The Likelihood Principle (Second Edition)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Likelihood Principle (Second Edition) Institute of Mathematical Statistics LECTURE NOTES-MONOGRAPH SERIES The Likelihood Principle (Second Edition) James O. Berger Purdue University Robert L. Wolpert Duke University THE LIKELIHOOD PRINCIPLE: A REVIEW, GENERALIZATIONS, AND STATISTICAL IMPLICATIONS SECOND EDITION Institute of Mathematical Statistics LECTURE NOTES-MONOGRAPH SERIES Shanti S. Gupta, Series Editor Volume 6 The Likelihood Principle (Second Edition) James O. Berger Purdue University Robert L. Wolpert Duke University Institute of Mathematical Statistics Hayward, California Institute of Mathematical Statistics Lecture Notes-Monograph Series Series Editor, Shanti S. Gupta, Purdue University The production of the IMS Lecture Notes-Monograph Series is managed by the IMS Business Office: Nicholas P. Jewell, IMS Treasurer, and Jose L. Gonzalez, IMS Business Manager. Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 88-81456 International Standard Book Number 0-940600-13-7 Copyright © 1988 Institute of Mathematical Statistics All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America To my parents, Orvis and Thelma James Berger To my wife, Ruta Robert Wolpert PREFACE This monograph began with research designed to provide a generali- zation of the Likelihood Principle (LP) to quite arbitrary statistical situations. The purpose of seeking such a generalization was to partially answer certain criticisms that had been levied against the LP, criticisms which seemed to prevent many statisticians from seriously considering the LP and its implications. The research effort seemed worthwhile because of the simplicity, central importance, and far reaching implications of the LP. Background reading for the research revealed a wider than expected range of published criticisms of the LP. In an attempt to be complete and address all such criticisms, the research paper expanded considerably. Eventually it seemed sensible to enlarge the paper to a monograph. This also allowed for discussion of conditioning ideas in general and for a review of the implications of the LP. It was decided, however, to stop short of a general review of conditional methods in statistics. In particular, the monograph does not discuss the many likelihood based statistical methodologies that have been developed, although references to these methodologies will be given. This limitation was, in part, because such an endeavor would be far too ambitious, and, in part, because we feel (and indeed argue in Chapter 5) that Bayesian implementation of the LP is the correct conditional methodology. The mathematical level of the monograph is, for the most part, kept at a nontechnical level. The main exception is the generalization of the LP in Section 3.4, which is (necessarily) presented at a measure-theoretic level, but can be skipped with no loss in continuity. Also, the monograph vii viii PREFACE presupposes no familiarity with conditioning concepts. Indeed Chapter 2 provides an elementary review of conditioning, with many examples. This second edition was produced under the rather severe constraint that the original manuscript, used for photo-offset printing, was inadvertantly destroyed; only the photos were kept. Thus changes could only be made by retyping entire pages or inserting new pages. A list of corrections that were too minor to justify the retyping of an entire page is given at the end of the monograph. Inserted pages received decimal page numbers: e.g. 74.1, 74.2. A list of additional references was added, and new discussions were kindly contri- buted by M. J. Bayarri and M. H. DeGroot, Bruce Hill, and Lucien Le Cam. Substantial changes or additions were made in Sections 3.1, 3.5, 4.2.1, 4.4, and 4.5. The changes in Section 4.4 correct a glaring oversight in the first edition: the failure to emphasize the misleading conclusions that can result from violation of the Likelihood Principle in significance testing of a precise hypothesis. Another very weak part of the first edition was Section 3.5, which discussed prediction, design, and nuisance parameters. The new material incorporates recent substantive insights from the literature. Numerous other minor changes and literature updatings were made throughout