The University of Chicago in Praise of Praise a Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Division of the Humanities in Candi

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The University of Chicago in Praise of Praise a Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Division of the Humanities in Candi THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO IN PRAISE OF PRAISE A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY DANIEL J. TELECH CHICAGO, ILLINOIS AUGUST 2018 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I thank my dissertation committee. I am incredibly fortunate to have had Agnes Callard and Brian Leiter direct my dissertation project. Their support, wisdom, and generosity have meant a great deal to me—philosophically and personally—over the past several years. Joint dissertation meetings with Agnes and Brian unfailingly left me with a sense of urgency, demandingness, and encouragement that remains with me, at least on good days, when doing philosophy. Before they were my advisors, they were my teachers. Agnes’ seminar on deliberation, on the one hand, and Brian’s workshop on free will and responsibility, on the other, played significant roles in my becoming gripped by the questions animating this project. I hope to be able to live up to the ideals that working and studying with them has allowed me, however incipiently, to appreciate. I thank Paul Russell for being an excellent committee member. Paul has helped me stay attuned to the complexity and humanness of issues of agency and responsibility. This dissertation owes much to insightful conversations with him. I also thank Derk Pereboom. Derk supervised a valuable visit of mine to Cornell in the fall of 2016, and became something of an unofficial committee member, providing me with generous and instructive comments on the majority of the dissertation. There are many others to whom I am grateful for support with and valuable discussion on, parts of my project, and its earlier and attendant stages. I thank Nomy Arpaly, Dani Attas, Gunnar Björnsson, Dan Baras, Alex Boeglin, Matt Boyle, Pascal Brixel, Mark Bronson, Dan Brudney, Andreas Carlsson-Brekke, Justin Coates, Taylor Cyr, Evan Dutmer, David Enoch, Augie Faller, Paul Franks, Tobias Fuchs, Sol Goldberg, ii Matthias Haase, David Heyd, Karolina Huebner, Jessica Isserow, Michael Kremer, Jonathan Lear, Arnon Levy, Nethanel Lipshitz, Julia Markovits, Karin Nisenbaum, Martha Nussbaum, Andrew Pitel, Gabriel Richardson Lear, Robert Roberts, Kirun Sankaran, Sophia Sklaviadis, Nicholas Smyth, Hannah Tierney, Patrick Todd, Mark Thomson, Evan Thompson, Candace Vogler, the Centre for Moral and Political Philosophy at the Hebrew University, and Princeton University’s Social Philosophy Workshop. Lastly, and in warm anticipation, I thank the Polonsky Academy at the Van Leer Jerusalem Institute. Daniel J. Telech, Berlin, 2018 iii ABSTRACT It is a commonplace that blameworthy agents deserve blame, and praiseworthy agents deserve praise. But while blame has in recent years received considerable and often illuminating philosophical discussion (e.g. Bell 2013; Coates and Tognazzini 2013; Hieronymi 2004; Mason 2011; McKenna 2012; Pickard 2014; Scanlon 2008; Sher 2008; Smith 2007; Talbert 2012; Wallace 1994, 2011; Wolf 2011), the nature and norms of praise remain relatively unanalyzed. Since the publication of Peter Strawson’s highly influential essay “Freedom and Resentment” (1962), philosophers have increasingly understood moral responsibility in terms of our susceptibility to a range of moral emotions (or “reactive attitudes”) in response to expressions of good and ill will. The Strawsonian, moral psychological, approach to moral responsibility owes part of its appeal to its ability to captures the valence and interpersonal significance of the forms of assessment characteristic of our responsibility responses. But while Strawson himself includes blaming and praising emotions among the reactive attitudes, subsequent philosophical work in this area has concentrated overwhelmingly on blame. Our philosophical vocabulary of praise is impoverished. (But this is not because we fail to respond positively to praiseworthy actions. Nor do we fail to recognize the importance of so responding. The popular saying, ‘give credit where credit is due’ is an injunction to just this.) This omission matters in part because blameworthiness and praiseworthiness are opposed modes of moral iv responsibility—i.e. they are taken to be two—often the two— ways of being morally responsible.1 A negative effect of the disproportionate attention dedicated to blame is that philosophers have imported to their conceptions of moral responsibility in general features that are in fact specific to blame(-worthiness). Resultantly, we not only lack an account of the nature and norms of praise; philosophical work on our responsibility practices displays a narrow, quasi-legalistic, moral orientation, one in which the concepts of normative demand, right-violation, and sanction reign supreme. If, however, we seek to understand what it is to be, and to respond to, a full range of responsible agents, it is incumbent upon us to enrich our