An Improved Approximation to the Poisson-Likelihood Chi-Square

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Improved Approximation to the Poisson-Likelihood Chi-Square Combined Neyman–Pearson Chi-square: An Improved Approximation to the Poisson-likelihood Chi-square Xiangpan Ji∗, Wenqiang Gu, Xin Qian, Hanyu Wei, Chao Zhang∗∗ Physics Department, Brookhaven National Laboratory, Upton, NY, USA Abstract We describe an approximation to the widely-used Poisson-likelihood chi-square using a linear combination of Neyman’s and Pearson’s chi-squares, namely “combined Neyman–Pearson chi- 2 2 square” (χCNP). Through analytical derivations and toy model simulations, we show that χCNP leads to a significantly smaller bias on the best-fit model parameters compared to those using either Neyman’s or Pearson’s chi-square. When the computational cost of using the Poisson-likelihood 2 chi-square is high, χCNP provides a good alternative given its natural connection to the covariance matrix formalism. Keywords: test statistics, Poisson-likelihood chi-square, Neyman’s chi-square, Pearson’s chi-square 1. Introduction In high-energy physics experiments, it is often convenient to bin the data into a histogram with n bins. The number of measured events Mi in each bin typically follows a Poisson distribution with the mean value µi¹θº predicted by a set of model parameters θ = ¹θ1; :::; θN º. The likelihood function of this Poisson histogram can be written as: n − M Ö e µi µ i L¹µ¹θº; Mº = i : (1) M ! i i A maximum-likelihood estimator (MLE) of θ can be constructed by maximizing the likelihood ratio [1, 2] L¹µ¹θº; Mº L¹µ¹θº; Mº λ¹θº = 0 = ; (2) max L¹µ ; Mº L¹M; Mº where the denominator is a model-independent constant that maximizes the likelihood of the data without any restriction on the model1. Maximizing this likelihood ratio is equivalent to minimizing arXiv:1903.07185v3 [physics.data-an] 25 Feb 2020 ∗Corresponding author. Email: [email protected] ∗∗Corresponding author. Email: [email protected] 1While the estimation of model parameters θ does not depend on the denominator of the likelihood ratio, the chi- square test statistic constructed in this way, such as that in Eq. (3), can be used to examine the data-model compatibility with a goodness-of-fit test. Preprint submitted to Nuclear Instruments and Methods A February 26, 2020 the Poisson-likelihood chi-square function [3, 4]: n Õ Mi χ2 = −2 ln λ¹θº = 2 µ ¹θº − M + M ln : (3) Poisson i i i µ ¹θº i=1 i The MLE is commonly used in the high-energy physics, as it is generally an asymptotically unbiased estimator, and has the advantage of being consistent and efficient [5]. At large statistics, the previous Poisson distribution can be approximated by a normal (or 2 Gaussian) distribution with mean µi¹θº and variance σi = µi¹θº. The likelihood then becomes: 2 Ö 1 ¹µi¹θº − Miº L ¹µ¹θº; Mº = exp − : (4) Gauss p 2µ ¹θº i 2πµi¹θº i The Gauss-MLE can be similarly constructed through a likelihood ratio: LGauss¹µ¹θº; Mº λGauss¹θº = 0 ; (5) max LGauss¹µ ; Mº where the denominator is the maximum of LGauss without any restriction on the model, and can 0 be derived by calculating @LGauss/@µi = 0. Maximizing λGauss¹θº is equivalent to minimizing the Gauss-likelihood chi-square function 2 0 2 ! Õ ¹µ ¹θº − M º µ ¹θº ¹µ − Miº χ2 = −2 ln λ ¹θº = i i + ln i − i ; Gauss Gauss µ ¹θº µ0 µ0 i=1 i i i (6) 0 q 2 with µi = 1/4 + Mi − 1/2 : While the Gauss-likelihood chi-square is relatively well-known (see e.g. [6, 7]) 2, interestingly, it is not widely used in high-energy physics experiments. Instead, a direct chi-square test statistic, namely the Pearson’s chi-square, is constructed through: 2 Õ ¹µi¹θº − Miº χ2 = : (7) Pearson µ ¹θº i i 2 2 Comparing with Eq. (6), we see χPearson consists of only the first term in χGauss. These two chi-squares become asymptotically equivalent when Mi is large. 