the monograph. We did not attempt complete coverage of recent lit- erature, however. We are grateful to a number of people for valuable discussions on this subject and/or for comments and suggestions on original drafts or the first edition of the monograph. In particular, we would like to thank George Barnard, M. J. Bayarri, Mark Berliner, Lawrence Brown, George Casella, Morris DeGroot, J. L. Foulley, Leon Gleser, Prem Goel, Clyde Hardin, Bruce Hill, Jiunn Hwang, Rajeev Karandikar, Lucien Le Cam, Ker-Chau Li, Dennis Lindley, George McCabe, Georges Monette, John Pratt, Don Rubin, Herman Rubin, Myra Samuels, Steve Samuels, and Tom Sellke. We are especially grateful to M. J. Bayarri and M. H. DeGroot for an exceptionally complete and insightful set of corrections and comments on the first edition. We are also grateful to Shanti Gupta for the encouragement to turn the material into a monograph. PREFACE ix Thanks are also due to the Alfred P. Sloan Foundation, the National Science Foundation (Grants MCS-7801737, MCS-8101670A1, and DMS-8702620), and the Center for Stochatic Processes at the University of North Carolina for support of the research in the monograph. Finally, we are extremely grateful to Norma Lucas, Teena Chase, and Betty Gick for excellent typing of the manuscript. March, 1988 JAMES 0. BERGER Purdue University, West Lafayette ROBERT WOLPERT Duke University, Durham TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER 2. CONDITIONING 5 2.1. Simple Examples 5 2.2. Relevant Subsets 11 2.3. Ancillarity 13 2.4. Conditional Frequentist Procedures 14 2.4.1. Conditional Confidence 14 2.4.2. Estimated Confidence 16 2.5. Criticisms of Partial Conditioning 16 CHAPTER 3. THE LIKELIHOOD PRINCIPLE AND GENERALIZATIONS . 19 3.1. Introduction 19 3.2. History of the Likelihood Principle 22 3.3. Birnbaum's Development - the Discrete Case 24 3.3.1. EvidenceΛ Conditionally, and Sufficiency 24 3.3.2. Axiomatic Development 26 3.4. Generalizations Beyond the Discrete Case 28 3.4.1. Difficulties in the Nondiscrete Case 29 3.4.2. Evidencej Conditionality> and Sufficiency 31 3.4.3. The Relative Likelihood Principle 32 3.5. Prediction, Design, Nuisance Parameters, and the LP 36 3.5.1. Introduction 36 3.5.2. Unobserved Variables: Prediction and Design 37 3.5.3. Nuisance Variables and Parameters 41 x TABLE OF CONTENTS xi 3.6. Criticisms of Birnbaum's Axiomatic Development 42 3.6.1. The Model Assumption 43 3.6.2. The Evidence Assumption 45 3.6.3. The Weak Conditionality Principle 45 3.6.4. The Sufficiency Principle 46 3.7. Violation of the Likelihood Principle: Inadmissibility and Incoherency 50 3.7.1. Introduction 50 3.7.2. Decision Theoretic Evaluation 52 3.7.3. Betting Evaluation 59 CHAPTER 4. CONSEQUENCES AND CRITICISMS OF THE LIKELIHOOD PRINCIPLE AND THE RELATIVE LIKELIHOOD PRINCIPLE 65 4.1. Incompatibility with Frequentist Concepts 65 4.1.1. Introduction 65 4.1.2. Objectivity 67 4.1.3. Procedures for Nonspecialists 68 4.1.4. Repeatability 70 4.1.5. The Confidence Principle 71 4.2. The Irrelevance of Stopping Rules 74 4.2.1. Introduction 74 4.2.2. The (Discrete) Stopping Rule Principle 75 4.3.2. Positive Implications 77 4.2.4. Criticisms 80 4.2.5. Stopping Rules and Inadmissibility 83 4.2.6. The General Stopping Rule Principle 86 4.2.7. Informative Stopping Rules 88 4.3. The Irrelevance of Censoring Mechanisms 4.3.1. Introduction 90 4.3.2. Fixed Censoring and Equivalent Censoring Mechanisms ... 92 4.3.3. Random Censoring 95 4.3.4. Informative Censoring 103 xϋ TABLE OF CONTENTS 4.4. Significance Testing 104 4.4.1. Conflict with the Likelihood Principle 104 4.4.2. Averaging Over "More Extreme" Observations 105 4.4.3. Testing a Single Null Model 109 4.4.4. Conclusions 109.3 4.5. Randomization Analysis 110 4.5.1. Introduction 110 4.5.2. Finite Population Sampling 112 4.5.3. Randomization Tests 117 CHAPTER 5. IMPLEMENTATION OF THE LIKELIHOOD PRINCIPLE 121 5.1. Introduction 121 5.2. Non-Bayesian Likelihood Methods 122 5.3. Arguments for Bayesian Implementation 124 5.3.1. General Considerations 124 5.3.2. The Fraser-Monette-Ng_, Stone, and Stein Examples . 