vocabulary of praise. My dissertation takes a step in this direction. In chapter 1, I offer a novel account of gratitude and on its basis argue that the significance of benevolence is limited in several ways that have not been duly appreciated by pure quality of will theorists of moral responsibility—i.e. those who think that quality of will is all that matters in assessing an agent’s moral responsibility—and especially those quality of will theorists who take the reactive attitudes to comprise our responsibility 1 This is not a claim merely about recent scholarship about moral responsibility. The idea that expressions of our agency may be assessable as warranting blame or praise—where these are understood as contraries— has featured in philosophical thought concerning agency and ethics since at least the 4th century BC. In the Eudemian Ethics, Aristotle (2.1223a) writes that “since goodness and badness and the actions that spring from them are in some cases praiseworthy and in other cases blameworthy (for praise and blame are not given to things that we possess from necessity or fortune or nature but to things of which we ourselves are the cause, since for things of which another person is the cause, that person has the blame and the praise), it is clear that both goodness and badness have to do with things where a man is himself the cause and origin of his actions.” Epicurus similarly writes: “...some things happen of necessity, others by chance, others through our own agency...necessity destroys responsibility and chance is uncertain; whereas our own actions are autonomous, and it is to them that praise and blame naturally attach.” (Letter to Menoeceus, §133) v responses, i.e. Strawsonians. The claim that I defend most extensively in that chapter is that gratitude is susceptible to retroactive feedback, according to which the (unforeseen and unintended) consequences of the benefactor’s manifestation of quality of will can give the beneficiary reason to be more grateful to their benefactor than they were for the immediately willed benefit, despite the fact that the benefactor’s degree of benevolence is recognized as remaining diachronically stable. If this “gratitude-feedback thesis” is accepted, in those cases where gratitude constitutes a form of moral praise, as Strawsonians maintain it sometimes does, it will be a matter of luck in consequences whether an agent’s action garners her more or less praise. Another way to put this is to say that the moral worth of an action, its praiseworthiness, may be vulnerable to resultant moral luck (Nagel 1979; Williams 1981). In chapter 2, I provide an analysis of the nature of pride that overcomes the shortcomings of the restrictive approach to pride, on the one hand, and the disjunctive approach, on the other. On the restrictive approach, pride involves viewing an object as expressive of one’s agency and as something for which one is thereby morally responsible. On this view, to be proud of one’s naturally good memory is either to misrepresent one’s memory as a product of one’s agency, or to misidentify one’s happiness that one has a good memory. On the disjunctive view, by contrast, there are really two distinct emotions called “pride”: a moral emotion and a non-moral one. Although the disjunctive view accommodates pride for traits and other non-actions, it fails to explain the sense we have that there is unity to our range of pride emotions. A capacious and unified view of pride’s objects is available, and through its outline and defense I shed light on the relationship vi between agency and practical identity, one reflecting that we are, even as agents, more than what we do. In chapter 3 I argue that interpersonal praise cannot be understood in terms of deontic concepts like “moral demand”, and that the assumption that it can be so understood—which I call the demand prejudice— has a stronghold largely owing to the kind of dominance that “accountability” views of responsibility have enjoyed. I propose a novel axiological conception of responsibility in the estimability sense. Estimability characterizes our aspirational stance of holding agents up to interpersonal ideals. It is in light of this latter stance, which I characterize as a broad disposition of “normative hope”, that our praise of others is fruitfully understood. I then provide a way of unifying accountability and estimability by construing both as forms of responsibility in the deserved moral address sense. On this picture, accountability blame and estimability praise are both paradigmatically expressed through moral address (demand and affirmation, respectively), which forms of address characteristically impact their targets’ interests. In chapter 4, I challenge the assumption that blame is unique in being governed by norms of “standing”, like the non-hypocrisy condition. I first motivate a shift in attention from the target of praise to the person doing the praising, i.e. the praiser, by introducing two relatively uncontroversial norms governing the praise of candidate praisers: an epistemic condition and a right-relationship condition. I then make a case for the existence and importance of norms of standing to praise.