2 In practice, the variance σi is often approximated by the measured value Mi, which is indepen- dent of the model parameters. This leads to another popular chi-square test statistic in high-energy physics experiments, namely the Neyman’s chi-square: 2 Õ ¹µi¹θº − Miº χ2 = : (8) Neyman M i i 2We further provide some relevant formulas for the Gauss-likelihood chi-square in Appendix D. 2 Comparing to the MLE from the Poisson-likelihood chi-square, it is known that the estimator of model parameters constructed from Pearson’s or Neyman’s chi-square leads to biases especially 2 when the large-statistics condition is not met [4, 8, 9]. Despite this shortcoming, both χPearson and 2 χNeyman are commonly used in physics data analysis, partly because of their close connection to the covariance-matrix formalism: 2 T −1 χcov = ¹M − µ¹θºº · V · ¹M − µ¹θºº; (9) where Vij = cov»µi; µj¼ is the covariance matrix of the prediction, and can often be calculated through Monte Carlo methods based on the statistical and systematic uncertainties of the experiment 2 prior to the minimization of χcov. In situations where many nuisance parameters [5] are required in the likelihood function L as in Eq. (1), the covariance matrix format Eq. (9) has a natural advantage of reducing the number of nuisance parameters, thus leads to a faster minimization of the χ2 function. 2 One method to remove the bias of the estimator from χPearson is through an iteration of the 2 weighted least-squares fit, where the variance in one round of χPearson minimization is replaced by the prediction from the best-fit value in the previous round of iteration [10, 11, 12]. Several modified chi-square test statistics have also been proposed in past literatures to mitigate the bias 2 2 issue. For example, χGauss defined in Eq. (6) is a good replacement of χPearson when the number of 2 2 measurements is large. Similarly, χγ as proposed by Mighell [13] is a good alternative to χNeyman 2 2 when the number of measurements is large. Both χGauss and χγ , however, still lead to biases when the number of measurements is small. Redin proposed a solution by including a cubic term in 2 2 2 χNeyman and χPearson [14], or by reporting a weighted average of fitting results from χNeyman and 2 χPearson [15]. In this paper, we propose a new method through the construction of a chi-square test statistic 2 (χCNP) with a linear combination of Neyman’s and Pearson’s chi-squares. As an improved approximation to the Poisson-likelihood chi-square with respect to either Neyman’s or Pearson’s 2 chi-square, the χCNP significantly reduces the bias while keeping the advantage of the covariance 2 matrix formalism. This paper is organized as follows. The construction of χCNP and its covariance matrix format is described in Sec. 2. Three toy examples are presented in Sec. 3 to illustrate the 2 features and advantages of χCNP. Finally, we summarize the recommended usage in data analysis of counting experiments in Sec. 4. 2 2. Combined Neyman–Pearson Chi-square (χCNP) The bias in the estimator of model parameters θ using Neyman’s or Pearson’s chi-square can be traced back to the different χ2 definitions in approximating the Poisson-likelihood chi-square. To illustrate this, we start with a simple example. A set of n independent counting experiments were performed to measure a common expected value µ. Each experiment measured Mi events. 3 The three chi-square functions in this case are 3: n Õ M χ2 = 2 µ − M + M ln i ; Poisson i i µ i=1 n 2 Õ ¹µ − Miº χ2 = ; (10) Neyman M i i n Õ ¹µ − M º2 χ2 = i : Pearson µ i µ^ (the estimator of µ) can be calculated through the minimization of Eq. (10): @ χ2/@µ = 0. We obtain: s Ín Ín 2 Mi n i=1 M µ^ = i=1 ; µ^ = ; µ^ = i : (11) Poisson n Neyman Ín 1 Pearson n i=1 Mi Given Eq. (11), it is straightforward to show that µ^Neyman ≤ µ^Poisson ≤ µ^Pearson, where the equal sign is only established when all values of Mi are the same. Since µ^Poisson is unbiased in this simple example, we see that µ^Pearson and µ^Neyman are biased in the opposite directions. We further examine the difference in chi-square values. Assuming that Mi and µ are reasonably 2 large so that Mi is close to µ, a Taylor expansion of χPoisson yields: n Õ µ − M