127 5.4. Robust Bayesian Analysis 136 5.5. Conclusions 141 REFERENCES 143 ADDITIONAL OR UPDATED REFERENCES 160 DISCUSSION BY M. J. BAYARRI AND M. H. DEGROOT 160.3 DISCUSSION BY BRUCE HILL 161 DISCUSSION BY DAVID LANE 175 DISCUSSION BY LUCIEN LE CAM 182 REPLY TO THE DISCUSSION 186 ADDITIONAL REFERENCES IN THE DISCUSSION 198 INDEX OF EXAMPLES 200 AUTHOR INDEX 201 SUBJECT INDEX 204 ERRATA AND CLARIFICATIONS 207 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION Among all prescriptions for statistical behavior, the Likelihood Principle (LP) stands out as the simplest and yet most farreaching. It essen- tially states that all evidence, which is obtained from an experiment, about an unknown quantity θ, is contained in the likelihood function of θ for the given data. The implications of this are profound, since most non-Bayesian approaches to statistics and indeed most standard statistical measures of evidence (such as coverage probability, error probabilities, significance level, frequentist risk, etc.) are then contraindicated. The LP was always implicit in the Bayesian approach to statistics, but its development as a separate statistical principle was due in large part to ideas of R. A. Fisher and G. Barnard (see Section 3.2 for references). It received major notice when Birnbaum (1962a) showed it to be a consequence of the more commonly trusted Sufficiency Principle (that a sufficient statistic summarizes the evidence from an experiment) and Conditionality Principle (that experiments not actually performed should be irrelevant to conclusions). Since then the LP has been extensively debated by statisticians interested in founda- tions, but has been ignored by most statisticians.
Recommended publications
  • The Likelihood Principle
    1 01/28/99 ãMarc Nerlove 1999 Chapter 1: The Likelihood Principle "What has now appeared is that the mathematical concept of probability is ... inadequate to express our mental confidence or diffidence in making ... inferences, and that the mathematical quantity which usually appears to be appropriate for measuring our order of preference among different possible populations does not in fact obey the laws of probability. To distinguish it from probability, I have used the term 'Likelihood' to designate this quantity; since both the words 'likelihood' and 'probability' are loosely used in common speech to cover both kinds of relationship." R. A. Fisher, Statistical Methods for Research Workers, 1925. "What we can find from a sample is the likelihood of any particular value of r [a parameter], if we define the likelihood as a quantity proportional to the probability that, from a particular population having that particular value of r, a sample having the observed value r [a statistic] should be obtained. So defined, probability and likelihood are quantities of an entirely different nature." R. A. Fisher, "On the 'Probable Error' of a Coefficient of Correlation Deduced from a Small Sample," Metron, 1:3-32, 1921. Introduction The likelihood principle as stated by Edwards (1972, p. 30) is that Within the framework of a statistical model, all the information which the data provide concerning the relative merits of two hypotheses is contained in the likelihood ratio of those hypotheses on the data. ...For a continuum of hypotheses, this principle
    [Show full text]
  • Statistical Theory
    Statistical Theory Prof. Gesine Reinert November 23, 2009 Aim: To review and extend the main ideas in Statistical Inference, both from a frequentist viewpoint and from a Bayesian viewpoint. This course serves not only as background to other courses, but also it will provide a basis for developing novel inference methods when faced with a new situation which includes uncertainty. Inference here includes estimating parameters and testing hypotheses. Overview • Part 1: Frequentist Statistics { Chapter 1: Likelihood, sufficiency and ancillarity. The Factoriza- tion Theorem. Exponential family models. { Chapter 2: Point estimation. When is an estimator a good estima- tor? Covering bias and variance, information, efficiency. Methods of estimation: Maximum likelihood estimation, nuisance parame- ters and profile likelihood; method of moments estimation. Bias and variance approximations via the delta method. { Chapter 3: Hypothesis testing. Pure significance tests, signifi- cance level. Simple hypotheses, Neyman-Pearson Lemma. Tests for composite hypotheses. Sample size calculation. Uniformly most powerful tests, Wald tests, score tests, generalised likelihood ratio tests. Multiple tests, combining