Recommended publications
  • August 26, 2014 (Series 29: 1) D.W
    August 26, 2014 (Series 29: 1) D.W. Griffith, BROKEN BLOSSOMS, OR THE YELLOW MAN AND THE GIRL (1919, 90 minutes) Directed, written and produced by D.W. Griffith Based on a story by Thomas Burke Cinematography by G.W. Bitzer Film Editing by James Smith Lillian Gish ... Lucy - The Girl Richard Barthelmess ... The Yellow Man Donald Crisp ... Battling Burrows D.W. Griffith (director) (b. David Llewelyn Wark Griffith, January 22, 1875 in LaGrange, Kentucky—d. July 23, 1948 (age 73) in Hollywood, Los Angeles, California) won an Honorary Academy Award in 1936. He has 520 director credits, the first of which was a short, The Adventures of Dollie, in 1908, and the last of which was The Struggle in 1931. Some of his other films are 1930 Abraham Lincoln, 1929 Lady of the Pavements, 1928 The Battle of the Sexes, 1928 Drums of Love, 1926 The Sorrows of Satan, 1925 That Royle Girl, 1925 Sally of the Sawdust, 1924 Darkened Vales (Short), 1911 The Squaw's Love (Short), 1911 Isn't Life Wonderful, 1924 America, 1923 The White Rose, 1921 Bobby, the Coward (Short), 1911 The Primal Call (Short), 1911 Orphans of the Storm, 1920 Way Down East, 1920 The Love Enoch Arden: Part II (Short), and 1911 Enoch Arden: Part I Flower, 1920 The Idol Dancer, 1919 The Greatest Question, (Short). 1919 Scarlet Days, 1919 The Mother and the Law, 1919 The Fall In 1908, his first year as a director, he did 49 films, of Babylon, 1919 Broken Blossoms or The Yellow Man and the some of which were 1908 The Feud and the Turkey (Short), 1908 Girl, 1918 The Greatest Thing in Life, 1918 Hearts of the World, A Woman's Way (Short), 1908 The Ingrate (Short), 1908 The 1916 Intolerance: Love's Struggle Throughout the Ages, 1915 Taming of the Shrew (Short), 1908 The Call of the Wild (Short), The Birth of a Nation, 1914 The Escape, 1914 Home, Sweet 1908 Romance of a Jewess (Short), 1908 The Planter's Wife Home, 1914 The Massacre (Short), 1913 The Mistake (Short), (Short), 1908 The Vaquero's Vow (Short), 1908 Ingomar, the and 1912 Grannie.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrastivism Surveyed
    Contrastivism Surveyed (Forthcoming in Nous) Jonathan Schaffer Joshua Knobe ANU-RSSS Yale University Suppose that Ann says, “Keith knows that the bank will be open tomorrow.” Her audience may well agree. Her knowledge ascription may seem true. But now suppose that Ben—in a different context—also says “Keith knows that the bank will be open tomorrow.” His audience may well disagree. His knowledge ascription may seem false. Indeed, a number of philosophers have claimed that people’s intuitions about knowledge ascriptions are context sensitive, in the sense that the very same knowledge ascription can seem true in one conversational context but false in another. This purported fact about people’s intuitions serves as one of the main pieces of evidence for epistemic contextualism, which is (roughly speaking) the view that the truth conditions of a knowledge attribution can differ from one conversational context to another. Opponents of contextualism have replied by trying to explain these purported intuitions in other ways. For instance, they have proposed that these purported intuitions may be explained via shifts in what is at stake for the subject, pragmatic shifts in what is assertible, or performance shifts in our liability to error. Yet a recent series of empirical studies threatens to undermine this whole debate. These studies presented ordinary people with precisely the sorts of cases that have been discussed in the contextualism literature and gave them an opportunity to say whether they agreed or disagreed with the relevant knowledge attributions. Strikingly, the results suggest that people simply do not have the intuitions they were purported to have.