χ2 = 2 µ − M − M ln 1 + i Poisson i i M i=1 i n " # (12) Õ ¹µ − M º2 2 ¹µ − M º3 ¹µ − M º4 ≈ i − i + O¹ i º : M 3 2 3 i=1 i Mi Mi From Eq. (12), it is straightforward to deduce: n Õ 2 ¹µ − M º3 χ2 − χ2 ≈ − i ; Poisson Neyman 3 2 i Mi n (13) Õ 1 ¹µ − M º3 χ2 − χ2 ≈ i : Poisson Pearson 3 2 i Mi Naturally, we can define a new chi-square function as a linear combination of Neyman’s and Pearson’s chi-squares: n 2 1 Õ ¹µ − Miº χ2 ≡ χ2 + 2χ2 = ; (14) CNP 3 Neyman Pearson 3/( 1 + 2 º i=1 Mi µ 3 The treatment for bins where Mi = 0 is described in Appendix A. 4 4 2 ¹µ−Miº 2 2 which is approximately equal to χPoisson up to O¹ 3 º, better than either χNeyman or χPearson Mi 2 alone. In this example, the estimator µ^ from minimizing χCNP can be derived as: v tÍn M2 q µ^ = 3 i=1 i = 3 µ^2 · µ^ ; CNP Ín 1 Pearson Neyman (15) i=1 Mi which is the geometric mean of two µ^Pearson and one µ^Neyman.
Recommended publications
  • The Likelihood Principle
    1 01/28/99 ãMarc Nerlove 1999 Chapter 1: The Likelihood Principle "What has now appeared is that the mathematical concept of probability is ... inadequate to express our mental confidence or diffidence in making ... inferences, and that the mathematical quantity which usually appears to be appropriate for measuring our order of preference among different possible populations does not in fact obey the laws of probability. To distinguish it from probability, I have used the term 'Likelihood' to designate this quantity; since both the words 'likelihood' and 'probability' are loosely used in common speech to cover both kinds of relationship." R. A. Fisher, Statistical Methods for Research Workers, 1925. "What we can find from a sample is the likelihood of any particular value of r [a parameter], if we define the likelihood as a quantity proportional to the probability that, from a particular population having that particular value of r, a sample having the observed value r [a statistic] should be obtained. So defined, probability and likelihood are quantities of an entirely different nature." R. A. Fisher, "On the 'Probable Error' of a Coefficient of Correlation Deduced from a Small Sample," Metron, 1:3-32, 1921. Introduction The likelihood principle as stated by Edwards (1972, p. 30) is that Within the framework of a statistical model, all the information which the data provide concerning the relative merits of two hypotheses is contained in the likelihood ratio of those hypotheses on the data. ...For a continuum of hypotheses, this principle
    [Show full text]
  • Statistical Theory
    Statistical Theory Prof. Gesine Reinert November 23, 2009 Aim: To review and extend the main ideas in Statistical Inference, both from a frequentist viewpoint and from a Bayesian viewpoint. This course serves not only as background to other courses, but also it will provide a basis for developing novel inference methods when faced with a new situation which includes uncertainty. Inference here includes estimating parameters and testing hypotheses. Overview • Part 1: Frequentist Statistics { Chapter 1: Likelihood, sufficiency and ancillarity. The Factoriza- tion Theorem. Exponential family models. { Chapter 2: Point estimation. When is an estimator a good estima- tor? Covering bias and variance, information, efficiency. Methods of estimation: Maximum likelihood estimation, nuisance parame- ters and profile likelihood; method of moments estimation. Bias and variance approximations via the delta method. { Chapter 3: Hypothesis testing. Pure significance tests, signifi- cance level. Simple hypotheses, Neyman-Pearson Lemma. Tests for composite hypotheses. Sample size calculation. Uniformly most powerful tests, Wald tests, score tests, generalised likelihood ratio tests. Multiple tests, combining independent tests. { Chapter 4: Interval estimation. Confidence sets and their con- nection with hypothesis tests. Approximate confidence intervals. Prediction sets. { Chapter 5: Asymptotic theory. Consistency. Asymptotic nor- mality of maximum likelihood estimates, score tests. Chi-square approximation for generalised likelihood ratio tests. Likelihood confidence regions. Pseudo-likelihood tests. • Part 2: Bayesian Statistics { Chapter 6: Background. Interpretations of probability; the Bayesian paradigm: prior distribution, posterior distribution, predictive distribution, credible intervals. Nuisance parameters are easy. 1 { Chapter 7: Bayesian models. Sufficiency, exchangeability. De Finetti's Theorem and its intepretation in Bayesian statistics. { Chapter 8: Prior distributions. Conjugate priors.