independent tests. { Chapter 4: Interval estimation. Confidence sets and their con- nection with hypothesis tests. Approximate confidence intervals. Prediction sets. { Chapter 5: Asymptotic theory. Consistency. Asymptotic nor- mality of maximum likelihood estimates, score tests. Chi-square approximation for generalised likelihood ratio tests. Likelihood confidence regions. Pseudo-likelihood tests. • Part 2: Bayesian Statistics { Chapter 6: Background. Interpretations of probability; the Bayesian paradigm: prior distribution, posterior distribution, predictive distribution, credible intervals. Nuisance parameters are easy. 1 { Chapter 7: Bayesian models. Sufficiency, exchangeability. De Finetti's Theorem and its intepretation in Bayesian statistics. { Chapter 8: Prior distributions. Conjugate priors.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Relation Between Frequency Inference and Likelihood
    On the Relation between Frequency Inference and Likelihood Donald A. Pierce Radiation Effects Research Foundation 5-2 Hijiyama Park Hiroshima 732, Japan [email protected] 1. Introduction Modern higher-order asymptotic theory for frequency inference, as largely described in Barn- dorff-Nielsen & Cox (1994), is fundamentally likelihood-oriented. This has led to various indica- tions of more unity in frequency and Bayesian inferences than previously recognised, e.g. Sweeting (1987, 1992). A main distinction, the stronger dependence of frequency inference on the sample space—the outcomes not observed—is isolated in a single term of the asymptotic formula for P- values. We capitalise on that to consider from an asymptotic perspective the relation of frequency inferences to the likelihood principle, with results towards a quantification of that as follows. Whereas generally the conformance of frequency inference to the likelihood principle is only to first order, i.e. O(n–1/2), there is at least one major class of applications, likely more, where the confor- mance is to second order, i.e. O(n–1). There the issue is the effect of censoring mechanisms. On a more subtle point, it is often overlooked that there are few, if any, practical settings where exact frequency inferences exist broadly enough to allow precise comparison to the likelihood principle. To the extent that ideal frequency inference may only be defined to second order, there is some- times—perhaps usually—no conflict at all. The strong likelihood principle is that in even totally unrelated experiments, inferences from data yielding the same likelihood function should be the same (the weak one being essentially the sufficiency principle).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Likelihood Principle
    ISyE8843A, Brani Vidakovic Handout 2 1 The Likelihood Principle Likelihood principle concerns foundations of statistical inference and it is often invoked in arguments about correct statistical reasoning. Let f(xjθ) be a conditional distribution for X given the unknown parameter θ. For the observed data, X = x, the function `(θ) = f(xjθ), considered as a function of θ, is called the likelihood function. The name likelihood implies that, given x, the value of θ is more likely to be the true parameter than θ0 if f(xjθ) > f(xjθ0): Likelihood Principle. In the inference about θ, after x is observed, all relevant experimental information is contained in the likelihood function for the observed x. Furthermore, two likelihood functions contain the same information about θ if they are proportional to each other. Remark. The maximum-likelihood estimation does satisfy the likelihood principle. Figure 1: Leonard Jimmie Savage; Born: November 20, 1917, Detroit, Michigan; Died: November 1, 1971, New Haven, Connecticut The following example quoted by Lindley and Phillips (1976) is an argument of Leonard Savage dis- cussed at Purdue Symposium 1962. It shows that the inference can critically depend on the likelihood principle. Example 1: Testing fairness. Suppose we are interested in testing θ, the unknown probability of heads for possibly biased coin. Suppose, H0 : θ = 1=2 v:s: H1 : θ > 1=2: 1 An experiment is conducted and 9 heads and 3 tails are observed. This information is not sufficient to fully specify the model f(xjθ): A rashomonian analysis follows: ² Scenario 1: Number of flips, n = 12 is predetermined.