    [Show full text]
  • THOMAS GODFREY: PROTEGE of WILLIAM SMITH (Part Two)
    THOMAS GODFREY: PROTEGE OF WILLIAM SMITH (Part Two) By ALBERT FRANK GEGENHEIMER The University of Arizona F OR one of his age and lack of educational advantages Godfrey's lperformance was genuinely amazing and testified not only to his innate powers but likewise to the powers of his mentor, William Smith. The poem abounds in mythological and historical ref- erences, all handled in a manner demonstrating familiarity. Its pattern is of course derivative, and many of the lines echo the two sources cited by Evans. This fact in itself proves Godfrey's first-hand acquaintance with these masters. His poem is not, however, a mere imitation of Chaucer with traces of Popean influence. Godfrey had assimilated his sources and out of the fusion of them with his own mind produced a new work of real merit. While in Philadelphia superintending the publication of The Court of Fancy Godfrey kept his eye out for further and more lucrative employment. His chief friend of influence, William Smith, was in Philadelphia for little of the year 1762 before going to England on his mission for the college. Godfrey, . finding nothing offer, that was advantageous, . determined to make another voyage abroad; and, ac- cordingly, procured some small commissions, and went, as a super-cargo, to the Island of New-Providence, where he was for some months, but met with no great en- couragement. From New-Providence, . he sailed, once more, to North-Carolina. 3 0 Smith did not allow his absence from Philadelphia to halt his efforts on behalf of his prot6g6. With him he carried the manu- script of the latter's poem "Victory," which was published, surely at his recommendation, in an English periodical, The Library, :°Thomas Godfrey, Juvenile Poemns, p.
    [Show full text]
  • George Gebhardt Ç”Μå½± ĸ²È¡Œ (Ť§Å…¨)
    George Gebhardt 电影 串行 (大全) The Dishonored https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-dishonored-medal-3823055/actors Medal A Rural Elopement https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/a-rural-elopement-925215/actors The Fascinating https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-fascinating-mrs.-francis-3203424/actors Mrs. Francis Mr. Jones at the https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/mr.-jones-at-the-ball-3327168/actors Ball A Woman's Way https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/a-woman%27s-way-3221137/actors For Love of Gold https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/for-love-of-gold-3400439/actors The Sacrifice https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-sacrifice-3522582/actors The Honor of https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-honor-of-thieves-3521294/actors Thieves The Greaser's https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-greaser%27s-gauntlet-3521123/actors Gauntlet The Tavern https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-tavern-keeper%27s-daughter-1756994/actors Keeper's Daughter The Stolen Jewels https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-stolen-jewels-3231041/actors Love Finds a Way https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/love-finds-a-way-3264157/actors An Awful Moment https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/an-awful-moment-2844877/actors The Unknown https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-unknown-3989786/actors The Fatal Hour https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-fatal-hour-961681/actors The Curtain Pole https://zh.listvote.com/lists/film/movies/the-curtain-pole-1983212/actors
    [Show full text]
  • Contrast and Contrastivism: the Logic of Contrastive Knowledge
    University of Calgary PRISM: University of Calgary's Digital Repository Arts Arts Research & Publications 2010 Contrast and Contrastivism: The Logic of Contrastive Knowledge Scobbie, Taylor http://hdl.handle.net/1880/51000 Thesis Downloaded from PRISM: https://prism.ucalgary.ca Contrast and Contrastivism: The Logic of Contrastive Knowledge Taylor Scobbie - 0 - Table of Contents I. Introduction ........................................................................................................................ - 2 - II. Contrast ............................................................................................................................... - 5 - A. Contrastive Sentences ..................................................................................................... - 5 - B. Knowledge of Contrastive Sentences .............................................................................. - 9 - III. Contrastivism .................................................................................................................... - 11 - A. Historical Context ........................................................................................................... - 11 - B. Contrastivism ................................................................................................................. - 13 - C. Contrastivism and Epistemic Logic ................................................................................ - 22 - D. Compatibility .............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Darrow Case Argument for Defendant by JUDGE O
    The Darrow Case Argument for Defendant BY JUDGE O. W. POWERS of SALT LAKE CITY ' PRESS OF THE F. W. GARDINER CO. SALT LAKE PREFACE. The following pages contain the argument of Judge O. W. Powers, made to the jury in Extra Sessions Department 4, Superior Court, Los Angeles County, California, Judge W. M. Conley of Madera county pre- siding, on behalf of Clarence S Darrow, charged with bribery, in con- nection with the celebrated McNamara murder trial. Judge Powers is the senior member of the law firms of Powers, Marioneaux, Stott & McKinney of Salt Lake City, Utah, and Powers, Marioneaux & Lady, of Los Angeles. Argument of Judge O. W. Powers Wednesday, March 5, 1913; 9 A. M. THE COURT: You may proceed, Judge. MR. POWERS: IF YOUR HONOR PLEASE, AND GENTLEMEN OF THE JURY: May I make a personal reference at the outset of my argument? I want to state that I shall not speak to you exactly as a stranger from a sister state; for before I received the request from my distinguished client to assist in his defense, I had made preparations to come among you and open an office, and help to pay the taxes of your county. There- fore I am here as a resident, as well as a lawyer whose home is in another city; anl I, therefore, can speak to you with less hesitation. I mention this because sometimes that which is said by one who has no interest connected with our own, has not as much weight. OUR FORM OF GOVERNMENT. You are performing a great duty, and I am here to perform a duty, because in the determination of the questions that arise in court, not only must we have the judge and the jury, under our system of gov- ernment, but the defendant in a case may speak for himself and he may have the man of his choice to speak for him.