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Relation Between Frequency Inference and Likelihood
    On the Relation between Frequency Inference and Likelihood Donald A. Pierce Radiation Effects Research Foundation 5-2 Hijiyama Park Hiroshima 732, Japan [email protected] 1. Introduction Modern higher-order asymptotic theory for frequency inference, as largely described in Barn- dorff-Nielsen & Cox (1994), is fundamentally likelihood-oriented. This has led to various indica- tions of more unity in frequency and Bayesian inferences than previously recognised, e.g. Sweeting (1987, 1992). A main distinction, the stronger dependence of frequency inference on the sample space—the outcomes not observed—is isolated in a single term of the asymptotic formula for P- values. We capitalise on that to consider from an asymptotic perspective the relation of frequency inferences to the likelihood principle, with results towards a quantification of that as follows. Whereas generally the conformance of frequency inference to the likelihood principle is only to first order, i.e. O(n–1/2), there is at least one major class of applications, likely more, where the confor- mance is to second order, i.e. O(n–1). There the issue is the effect of censoring mechanisms. On a more subtle point, it is often overlooked that there are few, if any, practical settings where exact frequency inferences exist broadly enough to allow precise comparison to the likelihood principle. To the extent that ideal frequency inference may only be defined to second order, there is some- times—perhaps usually—no conflict at all. The strong likelihood principle is that in even totally unrelated experiments, inferences from data yielding the same likelihood function should be the same (the weak one being essentially the sufficiency principle).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Likelihood Principle
    ISyE8843A, Brani Vidakovic Handout 2 1 The Likelihood Principle Likelihood principle concerns foundations of statistical inference and it is often invoked in arguments about correct statistical reasoning. Let f(xjθ) be a conditional distribution for X given the unknown parameter θ. For the observed data, X = x, the function `(θ) = f(xjθ), considered as a function of θ, is called the likelihood function. The name likelihood implies that, given x, the value of θ is more likely to be the true parameter than θ0 if f(xjθ) > f(xjθ0): Likelihood Principle. In the inference about θ, after x is observed, all relevant experimental information is contained in the likelihood function for the observed x. Furthermore, two likelihood functions contain the same information about θ if they are proportional to each other. Remark. The maximum-likelihood estimation does satisfy the likelihood principle. Figure 1: Leonard Jimmie Savage; Born: November 20, 1917, Detroit, Michigan; Died: November 1, 1971, New Haven, Connecticut The following example quoted by Lindley and Phillips (1976) is an argument of Leonard Savage dis- cussed at Purdue Symposium 1962. It shows that the inference can critically depend on the likelihood principle. Example 1: Testing fairness. Suppose we are interested in testing θ, the unknown probability of heads for possibly biased coin. Suppose, H0 : θ = 1=2 v:s: H1 : θ > 1=2: 1 An experiment is conducted and 9 heads and 3 tails are observed. This information is not sufficient to fully specify the model f(xjθ): A rashomonian analysis follows: ² Scenario 1: Number of flips, n = 12 is predetermined.