    [Show full text]
  • Model Selection by Normalized Maximum Likelihood
    Myung, J. I., Navarro, D. J. and Pitt, M. A. (2006). Model selection by normalized maximum likelihood. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 50, 167-179 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jmp.2005.06.008 Model selection by normalized maximum likelihood Jay I. Myunga;c, Danielle J. Navarrob and Mark A. Pitta aDepartment of Psychology Ohio State University bDepartment of Psychology University of Adelaide, Australia cCorresponding Author Abstract The Minimum Description Length (MDL) principle is an information theoretic approach to in- ductive inference that originated in algorithmic coding theory. In this approach, data are viewed as codes to be compressed by the model. From this perspective, models are compared on their ability to compress a data set by extracting useful information in the data apart from random noise. The goal of model selection is to identify the model, from a set of candidate models, that permits the shortest description length (code) of the data. Since Rissanen originally formalized the problem using the crude `two-part code' MDL method in the 1970s, many significant strides have been made, especially in the 1990s, with the culmination of the development of the refined `universal code' MDL method, dubbed Normalized Maximum Likelihood (NML). It represents an elegant solution to the model selection problem. The present paper provides a tutorial review on these latest developments with a special focus on NML. An application example of NML in cognitive modeling is also provided. Keywords: Minimum Description Length, Model Complexity, Inductive Inference, Cognitive Modeling. Preprint submitted to Journal of Mathematical Psychology 13 August 2019 To select among competing models of a psychological process, one must decide which criterion to use to evaluate the models, and then make the best inference as to which model is preferable.
    [Show full text]
  • P Values, Hypothesis Testing, and Model Selection: It’S De´Ja` Vu All Over Again1
    FORUM P values, hypothesis testing, and model selection: it’s de´ja` vu all over again1 It was six men of Indostan To learning much inclined, Who went to see the Elephant (Though all of them were blind), That each by observation Might satisfy his mind. ... And so these men of Indostan Disputed loud and long, Each in his own opinion Exceeding stiff and strong, Though each was partly in the right, And all were in the wrong! So, oft in theologic wars The disputants, I ween, Rail on in utter ignorance Of what each other mean, And prate about an Elephant Not one of them has seen! —From The Blind Men and the Elephant: A Hindoo Fable, by John Godfrey Saxe (1872) Even if you didn’t immediately skip over this page (or the entire Forum in this issue of Ecology), you may still be asking yourself, ‘‘Haven’t I seen this before? Do we really need another Forum on P values, hypothesis testing, and model selection?’’ So please bear with us; this elephant is still in the room. We thank Paul Murtaugh for the reminder and the invited commentators for their varying perspectives on the current shape of statistical testing and inference in ecology. Those of us who went through graduate school in the 1970s, 1980s, and 1990s remember attempting to coax another 0.001 out of SAS’s P ¼ 0.051 output (maybe if I just rounded to two decimal places ...), raising a toast to P ¼ 0.0499 (and the invention of floating point processors), or desperately searching the back pages of Sokal and Rohlf for a different test that would cross the finish line and satisfy our dissertation committee.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Likelihood 2 Maximum Likelihood Estimators 3 Properties of the Maximum Likelihood Estimators