    [Show full text]
  • BOWLING GREEN STATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY Clo 5 5 6 8 4 5 Ii
    I Vo. THE IMAGE OF THE "WHITE LIBERAL" IN BLACK AMERICAN FICTION AND DRAMA Norma Ramsay Jones A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate School of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY August 1973 BOWLING GREEN STATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY cLo ii 5 5 6 8 4 5 ABSTRACT Literary criticism has examined white American writing to determine whether black characters have received stereotypical treat­ ment, but little notice has been paid to white characters created by black authors. Existing criticism has focused on the frequently appearing White Oppressor stereotype. This study presented the other major white characterization, the White Liberal, "who opposes prevailing standards by relatively less oppressive behavior toward blacks." It was hoped that studying the White Liberal would show whether black writers, free from the hatred and fear entering into creation of the Oppressor stereotype, had learned to create complex, round white characters, thus reflecting artistic growth. It was assumed that the white liberal image in various periods of history would indicate any progress made in race relations. The image of the White Liberal was examined in the black fiction and drama of four periods of black American experience: Protest (1853-1920), Harlem Renaissance (1920-1930), Between "Pride" and "Power" (1930 to the mid-Sixties), Militancy (mid-Sixties to the present). Major liberal characters were analyzed and typed according to motive for liberalism. Dominant character types and modes of artistic treatment were noted. Results of period analyses were then compared. Comparison of white liberal characters’ motivation in histori­ cal context showed that the moral estimate of liberal motivation altered in relation to the amount of oppression blacks experienced in a given era and the extent to which they were dependent upon whites.
    [Show full text]
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • Degaulle Church of Christ
    1 May 26, 2019 CHURCH OF CHRIST 4700 GENERAL DEGAULLE DRIVE NEW ORLEANS, LA 70131 www.DegaulleDriveCOC.com SCHEDULE OF SERVICES John F. Kennedy once stated, “The cost of freedom is always high, but SUNDAY Americans have always paid it.” Morning Bible Class 9:00 AM This statement is true for the Morning Worship 10:00 AM SCOTT CAIN United States from the “shot heard Pew Packers 5:30 PM ‘round the world” near Old North Evening Worship 6:00 PM Bridge at Concord, Massachusetts, to bullets & bombs which MID-WEEK currently threaten the lives of the soldiers serving in the Middle Tuesday Ladies Class 10:00 AM East. As Abraham Lincoln addressed a warring nation from the (September – May) blood-soaked fields of Gettysburg, he declared the resolve, Wednesday Bible Class 7:00 PM “…from these honored dead we take increased devotion to that _____________________ cause for which they gave the last full measure of devotion, that ELDERS we here highly resolve that these dead shall not have died in vain, Wes Arabie 504-858-2881 Howard Goodale 504-319-3572 that this nation under God, ...and that government of the people Steve Tucker 504-812-2617 by the people and for the people shall not perish from the earth.” Woe unto the ingrate who shows a lack of appreciation toward a EVANGELISTS soldier’s ultimate sacrifice; woe unto the ingrate who cowers Scott Cain 504-392-4110 behind the banner of freedom & denigrates the memories of all Wes Arabie 504-858-2881 whose blood serves as the ink in liberty’s ledger.
