special Adviser on the Prevention of Genocide, on the continued deterioration of the situation in Ethiopia (New York, 30 July 2021) The Special Adviser of the Secretary-General on the Prevention of Genocide, Alice Wairimu Nderitu, expressed alarm at the continued deterioration of ethnic violence in Ethiopia and at the strong allegations of serious violations of international humanitarian and human rights law in the Tigray region as well as in other parts of the country, including in Afar, Somali, Oromo and Amhara regions. The Special Adviser also reiterated concerns expressed in her 5 February 2021 statement on the situation in the country. Since the beginning of the conflict in the Tigray region, the Special Adviser has continued to receive reports of serious human rights violations and abuses, including alleged sexual violence, recruitment of child soldiers, arbitrary arrests and ethnic based targeted killings committed by all parties, which have now escalated to other parts of the country. She also deplored the erosion of rule of law and echoed the recent call by the Human Rights Council for an immediate end to the violence and human rights violations in Tigray. The Special Adviser also condemned inflammatory statements used by top political leaders and associated armed groups. The use of pejorative and dehumanizing language like “cancer”, “devil”, “weed” and “bud” to refer to the Tigray conflict is of utmost concern. Hate speech, together with its propagation through social media is part of a worrisome trend that contributes to further fuel ethnic tensions in the country.
    [Show full text]
  • Collaborative Storytelling 2.0: a Framework for Studying Forum-Based Role-Playing Games
    COLLABORATIVE STORYTELLING 2.0: A FRAMEWORK FOR STUDYING FORUM-BASED ROLE-PLAYING GAMES Csenge Virág Zalka A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY May 2017 Committee: Kristine Blair, Committee Co-Chair Lisa M. Gruenhagen Graduate Faculty Representative Radhika Gajjala, Committee Co-Chair Jeremy Wallach ii ABSTRACT Kristine Blair and Radhika Gajjala, Committee Co-Chairs Forum-based role-playing games are a rich, yet barely researched subset of text- based digital gaming. They are a form of storytelling where narratives are created through acts of play by multiple people in an online space, combining collaboration and improvisation. This dissertation acts as a pilot study for exploring these games in their full complexity at the intersection of play, narrative, and fandom. Building on theories of interactivity, digital storytelling, and fan fiction studies, it highlights forum games’ most unique features, and proves that they are is in no way liminal or secondary to more popular forms of role-playing. The research is based on data drawn from a large sample of forums of various genres. One hundred sites were explored through close textual analysis in order to outline their most common features. The second phase of the project consisted of nine months of participant observation on select forums, in order to gain a better understanding of how their rules and practices influence the emergent narratives. Participants from various sites contributed their own interpretations of forum gaming through a series of ethnographic interviews. This did not only allow agency to the observed communities to voice their thoughts and explain their practices, but also spoke directly to the key research question of why people are drawn to forum gaming.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrastivism Surveyed
    Contrastivism Surveyed (Forthcoming in Nous) Jonathan Schaffer Joshua Knobe ANU-RSSS Yale University Suppose that Ann says, “Keith knows that the bank will be open tomorrow.” Her audience may well agree. Her knowledge ascription may seem true. But now suppose that Ben—in a different context—also says “Keith knows that the bank will be open tomorrow.” His audience may well disagree. His knowledge ascription may seem false. Indeed, a number of philosophers have claimed that people’s intuitions about knowledge ascriptions are context sensitive, in the sense that the very same knowledge ascription can seem true in one conversational context but false in another. This purported fact about people’s intuitions serves as one of the main pieces of evidence for epistemic contextualism, which is (roughly speaking) the view that the truth conditions of a knowledge attribution can differ from one conversational context to another. Opponents of contextualism have replied by trying to explain these purported intuitions in other ways. For instance, they have proposed that these purported intuitions may be explained via shifts in what is at stake for the subject, pragmatic shifts in what is assertible, or performance shifts in our liability to error. Yet a recent series of empirical studies threatens to undermine this whole debate. These studies presented ordinary people with precisely the sorts of cases that have been discussed in the contextualism literature and gave them an opportunity to say whether they agreed or disagreed with the relevant knowledge attributions. Strikingly, the results suggest that people simply do not have the intuitions they were purported to have.