    University of Colorado-Boulder Department of Applied Mathematics Prof. Vanja Dukic Review: Likelihood 1 Likelihood Consider a set of iid random variables X = fXig; i = 1; :::; N that come from some probability model M = ff(x; θ); θ 2 Θg where f(x; θ) is the probability density of each Xi and θ is an unknown but fixed parameter from some space Θ ⊆ <d. (Note: this would be a typical frequentist setting.) The likelihood function (Fisher, 1925, 1934) is defined as: N Y L(θ j X~ ) = f(Xi; θ); (1) i=1 or any other function of θ proportional to (1) (it does not need be normalized). More generally, the likelihood ~ N ~ function is any function proportional to the joint density of the sample, X = fXigi=1, denoted as f(X; θ). Note you don't need to assume independence, nor identically distributed variables in the sample. The likelihood function is sacred to most statisticians. Bayesians use it jointly with the prior distribution π(θ) to derive the posterior distribution π(θ j X) and draw all their inference based on that posterior. Frequentists may derive their estimates directly from the likelihood function using maximum likelihood estimation (MLE). We say that a parameter is identifiable if for any two θ 6= θ∗ we have L(θ j X~ ) 6= L(θ∗ j X~ ) 2 Maximum likelihood estimators One way of identifying (estimating) parameters is via the maximum likelihood estimators. Maximizing the likelihood function (or equivalently, the log likelihood function thanks to the monotonicity of the log transform), with respect to the parameter vector θ, yields the maximum likelihood estimator, denoted as θb.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 2 Estimating Probabilities
    CHAPTER 2 Estimating Probabilities Machine Learning Copyright c 2017. Tom M. Mitchell. All rights reserved. *DRAFT OF January 26, 2018* *PLEASE DO NOT DISTRIBUTE WITHOUT AUTHOR’S PERMISSION* This is a rough draft chapter intended for inclusion in the upcoming second edition of the textbook Machine Learning, T.M. Mitchell, McGraw Hill. You are welcome to use this for educational purposes, but do not duplicate or repost it on the internet. For online copies of this and other materials related to this book, visit the web site www.cs.cmu.edu/∼tom/mlbook.html. Please send suggestions for improvements, or suggested exercises, to [email protected]. Many machine learning methods depend on probabilistic approaches. The reason is simple: when we are interested in learning some target function f : X ! Y, we can more generally learn the probabilistic function P(YjX). By using a probabilistic approach, we can design algorithms that learn func- tions with uncertain outcomes (e.g., predicting tomorrow’s stock price) and that incorporate prior knowledge to guide learning (e.g., a bias that tomor- row’s stock price is likely to be similar to today’s price). This chapter de- scribes joint probability distributions over many variables, and shows how they can be used to calculate a target P(YjX). It also considers the problem of learning, or estimating, probability distributions from training data, pre- senting the two most common approaches: maximum likelihood estimation and maximum a posteriori estimation. 1 Joint Probability Distributions The key to building probabilistic models is to define a set of random variables, and to consider the joint probability distribution over them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Likelihood Function
    Introduction to Likelihood Statistics Edward L. Robinson* Department of Astronomy and McDonald Observatory University of Texas at Austin 1. The likelihood function. 2. Use of the likelihood function to model data. 3. Comparison to standard frequentist and Bayesean statistics. *Look for: “Data Analysis for Scientists and Engineers” Princeton University Press, Sept 2016. The Likelihood Function Let a probability distribution function for ⇠ have m + 1 • parameters aj f(⇠,a , a , , a )=f(⇠,~a), 0 1 ··· m The joint probability distribution for n samples of ⇠ is f(⇠ ,⇠ , ,⇠ , a , a , , a )=f(⇠~,~a). 1 2 ··· n 0 1 ··· m Now make measurements. For each variable ⇠ there is a measured • i value xi. To obtain the likelihood function L(~x,~a), replace each variable ⇠ with • i the numerical value of the corresponding data point xi: L(~x,~a) f(~x,~a)=f(x , x , , x ,~a). ⌘ 1 2 ··· n In the likelihood function the ~x are known and fixed, while the ~aare the variables. A Simple Example Suppose the probability • distribution for the data is 2 a⇠ f(⇠,a)=a ⇠e− . Measure a single data point. It • turns out to be x = 2. The likelihood function is • 2 2a L(x = 2, a)=2a e− . A Somewhat More Realistic Example Suppose we have n independent data points, each drawn from the same probability distribution 2 a⇠ f(⇠,a)=a ⇠e− . The joint probability distribution is f(⇠~,a)=f(⇠ , a)f(⇠ , a) f(⇠ , a) 1 2 ··· n n 2 a⇠i = a ⇠ie− . Yi=1 The data points are xi. The resulting likelihood function is n 2 axi L(~x, a)= a xie− .