    [Show full text]
  • Adventuring with Books: a Booklist for Pre-K-Grade 6. the NCTE Booklist
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 311 453 CS 212 097 AUTHOR Jett-Simpson, Mary, Ed. TITLE Adventuring with Books: A Booklist for Pre-K-Grade 6. Ninth Edition. The NCTE Booklist Series. INSTITUTION National Council of Teachers of English, Urbana, Ill. REPORT NO ISBN-0-8141-0078-3 PUB DATE 89 NOTE 570p.; Prepared by the Committee on the Elementary School Booklist of the National Council of Teachers of English. For earlier edition, see ED 264 588. AVAILABLE FROMNational Council of Teachers of English, 1111 Kenyon Rd., Urbana, IL 61801 (Stock No. 00783-3020; $12.95 member, $16.50 nonmember). PUB TYPE Books (010) -- Reference Materials - Bibliographies (131) EDRS PRICE MF02/PC23 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS Annotated Bibliographies; Art; Athletics; Biographies; *Books; *Childress Literature; Elementary Education; Fantasy; Fiction; Nonfiction; Poetry; Preschool Education; *Reading Materials; Recreational Reading; Sciences; Social Studies IDENTIFIERS Historical Fiction; *Trade Books ABSTRACT Intended to provide teachers with a list of recently published books recommended for children, this annotated booklist cites titles of children's trade books selected for their literary and artistic quality. The annotations in the booklist include a critical statement about each book as well as a brief description of the content, and--where appropriate--information about quality and composition of illustrations. Some 1,800 titles are included in this publication; they were selected from approximately 8,000 children's books published in the United States between 1985 and 1989 and are divided into the following categories: (1) books for babies and toddlers, (2) basic concept books, (3) wordless picture books, (4) language and reading, (5) poetry. (6) classics, (7) traditional literature, (8) fantasy,(9) science fiction, (10) contemporary realistic fiction, (11) historical fiction, (12) biography, (13) social studies, (14) science and mathematics, (15) fine arts, (16) crafts and hobbies, (17) sports and games, and (18) holidays.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Contrastivism
    EPISTEMIC CONTRASTIVISM (penultimate version of an entry for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2017) Peter Baumann Contrastivism about knowledge is the view that one does not just know some proposition. It is more adequate to say that one knows something rather than something else: I know that I am looking at a tree rather than a bush but I do not know that I am looking at a tree rather than a cleverly done tree imitation. Knowledge is a three-place relation between a subject, a proposition and a contrast set of propositions. There are several advantages of a contrastivist view but also certain problems with it. 1. Contrastivism 2. Pro Contrastivism 3. Contra Contrastivism 1. Contrastivism According to an orthodox view, knowledge is a binary relation between a subject and a proposition. Contrastivism about knowledge (or “contrastivism”) is the view that 2 knowledge is rather a ternary relation between a subject, a (true) target proposition and a (false) contrast proposition (or a set of contrast propositions) which is incompatible (but cf. Rourke 2013, sec.2) with the target proposition. The form of a knowledge-attributing sentence is “S knows that p, rather than q” rather than “S knows that p” (see Sinnott-Armstrong 2004 and 2008, Schaffer 2004a, 2005, 2007a, 2007b, 2008, Karjalainen and Morton 2003, Morton 2013; see also Morton 2011 and Schaffer 2012a). To say, for instance, that Jean knows that there is a dog in front of her, is elliptical and short for the claim that Jean knows that there is a dog in front of her rather than, say, a cat.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Contextualism and Its Problems: a Philosophical Critique
    EPISTEMIC CONTEXTUALISM AND ITS PROBLEMS EPISTEMIC CONTEXTUALISM AND ITS PROBLEMS: A PHILOSOPHICAL CRITIQUE By QILIN LI, B. A., M. A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy McMaster University © Copyright by Qilin Li, October 2012 DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY (2012) (Philosophy) McMaster University Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Epistemic Contextualism and Its Problems: A Philosophical Critique AUTHOR: Qilin Li, B.A. (Peking University), M.A. (Peking University) SUPERVISOR: Professor Nicholas Griffin NUMBER OF PAGES: vi, 234 ii ABSTRACT The purpose of this dissertation is to argue that epistemic contextualism, which proposes that the word ‘know’ is a context-sensitive term, is seriously deficient and therefore indefensible. Since epistemic contextualists claim that their semantic theory of ‘know’ contributes not only to a linguistic model of knowledge ascription but also to a unified solution to some important puzzles in epistemology, I divide my thesis into two basic parts. In the first part (i.e., Chapters 2 and 3), I argue that the proponents of both binary and ternary accounts of the supposed context-sensitivity of ‘know’ fail to provide a reasonable linguistic model of knowledge ascription. My argument in Chapter 1 indicates that ‘know’ cannot be treated as a binary context-sensitive term that is similar to paradigmatic indexical terms or gradable adjectives. Chapter 2 takes contrastivism as a representation of the ternary account of the supposed context-sensitivity of ‘know’ and argues that this theory is in an even worse position because it even fails to capture the supposed phenomena of the context-sensitivity of knowledge ascription.
    [Show full text]