    [Show full text]
  • Brigitte Bailer-Galanda “Revisionism”1 in Germany and Austria: the Evolution of a Doctrine
    www.doew.at Brigitte Bailer-Galanda “Revisionism”1 in Germany and Austria: The Evolution of a Doctrine Published in: Hermann Kurthen/Rainer Erb/Werner Bergmann (ed.), Anti-Sem- itism and Xenophobia in Germany after Unification, New York–Oxford 1997 Development of “revisionism” since 1945 Most people understand so called „revisionism“ as just another word for the movement of holocaust denial (Benz 1994; Lipstadt 1993; Shapiro 1990). Therefore it was suggested lately to use the word „negationism“ instead. How- ever in the author‘s point of view „revisionism“ covers some more topics than just the denying of the National Socialist mass murders. Especially in Germany and Austria there are some more points of National Socialist politics some people have tried to minimize or apologize since 1945, e. g. the responsibility for World War II, the attack on the Soviet Union in 1941 (quite a modern topic), (the discussion) about the number of the victims of the holocaust a. s. o.. In the seventies the late historian Martin Broszat already called that movement „run- ning amok against reality“ (Broszat 1976). These pseudo-historical writers, many of them just right wing extremist publishers or people who quite rapidly turned to right wing extremists, really try to prove that history has not taken place, just as if they were able to make events undone by denying them. A conception of “negationism” (Auerbach 1993a; Fromm and Kernbach 1994, p. 9; Landesamt für Verfassungsschutz 1994) or “holocaust denial” (Lipstadt 1993, p. 20) would neglect the additional components of “revision- ism”, which are logically connected with the denying of the holocaust, this being the extreme variant.
    [Show full text]
  • Holocaust-Denial Literature: a Fourth Bibliography
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Publications and Research York College 2000 Holocaust-Denial Literature: A Fourth Bibliography John A. Drobnicki CUNY York College How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/yc_pubs/25 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] Holocaust-Denial Literature: A Fourth Bibliography John A. Drobnicki This bibliography is a supplement to three earlier ones published in the March 1994, Decem- ber 1996, and September 1998 issues of the Bulletin of Bibliography. During the intervening time. Holocaust revisionism has continued to be discussed both in the scholarly literature and in the mainstream press, especially owing to the libel lawsuit filed by David Irving against Deb- orah Lipstadt and Penguin Books. The Holocaust deniers, who prefer to call themselves “revi- sionists” in an attempt to gain scholarly legitimacy, have refused to go away and remain as vocal as ever— Bradley R. Smith has continued to send revisionist advertisements to college newspapers (including free issues of his new publication. The Revisionist), generating public- ity for his cause. Holocaust-denial, which will be used interchangeably with Holocaust revisionism in this bib- liography, is a body of literature that seeks to “prove” that the Jewish Holocaust did not hap- pen. Although individual revisionists may have different motives and beliefs, they all share at least one point: that there was no systematic attempt by Nazi Germany to exterminate Euro- pean Jewry.
    [Show full text]
  • Tort Recovery for Loss of a Chance David A
    University of Missouri School of Law Scholarship Repository Faculty Publications Fall 2001 Tort Recovery for Loss of a Chance David A. Fischer University of Missouri School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.missouri.edu/facpubs Part of the Torts Commons Recommended Citation David A. Fischer, Tort Recovery for Loss of A Chance, 36 Wake Forest L. Rev. 605 (2001) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by University of Missouri School of Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of University of Missouri School of Law Scholarship Repository. TORT RECOVERY FOR LOSS OF A CHANCE David A- Fischer- "Loss of a chance" is a novel theory of causation commonly used by courts in the United States in medical misdiagnosis cases. Yet, the theory has a vastly broader potential application than this. In fact, it could be applied in virtually every case of questionable causation. While this Article asserts that the doctrine could legitimately be expanded and applied in a variety of additionalsituations, the Article cautions that it would be unwise to apply the doctrine so broadly that it routinely supplants traditional causation rules. The Article searches for a principled basis for limiting the theory within proper bounds by comparing the differing applicationsof the loss of a chance doctrine in British Commonwealth cases and United States cases. The Article concludes that current rationalesfor the doctrine do not provide an adequate limiting principle, but that a case by case policy analysis can appropriatelylimit the theory.