    [Show full text]
  • Model Selection by Normalized Maximum Likelihood
    Myung, J. I., Navarro, D. J. and Pitt, M. A. (2006). Model selection by normalized maximum likelihood. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 50, 167-179 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jmp.2005.06.008 Model selection by normalized maximum likelihood Jay I. Myunga;c, Danielle J. Navarrob and Mark A. Pitta aDepartment of Psychology Ohio State University bDepartment of Psychology University of Adelaide, Australia cCorresponding Author Abstract The Minimum Description Length (MDL) principle is an information theoretic approach to in- ductive inference that originated in algorithmic coding theory. In this approach, data are viewed as codes to be compressed by the model. From this perspective, models are compared on their ability to compress a data set by extracting useful information in the data apart from random noise. The goal of model selection is to identify the model, from a set of candidate models, that permits the shortest description length (code) of the data. Since Rissanen originally formalized the problem using the crude `two-part code' MDL method in the 1970s, many significant strides have been made, especially in the 1990s, with the culmination of the development of the refined `universal code' MDL method, dubbed Normalized Maximum Likelihood (NML). It represents an elegant solution to the model selection problem. The present paper provides a tutorial review on these latest developments with a special focus on NML. An application example of NML in cognitive modeling is also provided. Keywords: Minimum Description Length, Model Complexity, Inductive Inference, Cognitive Modeling. Preprint submitted to Journal of Mathematical Psychology 13 August 2019 To select among competing models of a psychological process, one must decide which criterion to use to evaluate the models, and then make the best inference as to which model is preferable.
    [Show full text]
  • P Values, Hypothesis Testing, and Model Selection: It’S De´Ja` Vu All Over Again1
    FORUM P values, hypothesis testing, and model selection: it’s de´ja` vu all over again1 It was six men of Indostan To learning much inclined, Who went to see the Elephant (Though all of them were blind), That each by observation Might satisfy his mind. ... And so these men of Indostan Disputed loud and long, Each in his own opinion Exceeding stiff and strong, Though each was partly in the right, And all were in the wrong! So, oft in theologic wars The disputants, I ween, Rail on in utter ignorance Of what each other mean, And prate about an Elephant Not one of them has seen! —From The Blind Men and the Elephant: A Hindoo Fable, by John Godfrey Saxe (1872) Even if you didn’t immediately skip over this page (or the entire Forum in this issue of Ecology), you may still be asking yourself, ‘‘Haven’t I seen this before? Do we really need another Forum on P values, hypothesis testing, and model selection?’’ So please bear with us; this elephant is still in the room. We thank Paul Murtaugh for the reminder and the invited commentators for their varying perspectives on the current shape of statistical testing and inference in ecology. Those of us who went through graduate school in the 1970s, 1980s, and 1990s remember attempting to coax another 0.001 out of SAS’s P ¼ 0.051 output (maybe if I just rounded to two decimal places ...), raising a toast to P ¼ 0.0499 (and the invention of floating point processors), or desperately searching the back pages of Sokal and Rohlf for a different test that would cross the finish line and satisfy our dissertation committee.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Likelihood 2 Maximum Likelihood Estimators 3 Properties of the Maximum Likelihood Estimators