    [Show full text]
  • Likelihood Principle
    Perhaps our standards are too high… • Maybe I am giving you too much food for thought on this one issue • The realization comes after reading a preprint by a >100-strong collaboration, MINOS • In a recent paper [MINOS 2011] they derive 99.7% upper limits for some parameters, using antineutrino interactions. How then to combine with previous upper limits derived with neutrino interactions ? 1 1 1 • They use the following formula: 2 2 2 up up,1 up,2 The horror, the horror. • You should all be able to realize that this cannot be correct! It looks like a poor man’s way to combine two significances for Gaussian distributions, but it does not even work in that simple case. Neyman vs MINOS • To show how wrong one can be with the formula used by MINOS, take the Gaussian measurement of a parameter. Take σ=1 for the Gaussian: this means, for instance, that if the unknown parameter is μ=3, there is then a 68% chance that your measurement x will be in the 2<x<4 interval. Since, however, what you know is your measurement and you want to draw conclusions on the unknown μ, you need to "invert the hypothesis". Let's say you measure x=2 and you want to know what is the maximum value possible for μ, at 95% confidence level. This requires producing a "Neyman construction". You will find that your limit is μ<3.64. • So what if you got twice the measurement x=2, in independent measurements ? Could you then combine the limits as MINOS does ? If you combine two x=2 measurements, each yielding μ1=μ2<3.64 at 95%CL, according to the 2 2 MINOS preprint you might do μcomb=1/sqrt(1/μ1,up + 1/μ2 ) < 2.57.
    [Show full text]
  • P-Values and the Likelihood Principle
    JSM 2016 - Section on Statistical Education p-Values and the Likelihood Principle Andrew Neath∗ Abstract The p-value is widely used for quantifying evidence in a statistical hypothesis testing problem. A major criticism, however, is that the p-value does not satisfy the likelihood principle. In this paper, we show that a p-value assessment of evidence can indeed be defined within the likelihood inference framework. The connection between p-values and likelihood based measures of evidence broaden the use of the p-value and deepen our understanding of statistical hypothesis testing. Key Words: hypothesis testing, statistical evidence, likelihood ratio, Wald statistic 1. Introduction The p-value is a popular tool for statistical inference. Unfortunately, the p-value and its role in hypothesis testing is often misused in drawing scientific conclusions. Concern over the use, and misuse, of what is perhaps the most widely taught statistical practice has led the American Statistical Association to craft a statement on behalf of its members (Wasserstein and Lazar, 2016). For statistical practitioners, a deeper insight into the workings of the p-value is essential for an understanding of statistical hypothesis testing. The purpose of this paper is to highlight the flexibility of the p-value as an assessment of statistical evidence. An alleged disadvantage of the p-value is its isolation from more rigorously defined likelihood based measures of evidence. However, this disconnect can be bridged. In this paper, we present a result establishing a p-value measure of evidence within the likelihood inferential framework. In Section 2, we discuss the general idea of statistical evidence.
    [Show full text]
  • Likelihood: Philosophical Foundations
    Likelihood and probability Properties of likelihood The likelihood principle Likelihood: Philosophical foundations Patrick Breheny August 24 Patrick Breheny University of Iowa Likelihood Theory (BIOS 7110) 1 / 34 Likelihood and probability Definition Properties of likelihood Bayesian and frequentist approaches The likelihood principle Combining likelihoods Introduction • This course is about developing a theoretical understanding of likelihood, the central concept in statistical modeling and inference • Likelihood offers a systematic way of measuring agreement between unknown parameters and observable data; in so doing, it provides a unifying principle that all statisticians can agree is reasonable (which is not to say that it doesn’t have any problems) • This provides two enormous benefits in statistics: ◦ A universal baseline of comparison for methods and estimators ◦ A coherent and versatile method of summarizing and combining evidence of all sources without relying on arbitrary, ad hoc decisions Patrick Breheny University of Iowa Likelihood Theory (BIOS 7110) 2 / 34 Likelihood and probability Definition Properties of likelihood Bayesian and frequentist approaches The likelihood principle Combining likelihoods Likelihood: Definition • Let X denote observable data, and suppose we have a probability model p that relates potential values of X to an unknown parameter θ • Definition: Given observed data X = x, the likelihood function for θ is defined as L(θ|x) = p(x|θ), although I will often just write L(θ) • Note that this is a function of θ,
    [Show full text]