    [Show full text]
  • A Contract Theory of Academic Freedom
    Saint Louis University Law Journal Volume 59 Number 2 Current Issues in Education Law Article 8 (Winter 2015) 2015 A Contract Theory of Academic Freedom Philip Lee University of the District of Columbia David A. Clarke School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.slu.edu/lj Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Philip Lee, A Contract Theory of Academic Freedom, 59 St. Louis U. L.J. (2015). Available at: https://scholarship.law.slu.edu/lj/vol59/iss2/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Saint Louis University Law Journal by an authorized editor of Scholarship Commons. For more information, please contact Susie Lee. SAINT LOUIS UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW A CONTRACT THEORY OF ACADEMIC FREEDOM1 PHILIP LEE* INTRODUCTION Academic freedom is central to the core role of professors in a free society. Yet, current First Amendment protections exist to protect academic institutions, not the academics themselves. For example, in Urofsky v. Gilmore, six professors employed by various public colleges and universities in Virginia challenged a law restricting state employees from accessing sexually explicit material on computers owned or leased by the state.2 The professors claimed, in part, that such a restriction was in violation of their First Amendment academic freedom rights to conduct scholarly research.3 The Fourth Circuit upheld the law and noted that “to the extent the Constitution recognizes any right of ‘academic freedom’ above and beyond the First Amendment rights to which every citizen is entitled, the right inheres in the University, not in individual professors, and is not violated by the terms of the Act.”4 In other words, this particular court held that academic freedom protects the institution as a whole, but not the individual professors.
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago in Praise of Praise a Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Division of the Humanities in Candi
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO IN PRAISE OF PRAISE A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY DANIEL J. TELECH CHICAGO, ILLINOIS AUGUST 2018 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I thank my dissertation committee. I am incredibly fortunate to have had Agnes Callard and Brian Leiter direct my dissertation project. Their support, wisdom, and generosity have meant a great deal to me—philosophically and personally—over the past several years. Joint dissertation meetings with Agnes and Brian unfailingly left me with a sense of urgency, demandingness, and encouragement that remains with me, at least on good days, when doing philosophy. Before they were my advisors, they were my teachers. Agnes’ seminar on deliberation, on the one hand, and Brian’s workshop on free will and responsibility, on the other, played significant roles in my becoming gripped by the questions animating this project. I hope to be able to live up to the ideals that working and studying with them has allowed me, however incipiently, to appreciate. I thank Paul Russell for being an excellent committee member. Paul has helped me stay attuned to the complexity and humanness of issues of agency and responsibility. This dissertation owes much to insightful conversations with him. I also thank Derk Pereboom. Derk supervised a valuable visit of mine to Cornell in the fall of 2016, and became something of an unofficial committee member, providing me with generous and instructive comments on the majority of the dissertation. There are many others to whom I am grateful for support with and valuable discussion on, parts of my project, and its earlier and attendant stages.
    [Show full text]
  • UN Strategy and Plan of Action on Hate Speech
    UNITED NATIONS STRATEGY AND PLAN OF ACTION ON HATE SPEECH Foreword Around the world, we are seeing a disturbing groundswell of xenophobia, racism and intolerance – including rising anti-Semitism, anti-Muslim hatred and persecution of Christians. Social media and other forms of communication are being exploited as platforms for bigotry. Neo-Nazi and white supremacy movements are on the march. Public discourse is being weaponized for political gain with incendiary rhetoric that stigmatizes and dehumanizes minorities, migrants, refugees, women and any so-called “other”. This is not an isolated phenomenon or the loud voices of a few people on the fringe of society. Hate is moving into the mainstream – in liberal democracies and authoritarian systems alike. And with each broken norm, the pillars of our common humanity are weakened. Hate speech is a menace to democratic values, social stability and peace. As a matter of principle, the United Nations must confront hate speech at every turn. Silence can signal indifference to bigotry and intolerance, even as a situation escalates and the vulnerable become victims. Tackling hate speech is also crucial to deepen progress across the United Nations agenda by helping to prevent armed conflict, atrocity crimes and terrorism, end violence against women and other serious violations of human rights, and promote peaceful, inclusive and just societies. Addressing hate speech does not mean limiting or prohibiting freedom of speech. It means keeping hate speech from escalating into something more dangerous, particularly incitement to discrimination, hostility and violence, which is prohibited under international law. The United Nations has a long history of mobilizing the world against hatred of all kinds through wide-ranging action to defend human rights and advance the rule of law.
    [Show full text]