    University of Colorado-Boulder Department of Applied Mathematics Prof. Vanja Dukic Review: Likelihood 1 Likelihood Consider a set of iid random variables X = fXig; i = 1; :::; N that come from some probability model M = ff(x; θ); θ 2 Θg where f(x; θ) is the probability density of each Xi and θ is an unknown but fixed parameter from some space Θ ⊆ <d. (Note: this would be a typical frequentist setting.) The likelihood function (Fisher, 1925, 1934) is defined as: N Y L(θ j X~ ) = f(Xi; θ); (1) i=1 or any other function of θ proportional to (1) (it does not need be normalized). More generally, the likelihood ~ N ~ function is any function proportional to the joint density of the sample, X = fXigi=1, denoted as f(X; θ). Note you don't need to assume independence, nor identically distributed variables in the sample. The likelihood function is sacred to most statisticians. Bayesians use it jointly with the prior distribution π(θ) to derive the posterior distribution π(θ j X) and draw all their inference based on that posterior. Frequentists may derive their estimates directly from the likelihood function using maximum likelihood estimation (MLE). We say that a parameter is identifiable if for any two θ 6= θ∗ we have L(θ j X~ ) 6= L(θ∗ j X~ ) 2 Maximum likelihood estimators One way of identifying (estimating) parameters is via the maximum likelihood estimators. Maximizing the likelihood function (or equivalently, the log likelihood function thanks to the monotonicity of the log transform), with respect to the parameter vector θ, yields the maximum likelihood estimator, denoted as θb.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 2 Estimating Probabilities
    CHAPTER 2 Estimating Probabilities Machine Learning Copyright c 2017. Tom M. Mitchell. All rights reserved. *DRAFT OF January 26, 2018* *PLEASE DO NOT DISTRIBUTE WITHOUT AUTHOR’S PERMISSION* This is a rough draft chapter intended for inclusion in the upcoming second edition of the textbook Machine Learning, T.M. Mitchell, McGraw Hill. You are welcome to use this for educational purposes, but do not duplicate or repost it on the internet. For online copies of this and other materials related to this book, visit the web site www.cs.cmu.edu/∼tom/mlbook.html. Please send suggestions for improvements, or suggested exercises, to [email protected]. Many machine learning methods depend on probabilistic approaches. The reason is simple: when we are interested in learning some target function f : X ! Y, we can more generally learn the probabilistic function P(YjX). By using a probabilistic approach, we can design algorithms that learn func- tions with uncertain outcomes (e.g., predicting tomorrow’s stock price) and that incorporate prior knowledge to guide learning (e.g., a bias that tomor- row’s stock price is likely to be similar to today’s price). This chapter de- scribes joint probability distributions over many variables, and shows how they can be used to calculate a target P(YjX). It also considers the problem of learning, or estimating, probability distributions from training data, pre- senting the two most common approaches: maximum likelihood estimation and maximum a posteriori estimation. 1 Joint Probability Distributions The key to building probabilistic models is to define a set of random variables, and to consider the joint probability distribution over them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Likelihood Function
    Introduction to Likelihood Statistics Edward L. Robinson* Department of Astronomy and McDonald Observatory University of Texas at Austin 1. The likelihood function. 2. Use of the likelihood function to model data. 3. Comparison to standard frequentist and Bayesean statistics. *Look for: “Data Analysis for Scientists and Engineers” Princeton University Press, Sept 2016. The Likelihood Function Let a probability distribution function for ⇠ have m + 1 • parameters aj f(⇠,a , a , , a )=f(⇠,~a), 0 1 ··· m The joint probability distribution for n samples of ⇠ is f(⇠ ,⇠ , ,⇠ , a , a , , a )=f(⇠~,~a). 1 2 ··· n 0 1 ··· m Now make measurements. For each variable ⇠ there is a measured • i value xi. To obtain the likelihood function L(~x,~a), replace each variable ⇠ with • i the numerical value of the corresponding data point xi: L(~x,~a) f(~x,~a)=f(x , x , , x ,~a). ⌘ 1 2 ··· n In the likelihood function the ~x are known and fixed, while the ~aare the variables. A Simple Example Suppose the probability • distribution for the data is 2 a⇠ f(⇠,a)=a ⇠e− . Measure a single data point. It • turns out to be x = 2. The likelihood function is • 2 2a L(x = 2, a)=2a e− . A Somewhat More Realistic Example Suppose we have n independent data points, each drawn from the same probability distribution 2 a⇠ f(⇠,a)=a ⇠e− . The joint probability distribution is f(⇠~,a)=f(⇠ , a)f(⇠ , a) f(⇠ , a) 1 2 ··· n n 2 a⇠i = a ⇠ie− . Yi=1 The data points are xi. The resulting likelihood function is n 2 axi L(~x, a)= a xie− .
    [Show full text]
  • Likelihood Principle
    Perhaps our standards are too high… • Maybe I am giving you too much food for thought on this one issue • The realization comes after reading a preprint by a >100-strong collaboration, MINOS • In a recent paper [MINOS 2011] they derive 99.7% upper limits for some parameters, using antineutrino interactions. How then to combine with previous upper limits derived with neutrino interactions ? 1 1 1 • They use the following formula: 2 2 2 up up,1 up,2 The horror, the horror. • You should all be able to realize that this cannot be correct! It looks like a poor man’s way to combine two significances for Gaussian distributions, but it does not even work in that simple case. Neyman vs MINOS • To show how wrong one can be with the formula used by MINOS, take the Gaussian measurement of a parameter. Take σ=1 for the Gaussian: this means, for instance, that if the unknown parameter is μ=3, there is then a 68% chance that your measurement x will be in the 2<x<4 interval. Since, however, what you know is your measurement and you want to draw conclusions on the unknown μ, you need to "invert the hypothesis". Let's say you measure x=2 and you want to know what is the maximum value possible for μ, at 95% confidence level. This requires producing a "Neyman construction". You will find that your limit is μ<3.64. • So what if you got twice the measurement x=2, in independent measurements ? Could you then combine the limits as MINOS does ? If you combine two x=2 measurements, each yielding μ1=μ2<3.64 at 95%CL, according to the 2 2 MINOS preprint you might do μcomb=1/sqrt(1/μ1,up + 1/μ2 ) < 2.57.
    [Show full text]
  • P-Values and the Likelihood Principle
    JSM 2016 - Section on Statistical Education p-Values and the Likelihood Principle Andrew Neath∗ Abstract The p-value is widely used for quantifying evidence in a statistical hypothesis testing problem. A major criticism, however, is that the p-value does not satisfy the likelihood principle. In this paper, we show that a p-value assessment of evidence can indeed be defined within the likelihood inference framework. The connection between p-values and likelihood based measures of evidence broaden the use of the p-value and deepen our understanding of statistical hypothesis testing. Key Words: hypothesis testing, statistical evidence, likelihood ratio, Wald statistic 1. Introduction The p-value is a popular tool for statistical inference. Unfortunately, the p-value and its role in hypothesis testing is often misused in drawing scientific conclusions. Concern over the use, and misuse, of what is perhaps the most widely taught statistical practice has led the American Statistical Association to craft a statement on behalf of its members (Wasserstein and Lazar, 2016). For statistical practitioners, a deeper insight into the workings of the p-value is essential for an understanding of statistical hypothesis testing. The purpose of this paper is to highlight the flexibility of the p-value as an assessment of statistical evidence. An alleged disadvantage of the p-value is its isolation from more rigorously defined likelihood based measures of evidence. However, this disconnect can be bridged. In this paper, we present a result establishing a p-value measure of evidence within the likelihood inferential framework. In Section 2, we discuss the general idea of statistical evidence.
    [Show full text]
  • Likelihood: Philosophical Foundations
    Likelihood and probability Properties of likelihood The likelihood principle Likelihood: Philosophical foundations Patrick Breheny August 24 Patrick Breheny University of Iowa Likelihood Theory (BIOS 7110) 1 / 34 Likelihood and probability Definition Properties of likelihood Bayesian and frequentist approaches The likelihood principle Combining likelihoods Introduction • This course is about developing a theoretical understanding of likelihood, the central concept in statistical modeling and inference • Likelihood offers a systematic way of measuring agreement between unknown parameters and observable data; in so doing, it provides a unifying principle that all statisticians can agree is reasonable (which is not to say that it doesn’t have any problems) • This provides two enormous benefits in statistics: ◦ A universal baseline of comparison for methods and estimators ◦ A coherent and versatile method of summarizing and combining evidence of all sources without relying on arbitrary, ad hoc decisions Patrick Breheny University of Iowa Likelihood Theory (BIOS 7110) 2 / 34 Likelihood and probability Definition Properties of likelihood Bayesian and frequentist approaches The likelihood principle Combining likelihoods Likelihood: Definition • Let X denote observable data, and suppose we have a probability model p that relates potential values of X to an unknown parameter θ • Definition: Given observed data X = x, the likelihood function for θ is defined as L(θ|x) = p(x|θ), although I will often just write L(θ) • Note that this is a function of θ,
    [Show full text]